<<

Equations and logic on words

Sam van Gool

Utrecht University

TACL, Nice 17 June 2019 Overview

Logic on words

Duality

Equations between words

Equations between languages

1 / 26 Overview

Logic on words

Duality

Equations between words

Equations between languages

1 / 26 I Solution 1: a (deterministic) automaton A: 0 1 1 0 q0 q1 q2 1 0

Answer yes iff A accepts w. ∗ I Solution 2: a ϕ: {0, 1} → S3 defined by 0 7→ (1 2), 1 7→ (0 1). Answer yes iff the permutation ϕ(w) sends 0 to 1.

.

Regular languages: example

I A programming problem: given a in binary, w ∈ {0, 1}∗, determine if w is congruent 1 modulo 3.

2 / 26 ∗ I Solution 2: a homomorphism ϕ: {0, 1} → S3 defined by 0 7→ (1 2), 1 7→ (0 1). Answer yes iff the permutation ϕ(w) sends 0 to 1.

.

Regular languages: example

I A programming problem: given a natural number in binary, w ∈ {0, 1}∗, determine if w is congruent 1 modulo 3.

I Solution 1: a (deterministic) automaton A: 0 1 1 0 q0 q1 q2 1 0

Answer yes iff A accepts w.

2 / 26 Regular languages: example

I A programming problem: given a natural number in binary, w ∈ {0, 1}∗, determine if w is congruent 1 modulo 3.

I Solution 1: a (deterministic) automaton A: 0 1 1 0 q0 q1 q2 1 0

Answer yes iff A accepts w. ∗ I Solution 2: a homomorphism ϕ: {0, 1} → S3 defined by 0 7→ (1 2), 1 7→ (0 1). Answer yes iff the permutation ϕ(w) sends 0 to 1.

.

2 / 26 Regular languages: example

I A programming problem: given a natural number in binary, w ∈ {0, 1}∗, determine if w is congruent 1 modulo 3.

I Solution 1: a (deterministic) automaton A: 0 1 1 0 q0 q1 q2 1 0

Answer yes iff A accepts w.

I Solution 3: an MSO sentence ϕ:

∃Q0∃Q1∃Q2(Q0(first) ∧ Q1(last)∧

∀x[0(x) ∧ Q0(x) → Q0(Sx)] ∧ [1(x) ∧ Q0(x) → Q1(Sx)] ∧ ... ).

Answer yes iff w satisfies the formula ϕ.

2 / 26 Regular languages

Regular languages are L ⊆ Σ∗ which are ...

I recognizable by a finite automaton;

I invariant under a finite index congruence;

I definable by a monadic second order sentence.

Myhill-Nerode 1958; Büchi 1960

3 / 26 I Semantics. A word w = a1 ... an gives a structure W .

I The underlying of W is {1,..., n}. W I The natural linear order < interprets the binary predicate <. W I For every letter a ∈ Σ, a := {i ∈ {1,..., n}: ai = a}.

Logic on words

I Syntax. Monadic Second Order (MSO) logic over <, Σ.

I Basic propositional connectives: ∧, ¬.

I Quantification over first-order variables x, y, . . . and monadic second-order variables P, Q, ... .

I Relational signature: x < y, a(x) for a ∈ Σ.

4 / 26 Logic on words

I Syntax. Monadic Second Order (MSO) logic over <, Σ.

I Basic propositional connectives: ∧, ¬.

I Quantification over first-order variables x, y, . . . and monadic second-order variables P, Q, ... .

I Relational signature: x < y, a(x) for a ∈ Σ.

I Semantics. A word w = a1 ... an gives a structure W .

I The underlying set of W is {1,..., n}. W I The natural linear order < interprets the binary predicate <. W I For every letter a ∈ Σ, a := {i ∈ {1,..., n}: ai = a}.

4 / 26 Logic on words

I Syntax. Monadic Second Order (MSO) logic over <, Σ.

I Semantics. A word w = a1 ... an gives a structure W .

∗ I For a sentence ϕ, Lϕ := {w ∈ Σ | w |= ϕ}.

I A language L is regular iff L = Lϕ for some ϕ in MSO.

I Shortcuts such as S(x), first, last, ⊆, ... are MSO-definable.

