Hegel's Dialectic Sovietica

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hegel's Dialectic Sovietica HEGEL'S DIALECTIC SOVIETICA PUBLICATIONS AND MONOGRAPHS OF THE INSTITUTE OF EAST-EUROPEAN STUDIES AT THE UNIVERSITY OF FRIBOURG/SWITZERLAND Edited by PROF. DR J. M. BOCHENSKI VOLUME 33 ANDRIES SARLEMIJN HEGEL'S DIALECTIC D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT-HOLLAND / BOSTON-U.S.A. HEGELSCHE DIALEKTIK First published in 1971 by Walter de Gruyter, Berlin/New York Translated from the German by Peter Kirschenmann Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 74-80522 ISBN-13: 978-94-010-1738-1 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-1736-7 001: 10.1007/978-94-010-1736-7 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company P.O. Box 17, Dordrecht, Holland Sold and distributed m the U.S.A., Canada, and Mexico by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Inc. 306 Dartmouth Street, Boston, Mass. 02116, U.S.A. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1975 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1975 No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or any other means, without written permission from the publisher TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE TO THE ENGLISH EDITION XI TRANSLATOR'S NOTE XIII INTRODUCTION 1 1 Subject Matter 1 2 Relevance 2 3 The Fate of Hegel Interpretations 3 3.1 Dialectical Materialists 3 3.2 Dialectical Idealism 4 3.3 Criticism by Formal Logicians 5 3.4 Old-Hegelians and Later Interpreters 5 4 Divisions 11 PART I / DIALECTIC CHAPTER 1 / DIALECTIC OF THE REAL 15 1.1 Unity and Main Theme of the Dialectic 15 1.2 Negative Dialectic 17 1.3 The Presupposition of Dialectical Method: Idealist Individuation 22 CHAPTER 2 I POSITIVE DIALECTIC 27 2.1 Hegel's Dialectic and Its Origin 27 2.11 'Dialectic', 'Dialectician' 27 2.111 Heraclitus and the Eleatics 27 2.112 Plato and the Sophists 29 2.113 From Aristotle to Kant 33 2.12 Criticism, Sophistry, Dialectic 34 2.13 The Circle of Being, the Most Abstract Form of the Dialectic 42 2.131 Technical Description 42 2.132 Presuppositions 43 2.133 Interpretation 45 VI TABLE OF CONTENTS 2.14 Idealist 'Exposition' of the Absolute 47 2.2 From Subjective to Objective Idealism 50 2.21 Subject-K-F-H 50 2.22 Argumentation with Kant 51 2.221 The 'Impulse from Outside' and Immanence 51 2.222 The Method for Knowing the Unconditioned 53 2.2221 Kant's Criticism of Metaphysics 53 2.2222 Dialectical lliusion 54 2.2223 The Significance of Critical Philosophy 56 2.23 Argumentation with Fichte 58 2.231 Identity in the Science of Know/edge 58 2.232 Identity and Separation in Hegel's Dialectic 59 2.2321 Identity and Separation in the Subject-Side-H 59 2.2322 Identity and Separation in the Object-Side-H 60 2.3 Intro-Reflection as the Essence of Self-Movement 61 2.31 The Expressions 'Self-Movement' and 'Intro-Reflection' 61 2.32 Determinations of Reflection 61 2.33 Intro-Reflection as the Nature of the Absolute Essence and as the Essence of Dialectical Method 65 CHAPTER 3 / THE SUBJECT MATTER OF DIALECTICAL PHILOSOPHY 68 3.1 Dialectic and the Starting-Point of Philosophy 68 3.2 The 'Soul' of Dialectical Movement 69 3.21 Possibility of a Dialectical Logic 69 First Interpretation: Hegelian Contradictions are Objective 70 Second Interpretation: Modification of the Requirement of Non-Contradiction 75 Third Interpretation: No Restriction of the Principle of Non-Contradiction 76 3.22 Hegel's Theory of Contradiction 81 3.221 KpNp as Determinately Being 81 3.222 Sublation 83 3.2221 Logical Sublation 84 3.2222 Spatial and Temporal Sublation 86 3.2223 The Non-Contradictory Whole 87 3.223 Knowledge of the Understanding that Is Free from Contra- diction 88 T ABLE OF CONTENTS VII 