5 / 26 I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

6 / 26 |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa

6 / 26 but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ,

6 / 26 ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

6 / 26 I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

6 / 26 |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb

6 / 26 but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ,

6 / 26 ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

6 / 26 I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

6 / 26 ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.”

6 / 26 Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order.

6 / 26 Logic on words: examples ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I aaaa |= ϕ, but aaaaa 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has even length.

ψ : ∃P ∃xP (x) ∧ P ⊆ a ∧ ∀y (∀x[P(x) → x < y]) → b(y) .

I aacbaccaabbb |= ϕ, but aacbaccaabbc 6|= ϕ.

I W |= ϕ iff W has a non-empty subset of a-positions after which there are only b-positions.

ψ0 : ∃x a(x) ∧ ∀y[x < y → (¬a(y) ∧ b(y))] .

I “There is a last a-position, with only b-positions after that.” ψ and ψ0 are equivalent, and ψ0 is first order. Question. Does such an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ? 6 / 26 I A congruence on M is an θ which respects multiplication.

I The quotient M/θ is again a monoid;

I A congruence θ has finite index if M/θ is finite. ∗ I A language L ⊆ Σ is regular iff there exists a finite index

congruence θL under which L is invariant: 0 0 w ∈ L and wθLw implies w ∈ L.

Monoids and finite index congruences

I A monoid is a set M equipped with an associative and a unit. ∗ I The set Σ of finite words is a .

I multiplication is ;

I unit is the empty word ;

7 / 26 and finite index congruences

I A monoid is a set M equipped with an associative binary operation and a unit. ∗ I The set Σ of finite words is a free monoid.

I multiplication is concatenation;

I unit is the empty word ;

I A congruence on M is an equivalence relation θ which respects multiplication.

I The quotient M/θ is again a monoid;

I A congruence θ has finite index if M/θ is finite. ∗ I A language L ⊆ Σ is regular iff there exists a finite index

congruence θL under which L is invariant: 0 0 w ∈ L and wθLw implies w ∈ L.

7 / 26 Regular languages

Regular languages are subsets L ⊆ Σ∗ which are ...

I recognizable by a finite automaton;

I invariant under a finite index monoid congruence;

I definable by a monadic second order sentence.

Myhill-Nerode 1958; Büchi 1960

7 / 26 Overview

Logic on words

Duality

Equations between words

Equations between languages

7 / 26 Equations between languages Equations between words

Duality

Key insight. The connection between MSO logic on words and monoids is an instance of Stone-Jónsson-Tarski duality.

Algebra Space Lindenbaum of a logic Canonical model Residuated Boolean algebra of (Pro)finite monoid regular languages

Gehrke, Grigorieff, Pin 2008

8 / 26 Duality

Key insight. The connection between MSO logic on words and monoids is an instance of Stone-Jónsson-Tarski duality.

Algebra Space Lindenbaum algebra of a logic Canonical model Residuated Boolean algebra of (Pro)finite monoid regular languages Equations between languages Equations between words

Gehrke, Grigorieff, Pin 2008

8 / 26 I A subset of a profinite monoid is clopen iff it is recognizable, i.e., invariant under a finite index topological congruence.

Profinite monoids and their clopens

I A profinite monoid is a monoid equipped with a Boolean topology in which multiplication is continuous.

I Also: a limit of finite monoids with the discrete topology.

9 / 26 Profinite monoids and their clopens

I A profinite monoid is a monoid equipped with a Boolean topology in which multiplication is continuous.

I Also: a limit of finite monoids with the discrete topology.

I A subset of a profinite monoid is clopen iff it is recognizable, i.e., invariant under a finite index topological congruence.

9 / 26 Under this duality...

I the free profinite monoid is dual to the residuated Boolean algebra of all regular languages;

I quotients of the free profinite monoid correspond to subalgebras of regular languages that are ideals for division.

Duality and profinite monoids

I There are natural division operators on the Boolean algebra of clopen sets of a profinite monoid:

K\L = {m | mK ⊆ L}, L/K = {m | Km ⊆ L}.

I These are ‘box’ operators dual to the monoid multiplication, more precisely, to two distinct ternary relations derived from it.

10 / 26 Duality and profinite monoids

I There are natural division operators on the Boolean algebra of clopen sets of a profinite monoid:

K\L = {m | mK ⊆ L}, L/K = {m | Km ⊆ L}.

I These are ‘box’ operators dual to the monoid multiplication, more precisely, to two distinct ternary relations derived from it.

Under this duality...

I the free profinite monoid is dual to the residuated Boolean algebra of all regular languages;

I quotients of the free profinite monoid correspond to subalgebras of regular languages that are ideals for division.

10 / 26 Duality

Key insight. The connection between MSO logic on words and monoids is an instance of Stone-Jónsson-Tarski duality.

Algebra Space Lindenbaum algebra of a logic Canonical model Residuated Boolean algebra of (Pro)finite monoid regular languages Equations between languages Equations between words

Gehrke, Grigorieff, Pin 2008

10 / 26 Overview

Logic on words

Duality

Equations between words

Equations between languages

10 / 26 A congruence θ on Σ∗ is called aperiodic if Σ∗/θ does not have non-trivial subgroups.

Schützenberger 1965; McNaughton, Papert 1971

Logic and monoids

A language L ⊆ Σ∗ is MSO-definable

if, and only if,

L is invariant under a finite index monoid congruence.

11 / 26 A congruence θ on Σ∗ is called aperiodic if Σ∗/θ does not have non-trivial subgroups.

Schützenberger 1965; McNaughton, Papert 1971

Logic and monoids

A language L ⊆ Σ∗ is FO-definable

if, and only if,

L is invariant under a finite index aperiodic monoid congruence.

11 / 26 Logic and monoids

A language L ⊆ Σ∗ is FO-definable

if, and only if,

L is invariant under a finite index aperiodic monoid congruence.

A congruence θ on Σ∗ is called aperiodic if Σ∗/θ does not have non-trivial subgroups.

Schützenberger 1965; McNaughton, Papert 1971

11 / 26 The quotient of the free profinite monoid obtained by enforcing xω = xωx is the free pro-aperiodic monoid. This is the dual space of the residuated algebra of FO-definable languages (instance of Eilenberg-Reiterman).

ω

In a finite monoid, any element x has a unique idempotent, xω, in its orbit {x, x2, x3,... }.

Fact. A finite monoid is aperiodic iff it validates the equation

xω = xωx.

12 / 26 The quotient of the free profinite monoid obtained by enforcing xω = xωx is the free pro-aperiodic monoid. This is the dual space of the residuated algebra of FO-definable languages (instance of Eilenberg-Reiterman).

ω

In a profinite monoid, any element x has a unique idempotent, xω, in its orbit- {x, x2, x3,... }.

Fact. A profinite monoid is aperiodic iff it validates the equation

xω = xωx.

12 / 26 ω

In a profinite monoid, any element x has a unique idempotent, xω, in its orbit-closure {x, x2, x3,... }.

Fact. A profinite monoid is aperiodic iff it validates the equation

xω = xωx.

The quotient of the free profinite monoid obtained by enforcing xω = xωx is the free pro-aperiodic monoid. This is the dual space of the residuated algebra of FO-definable languages (instance of Eilenberg-Reiterman).

12 / 26 No, because:

I any quotient under which Lϕ is invariant must contain a

subgroup Z2;

I for any generator a of the free profinite monoid, we have ω ω ω ω a ∈ Lcϕ and a a 6∈ Lcϕ, so Lϕ ‘falsifies’ the equation x = x x.

Logic on words: example revisited

ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I Lϕ = {w : w has even length}.

Question. Does an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

13 / 26 Logic on words: example revisited

ϕ: ∃P P(first) ∧ ¬P(last) ∧ ∀x(P(x) ↔ ¬P(S(x)) .

I Lϕ = {w : w has even length}.

Question. Does an equivalent first order formula exist for ϕ?

No, because:

I any quotient under which Lϕ is invariant must contain a

subgroup Z2;

I for any generator a of the free profinite monoid, we have ω ω ω ω a ∈ Lcϕ and a a 6∈ Lcϕ, so Lϕ ‘falsifies’ the equation x = x x.

13 / 26 The free profinite aperiodic monoid

Theorem.

The free profinite aperiodic monoid = The topological monoid of ultrafilters of FO-definable languages =

The topological monoid of ≡FO -classes of pseudo-finite words.

G. & Steinberg STACS 2017

14 / 26 and every occurring first-order property has a last occurrence.