3.2231 Human and Absolute Understanding 88 3.2232 Dialectic and Knowledge of Facts 90 3.2233 Dialectic and Natural Science 91 3.2234 Dialectic and Formal Logic: Truth and Correctness 91 3.2235 Dialectic and Its Justification 95 3.2236 Ex falso sequitur quodlibet 95 3.3 The Goal of Dialectical Method 96 3.31 The System 96 3.32 The Development of the Absolute and the Development of the System 97 PART III DIALECTIC AND METAPHYSICS CHAPTER 1/ 'METAPHYSICS' - A PHILOSOPHICAL DISCIPLINE 103 1.1 'Metaphysics' 103 1.2 The Logic is a Metaphysics 105 1.21 The Metaphysical Content of the Logic 105 1.22 Why Does Hegel Call His Metaphysics 'Logic'? 106 1.221 Kant's Influence 106 1.222 'Logic' - 'Logos' 107 1.223 The Metaphysical is Logical 107 1.224 'Sublation' of Metaphysics of Being into Logic 107 1.225 The Demythologizing of Metaphysics 108 1.23 Does Dialectical Metaphysics Replace Formal Logic? 109 1.231 'Ordinary Logic' 109 1.232 'Formal Logic' 109 1.233 Hegel's Logic Is a Metaphysics of Being, and a Metaphysics of Knowledge Based Thereon 110 1.3 Hegel's Entire System Is a Metaphysics 110 CHAPTER 2 / METAPHYSICAL METHOD IN GENERAL 112 2.1 Positive Elements in the Method of Metaphysics of the Understanding 112 2.11 The 'View of the Understanding' 112 2.12 Epistemological Realism 113 2.13 The Idea In-and-for-itself 113 2.2 Criticism of the Method of Metaphysics of the Under- standing 113 VIII TABLE OF CONTENTS 2.21 'The Dead Product of Enlightenment' 114 2.22 Dependency on Imagination 115 2.23 Mathematical Metaphysics 115 2.24 Dogmatism 116 2.25 'Inferences of the Understanding' 118 2.26 Univocal Conception of Being 119 2.27 Multiplicity of Proofs 120 CHAPTER 3 I SPINOZA AND DOUBLE NEGA TION 121 3.1 Determinatio est negatio 121 3.2 Positio est negatio 121 3.3 Negation as Contradiction 123 3.4 Double Negation 123 3.5 Ambivalence of Spinoza's Position 124 3.6 Substance and Tnought 124 PART III / DIALECTICAL METAPHYSICS CHAPTER 1 I INFINITY 127 1.1 The Finite and the Infinite 127 1.2 The 'Bad' Infinite 128 1.21 Infinity as Perennial Ought 128 1.22 Dualistic Infinity 129 1.23 The Bad and Untrue 130 1.3 True Infinity 131 1.31 The Finite Is Subia ted 131 CHAPTER 2 / ABSOLUTE NECESSITY 133 2.1 Accidentality and Necessity 133 2.2 Absolute Actuality 13S 2.3 Substantiality and Causality 138 2.31 'The Substance' 138 2.32 Causal Relationship 139 2.33 The Sublation of Metaphysics 141 CHAPTER 3/ BEING IS THOUGHT 143 3.1 The Sum Total of All Realities 143 3.11 The Subjective Concept 143 TABLE OF CONTENTS IX 3.12 The Metaphysical Concept 144 3.121 The Identity in the Metaphysics of the Understanding 144 3.122 The Critical Non-Identity 145 3.123 Dialectical Identity and Non-Identity 146 3.13 'The Derivation of the Real' 147 3.2 The Idea of Life 148 3.21 External Purposiveness 148 3.22 Internal Purposiveness 149 3.23 The Speculative Death 150 3.3 Teleology 151 3.31 Absolute Spirit 151 3.32 Absolute and Finite Spirit: Freedom 152 3.33 All of Hegel's Dialectic Is Teleological 153 SUMMARY ISS EPILOGUE I HEGEL'S DIALECTIC AND CONTEMPORARY ISSUES 160 1 Analytic and Dialectic 160 2 The Sublation of Hegel's Dialectic 162 2.1 First Reversion 162 2.2 Second Reversion 164 2.3 Third Reversion 165 2.4 Fourth Reversion 166 CONCERNING NOTES AND ABBREVIA TIONS 168 NOTES 169 BIBLIOGRAPHY 183 INDEX OF NAMES 187 PREFACE TO THE ENGLISH EDITION This book was written in 1968, and defended as a doctoral dissertation before the Philosophical Faculty at the University of Fribourg (Switzerland) in 1969. It treats of the systematic views of Hegel which led him to give to the princi­ ple of non-contradiction, the principle of double negation, and the principle of excluded middle, meanings which are difficult to understand. The reader will look in vain for