I For example:

I any finite word is pseudo-finite; op I the word aN + aN = aaaa ...... aaaa is pseudo-finite. op I the word aN + bN = aaaa ...... bbbb is not!

I The first-order sentence

∃xa(x) → (∃x0a(x0) ∧ ∀y > x0¬a(y))

op is true in every finite word, but not in aN + bN .

Pseudo-finite words

I By a pseudo-finite word we mean a first-order structure W (W , <, (a )a∈Σ) that is a model of the theory of finite words.

I A pseudo-finite word is a discrete linear order with endpoints which is partitioned by the sets aW

15 / 26 and every occurring first-order property has a last occurrence.

op I the word aN + bN = aaaa ...... bbbb is not!

I The first-order sentence

∃xa(x) → (∃x0a(x0) ∧ ∀y > x0¬a(y))

op is true in every finite word, but not in aN + bN .

Pseudo-finite words

I By a pseudo-finite word we mean a first-order structure W (W , <, (a )a∈Σ) that is a model of the theory of finite words.

I A pseudo-finite word is a discrete linear order with endpoints which is partitioned by the sets aW

I For example:

I any finite word is pseudo-finite; op I the word aN + aN = aaaa ...... aaaa is pseudo-finite.

15 / 26 and every occurring first-order property has a last occurrence.

is not!

I The first-order sentence

∃xa(x) → (∃x0a(x0) ∧ ∀y > x0¬a(y))

op is true in every finite word, but not in aN + bN .

Pseudo-finite words

I By a pseudo-finite word we mean a first-order structure W (W , <, (a )a∈Σ) that is a model of the theory of finite words.

I A pseudo-finite word is a discrete linear order with endpoints which is partitioned by the sets aW

I For example:

I any finite word is pseudo-finite; op I the word aN + aN = aaaa ...... aaaa is pseudo-finite. op I the word aN + bN = aaaa ...... bbbb

15 / 26 and every occurring first-order property has a last occurrence.

I The first-order sentence

∃xa(x) → (∃x0a(x0) ∧ ∀y > x0¬a(y))

op is true in every finite word, but not in aN + bN .

Pseudo-finite words

I By a pseudo-finite word we mean a first-order structure W (W , <, (a )a∈Σ) that is a model of the theory of finite words.

I A pseudo-finite word is a discrete linear order with endpoints which is partitioned by the sets aW

I For example:

I any finite word is pseudo-finite; op I the word aN + aN = aaaa ...... aaaa is pseudo-finite. op I the word aN + bN = aaaa ...... bbbb is not!

15 / 26 and every occurring first-order property has a last occurrence.

Pseudo-finite words

I By a pseudo-finite word we mean a first-order structure W (W , <, (a )a∈Σ) that is a model of the theory of finite words.

I A pseudo-finite word is a discrete linear order with endpoints which is partitioned by the sets aW

I For example:

I any finite word is pseudo-finite; op I the word aN + aN = aaaa ...... aaaa is pseudo-finite. op I the word aN + bN = aaaa ...... bbbb is not!

I The first-order sentence

∃xa(x) → (∃x0a(x0) ∧ ∀y > x0¬a(y))

op is true in every finite word, but not in aN + bN .

15 / 26 Pseudo-finite words

I By a pseudo-finite word we mean a first-order structure W (W , <, (a )a∈Σ) that is a model of the theory of finite words.

I A pseudo-finite word is a discrete linear order with endpoints which is partitioned by the sets aW and every occurring first-order property has a last occurrence.

I For example:

I any finite word is pseudo-finite; op I the word aN + aN = aaaa ...... aaaa is pseudo-finite. op I the word aN + bN = aaaa ...... bbbb is not!

I The first-order sentence

∃xa(x) → (∃x0a(x0) ∧ ∀y > x0¬a(y))

op is true in every finite word, but not in aN + bN .

15 / 26 Ultrafilters and pseudo-finite words

I An ultrafilter U of FO-definable languages uniquely determines

an ≡FO - [W ] of pseudo-finite words.

I This is a between the ultrafilter space and the space of types.

I There is a natural topological monoid multiplication on types:

if W ≡ W 0 then VW ≡ VW 0 and WV ≡ W 0V .