the philosophical position of the author. A few words about the intentions which motivated the author to study and clarify Hegel's thought are therefore not out of place. In the early sixties, when occupying myself with the history of Marxist philosophy, I discovered that the representatives of the logical-positivist tra­ dition were not alone in employing a principle of demarcation; that those of the dialectical Marxist tradition were also using such a principle ('self-move­ ment') as a foundation of a scientific philosophy and as a means to delimit unscientific ideas. I aimed at a clear conception of this principle in order to be able to judge whether, and to what extent, it accords with the foundations of the analytical method. In this endeavor I encountered two problems: (1) What is to be understood by 'analytical method' cannot be ascertained un­ equivocally. (2) The representatives of the dialectical or Marxist tradition, on the one hand, do not sufficiently clarify what is meant by 'principle of self­ movement' and by 'dialectical contradiction' in a Hegelian context and, on the other hand, presuppose the results of Hegel's Logic in the elucidation and logical justification of their position. I decided not to solve all of the problems pertinent to these issues, but to write instead an 'analytical' treatise on Hegel's Logic with the purpose of clarifying the issues. 'Analytical' is here taken to mean three things: (1) a discussion based on a precise interpretation of texts; (2) a particular consid­ eration of theses which deviate from the analytical position (an analysis of what is given that is based on the principles of formal logic); (3) a renuncia­ tion of 'modernizing' Hegel's dialectic (so as not to confront the reader with two philosophical systems - that of Hegel and that of the interpreter).
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Ecological Crisis and Two Forms of Modern Dialectics
    Utopía y Praxis Latinoamericana ISSN: 1315-5216 ISSN: 2477-9555 [email protected] Universidad del Zulia Venezuela Philosophy of Ecological Crisis and two Forms of Modern Dialectics VALIULLINA, Zaynab R.; LUKJANOV, Arkadiy V.; PUSKAREWA, Marina A. Philosophy of Ecological Crisis and two Forms of Modern Dialectics Utopía y Praxis Latinoamericana, vol. 23, no. 82, 2018 Universidad del Zulia, Venezuela Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=27957591037 DOI: https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.1513030 This work is licensed under Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 3.0 International. PDF generated from XML JATS4R by Redalyc Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Utopía y Praxis Latinoamericana, 2018, vol. 23, no. 82, July-September, ISSN: 1315-5216 2477-9555 Notas y debates de actualidad Philosophy of Ecological Crisis and two Forms of Modern Dialectics La filosofía de la crisis ecológica y dos formas de la dialéctica moderna Zaynab R. VALIULLINA DOI: https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.1513030 Bashkir State University, Rusia Redalyc: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa? [email protected] id=27957591037 http://orcid.org/0000-0002-7120-4516 Arkadiy V. LUKJANOV Bashkir State University, Rusia Marina A. PUSKAREWA Bashkir State University, Rusia Received: 21 August 2018 Accepted: 16 September 2018 Abstract: e rapid development of science and technology results in a change of human lifestyle. e main purpose of the work is to study the philosophy of ecological crisis and the forms of modern dialectics. e idea of "intersubjectivity" will function as our methodological basis. Continuation of Hegel’s ideas and essays of existentialists are related to dialectical processing of thought and technology.
    [Show full text]
  • Anarchy in the PA? Anti-Essentialism, Anti-Statism, and the Future of Public Administration
    CONFERENCE DRAFT This paper is not intended for general circulation and may not be cited without the permission of the author. Anarchy in the PA? Anti-Essentialism, Anti-Statism, and the Future of Public Administration Thomas J. Catlaw Assistant Professor School of Public Affairs Arizona State University 411 North Central Avenue Mail Code 3720, Suite 450 Phoenix, AZ 85004 Email: [email protected] Phone (602) 496-0459 Paper prepared for presentation at the “Public Administration and Anti-Essentialism” Conference, Florida Atlantic University, Fort Lauderdale, FL—March 2-3, 2007 Introduction Authority has been an ongoing focus of scholarly and intellectual investigation for nearly entirety of modern social science. In sociology, this concern can be tracked from Weber’s famous typologies and Durkheim’s exposition of anomie, a state induced by the decline of regulative authority relations, through the 1960’s “twilight of authority” (Nisbet, 1975) and the contemporary declaration of a “post-traditional” order (Giddens, 1994). Authority has also received enormous consideration in political science and political philosophy (Agamben, 2005; Arendt, 1958; Benne, 1943; DeGeorge, 1985; Engles, 1978; Flathman, 1980; Friedrich, 1972; Laski, 2000/1919; Lowi, 1970; McKercher, 1989), anthropology (W. B. Miller, 1955; Turner, 1969), organizational sociology (Blau, 1968; Dalton, Barnes, & Zaleznik, 1973/1968; Meyer, 1972), psychology (Kelman & Hamilton, 1989), and a wide range of provocative interdisciplinary legal, political, and psychological perspectives (Diggins & Kann, 1981; Friedrich, 1958; Horkheimer, 1972; Lincoln, 1994; Pennock & Chapman, 1987; Sennett, 1980). The literature on the topic is internally contradictory and voluminous—not withstanding the fact that consideration of authority readily expands into equally nebulous and complex concepts such as power, legitimacy, the state, and the nature of social order itself with no obvious analytic or historical limit.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary
    CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary Augustine Aurelius Augustinus Hipponensis (henceforth Augustine) was born in 354 A.D. in the municipium of Thagaste (modern day Souk Ahras, Algeria, close to the border with Tunisia). He died in 430, as the Arian1 Vandals besieged the city of Hippo where he was bishop, marking another stage in the demise of the Roman Empire. Rome had already been sacked in 410 by Alaric the Visigoth, but the slow decline of Roman grandeur took place over a period of about 320 years which culminated in 476 when Romulus Augustus, the last Emperor of the Western Roman Empire, was deposed by Odoacer, a Germanic chieftain. Augustine thus lived at a time which heralded the death knell of the ancient world and the beginnings of mediaeval western European Christendom.2 Augustine‘s great legacy to western civilization is that intellectually he united both worlds in drawing from the ancient thought of Greece and Rome and providing a Christian understanding of the intellectual achievements of the ancients. His new synthesis is a remarkable achievement even today and for those of us, who remain Christians in the West, our debates, agreements and disagreements are still pursued in Augustine‘s shadow.3 1 Arianism was a schismatic sect of Christianity that held the view that the Second Person of the Trinity, Christ, is created and thus does not exist eternally with the Father. 2 See J. M. Rist‘s magnificent Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2003. Rist notes that, ‗Despite his lack of resources he managed to sit in judgment on ancient philosophy and ancient culture.‘ p.
    [Show full text]
  • Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic
    Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic Immanuel Kant 1781 Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Each four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions will be reported between square brackets in normal-sized type. This version follows (B) the second edition of the Critique, though it also includes the (A) first-edition version of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason. Undecorated marginal numerals refer to page-numbers in B; ones with an ‘A’ in front refer to A, and are given only for passages that don’t also occur in B. The likes of ..356 in the margin mean that B356 (or whatever) started during the immediately preceding passage that has been omitted or only described between square brackets. These marginal numerals can help you to connect this version with other translations, with the original German, and with references in the secondary literature. Cross-references to other parts of this work include the word ‘page(s)’, and refer to numbers at the top-right corner of each page.—The Transcendental logic divides into the Transcendental analytic, which started on page 45, and the Transcendental dialectic, which starts here. First launched: January 2008 Critique. Dialectic Immanuel Kant Contents Introduction 155 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Account of the Rational Sources of Metaphysics in The
    CON-TEXTOS KANTIANOS. International Journal of Philosophy N.o 10, Diciembre 2019, pp. 235-239 ISSN: 2386-7655 Doi: 10.5281/zenodo.3583193 Kant’s Account of the Rational Sources of Metaphysics in the Transcendental Dialectic of the Critique of Pure Reason RUDOLF MEER• Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University, Russia Review of: Willaschek, M., Kant on the Sources of Metaphysics. The Dialectic of Pure Reason. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2018, pp. 308. ISBN-13: 978- 1108472630. The Transcendental Dialectic is an insufficiently studied section of the Critique of Pure Reason. This is surprising given that Division Two of the Transcendental Logic forms the largest part of Kant’s first critique. If the doctrine is systematically considered, then Kant’s critique of the metaphysica specialis—that is, rational psychology, rational cosmology, and rational theology—is at the core of the investigations (Willaschek 2018, p. 11). And in fact, the emphasis seems to be on the destruction of the unconditioned objects, God, world, and soul. In this sense, the Transcendental Dialectic would be a long Appendix to the Transcendental Analytic and the Transcendental Aesthetic, in which Kant dissociates himself once again from the metaphysical tradition and his philosophical opponents, in order to legitimize indirectly the previous analysis. Kant gives unambiguous hints for understanding the architectonic of the Critique of Pure Reason in this sense, by classifying the Transcendental Analytic as Logic of Truth and the Transcendental Dialectic as Logic of Illusion. Hence, Kant’s early critics had determined that Kant neither has a positive dialectic theory nor a concept of system, and this is a point of view which is frequently repeated in subsequent writings.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant in the Dialectics of Enlightenment* Brian O’Connor (University College Dublin)
    Kant in the Dialectics of Enlightenment* Brian O’Connor (University College Dublin) In Dialektik der Aufklärung discussions of Kant’s ideas feature more than those of any other philosopher. Those discussions, however, rarely attempt to understand the argumentative structure of Kant’s philosophy. Kant’s ideas are invoked largely as an aide to gaining greater insight into the broader phenomenon of the evolution of modern reason. The text’s treatment of Kant’s work is, as a consequence, fragmentary and partial. Neither scholarly accuracy nor systematic reconstruction plays a role in Horkheimer and Adorno’s methodology. Sometimes Kant is presented as an important though typical enough enlightenment thinker, as blind as any other to the destructive power of totalizing reason. Yet Kant’s concepts of “synthesis” and “schematism” are also highlighted as amongst the most radical efforts to ground the Enlightenment interest in the mastery of nature. The text returns frequently to these concepts. Only occasionally are there acknowledgements that Kant’s conception of the limits of knowledge might actually separate him from a single-tracked scientistic rationalism. Perhaps the most critical assessment of Kant found in Dialektik der Aufklärung comes in the shape of associations made between Kant’s moral rigorism and the amoralism promoted in Sade’s Juliette. In order to gain an overview of the various uses to which Kant is put in Dialektik der Aufklärung this chapter will focus on the two most substantial topics. First is the relationship between transcendental idealism and enlightenment rationality. This topic will bring us to Horkheimer and Adorno’s interpretation of synthesis, schematism and the transcendental unity of apperception.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Misology and the Natural Dialectic
    volume 19, no. 47 1. Philosophy and Common Moral Cognition october 2019 Towards the conclusion of the First Section of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant describes a process whereby a subject can undergo a certain kind of moral corruption. This process, which he calls a “natural dialectic”, can cause one to undermine one’s own or- dinary grasp of the demands of morality (4: 405).1 The threat of the natural dialectic is of particular interest since it not only gives a precise Kant on Misology and causal account of the phenomenon of moral corruption but also con- stitutes Kant’s case for the relevance of philosophy to everyday practi- cal life. The question as to whether and how philosophy can have any practical significance within our ordinary moral lives is one that Kant the Natural Dialectic himself had just raised at the conclusion of the section. According to his own account of “common moral cognition”, the cognitive capacity of ordinary human beings “is very well informed in all cases that occur, to distinguish what is good, what is evil, what conforms with duty or is contrary to it” (4: 404). This commitment stemmed from Kant’s reading of Rousseau in the 1760s.2 Rousseau had convinced him that the unreflective responses of ordinary uneducated human subjects are more reliable than those of philosophical experts. Kant’s previous prioritization of the improve- ment of the intellect and the thought that “this alone could constitute the honor of mankind” later struck him as constituting both a philo- John J.
    [Show full text]
  • J. S. Mill and the Diversity of Utilitarianism
    The central thesis of this paper is that Mill's conception of utilitarianism was much broader than current philosophical usage allows.1 This seemingly modest point has two signifi- cant implications. First, it sheds light on Mill's primary aim in Utilitarianism, which was not to elaborate his own moral theory but to defend a general approach to ethics. He un- derstood this approach capaciously enough to include the diverse views of Bentham, Godwin, and Paley, among oth- ers. Second, the inclusiveness of Mill's conception of utili- J. S. Mill tarianism belies the common tendency to read his work with certain developments of modern consequentialism too much in mind. I will argue that the widespread failure to appreci- and the Diversity ate these points has resulted in a conventional view that dis- torts both Mill's moral theory and the status of Utilitarianism. of Utilitarianism This "little work," as Mill called it, has been accorded a place in his oeuvre that is vastly disproportionate to his own much more modest assessment.2 The conventional reading of Mill as a maximizing act- consequentialist takes the official statement of the Greatest Happiness Principle, in Utilitarianism 2.2, to specify his own Daniel Jacobson moral theory. Although many commentators have noted the substantial evidence that Mill was no ordinary conse- quentialist, no other interpretation has won general accep- tance. In particular, the rule-utilitarian readings advanced by J. O. Urmson and David Lyons have been eclipsed by more 1I would like to thank Roger Crisp, an editor of Philosophers' Imprint, an anonymous referee, and colloquium audiences at Bowling Green State University and the University of Wisconsin, Madison, for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Orthodoxy and Existentialism: the Religious Root of Dostoevsky's Moral Dialectic David Eschrich Director: Julie Degra
    ABSTRACT Orthodoxy and Existentialism: The Religious Root of Dostoevsky’s Moral Dialectic David Eschrich Director: Julie DeGraffenried In my thesis, I show the ways in which Russian Eastern Orthodoxy relates to and impacts Fyodor Dostoevsky’s Existentialism. I begin by identifying and explaining the Orthodox theme of transformative suffering, as it appears in the ecclesial tradition of Kievan Rus, after which I demonstrate the presence of this theme and tradition in Dostoevsky’s upbringing in Nicholaevan Russia. I close by relating this transformative suffering to the moral dialectic Dostoevsky establishes in his novels, specifically Notes From Underground and Crime and Punishment. In doing so, I show the similarities and conversation between Russian Eastern Orthodoxy and Dostoevsky’s existentialism. APPROVED BY DIRECTOR OF HONORS THESIS: ____________________________________________________ Dr. Julie deGraffenried, History APPROVED BY THE HONORS PROGRAM _________________________________________________________ ORTHODOXY AND EXISTENTIALISM: THE RELIGIOUS ROOTS OF DOSTOEVSKY’S MORAL DIALECTIC A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of Baylor University In the Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Honors Program By David Eschrich Waco, Texas May, 2015 TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter One . 1 Chapter Two . 7 Chapter Three . 25 Chapter Four . 40 Conclusion . 63 Bibliography . 65 ii CHAPTER ONE Introduction One of the greatest writers in Russia and the world is nineteenth century figure human existence.”2 Like the existentialists of the twentieth century, Dostoevsky likewise pursues an understanding of the individual apart from outside laws and social norms. One of the primary questions he pursues in his writings is, “What is a human being?” and his response relies on a definition of the individual, concentrating on human freedom and subjective passions.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Dialectic ?
    Sommer-Edition 2004 WHAT IS DIALECTIC ? There is nothing so absurd or incredible that it has not von Karl R. Popper [ * ] been asserted by one philosopher or another. Descartes 1. DIALECTIC EXPLAINED THE above motto can be generalized. It applies not only to philosophers and philosophy, but throughout the realm of human thought and enterprise, to science, technology, engineering and politics. Indeed, the tendency to try anything once, suggested by the motto, can be discerned in a still wider realm – in the stupendous variety of forms and appearances which are produced by life an our planet. Thus if we want to explain why human thought tends to try out every conceivable solution for any problem with which it is faced, then we can appeal to a highly general sort of regularity. The method by which a solution is approached is usually the same; it is the method of trial and error. This, fundamentally, is also the method used by living organisms in the process of adaptation. It is clear that the success of this method depends very largely an the number and variety of the trials : the more we try, the more likely it is that one of our attempts will be successful. We may describe the method employed in the development of human thought, and especially of philosophy, as a particular variant of the trial and error method. Men seem inclined to react to a problem either by putting forward some theory and clinging to it as long as they can (if it is erroneous they may even perish with it rather than give it up[1], or by fighting against such a theory, once they have seen its weaknesses.
    [Show full text]
  • Adorno, Hegel, and Dialectic Abstract This Article Explores Critical Theory's
    Adorno, Hegel, and Dialectic Abstract This article explores critical theory’s relations to German idealism by clarifying how Adorno’s thought relates to Hegel’s. Adorno’s apparently mixed responses to Hegel centre on the dialectic and actually form a coherent whole. In his Logic, Hegel outlines the dialectical process by which categories – fundamental forms of thought and reality – necessarily follow one another in three stages: abstraction, dialectic proper, and the speculative (famously simplified as ‘thesis, antithesis, synthesis’). Adorno’s allegiance to Hegel’s dialectic emerges when he traces the dialectical process whereby enlightenment reverts to myth and human domination over nature reverts into our domination by nature. However, Adorno criticises Hegel’s dialectic as the ultimate form of ‘identity thinking’, subsuming unique, material objects under universal concepts by using dialectical reason to expand those concepts to cover objects utterly. These two responses cohere because Adorno shares Hegel’s view that dialectical contradictions require reconciliation, but differs from Hegel on the nature of reconciliation. For Hegel, reconciliation unites differences into a whole; for Adorno, reconciled differences co-exist as differences. Finally, against Habermas who holds that Adorno cannot consistently criticize the enlightenment practice of critique, I show that Adorno can do so consistently because of how he reshapes Hegelian dialectic. Keywords: Adorno, critical theory, dialectic, enlightenment, Habermas, Hegel, nature 1 Adorno, Hegel, and Dialectic In this article I aim to shed light on the relations between German idealism and critical theory by providing a fresh interpretation of how Theodor Adorno’s thought relates to that of G. W. F. Hegel.1 The title of Adorno’s best-known work, the Dialectic of Enlightenment, already bespeaks a substantial debt to Hegel, the philosopher of dialectic.
    [Show full text]