16 / 26 The free profinite aperiodic monoid

Theorem.

The free profinite aperiodic monoid = The topological monoid of ultrafilters of FO-definable languages =

The topological monoid of ≡FO -classes of pseudo-finite words.

G. & Steinberg STACS 2017

16 / 26 An application: the aperiodic ω-word problem

Decision problem. Given two terms in · and ()ω, are they equal in every finite aperiodic monoid?

17 / 26 An application: the aperiodic ω-word problem

Decision problem. Given two terms in · and ()ω, are they equal in the free profinite aperiodic monoid?

17 / 26 I Crucially, substitutions of ω-saturated words into ω-saturated words are again ω-saturated.

I Thus, any ω-term can be realized as an ω-saturated word.

I Using the uniqueness of countable ω-saturated models, equality of ω-terms reduces to of these words, which we know is decidable.

Hüschenbett & Kufleitner STACS 2013; G. & Steinberg STACS 2017

Realizing ω-words as ω-saturated models

I A countable model is ω-saturated if it realizes all the complete types over a finite parameter set. I The following pseudo-finite words are ω-saturated:

I finite words; op I the constant word on N + Q × Z + N .

18 / 26 Realizing ω-words as ω-saturated models

I A countable model is ω-saturated if it realizes all the complete types over a finite parameter set. I The following pseudo-finite words are ω-saturated:

I finite words; op I the constant word on N + Q × Z + N . I Crucially, substitutions of ω-saturated words into ω-saturated words are again ω-saturated.

I Thus, any ω-term can be realized as an ω-saturated word.

I Using the uniqueness of countable ω-saturated models, equality of ω-terms reduces to isomorphism of these words, which we know is decidable.

Hüschenbett & Kufleitner STACS 2013; G. & Steinberg STACS 2017 18 / 26 Overview

Logic on words

Duality

Equations between words

Equations between languages

18 / 26 for every non-constant polynomial p, F |= ∃xp(x) = 0.

I A field F is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some field extension of F already holds in F .

I This is first order definable: F is existentially closed iff

∗ I A T -structure A is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some T -structure extending A already holds in A.

I This property is often first order definable:

I Linear orders without endpoints: density;

I Boolean : atomless;

I Heyting algebras: mimick fields, use uniform interpolation.

∗ If the class of T -structures does not have amalgamation, a more complicated definition is needed.

Solving equations

2 I Solve for x ∈ R: x + 1 = 0.

19 / 26 for every non-constant polynomial p, F |= ∃xp(x) = 0.

I A field F is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some field extension of F already holds in F .

I This is first order definable: F is existentially closed iff

∗ I A T -structure A is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some T -structure extending A already holds in A.

I This property is often first order definable:

I Linear orders without endpoints: density;

I Boolean algebras: atomless;

I Heyting algebras: mimick fields, use uniform interpolation.

∗ If the class of T -structures does not have amalgamation, a more complicated definition is needed.

Solving equations

2 I Solve for x ∈ C: x + 1 = 0.

19 / 26 for every non-constant polynomial p, F |= ∃xp(x) = 0.

I This is first order definable: F is existentially closed iff

∗ I A T -structure A is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some T -structure extending A already holds in A.

I This property is often first order definable:

I Linear orders without endpoints: density;

I Boolean algebras: atomless;

I Heyting algebras: mimick fields, use uniform interpolation.

∗ If the class of T -structures does not have amalgamation, a more complicated definition is needed.

Solving equations

2 I Solve for x ∈ C: x + 1 = 0.

I A field F is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some field extension of F already holds in F .

19 / 26 ∗ I A T -structure A is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some T -structure extending A already holds in A.

I This property is often first order definable:

I Linear orders without endpoints: density;

I Boolean algebras: atomless;

I Heyting algebras: mimick fields, use uniform interpolation.

∗ If the class of T -structures does not have amalgamation, a more complicated definition is needed.

Solving equations

2 I Solve for x ∈ C: x + 1 = 0.

I A field F is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some field extension of F already holds in F .

I This is first order definable: F is existentially closed iff for every non-constant polynomial p, F |= ∃xp(x) = 0.

19 / 26 I This property is often first order definable:

I Linear orders without endpoints: density;

I Boolean algebras: atomless;

I Heyting algebras: mimick fields, use uniform interpolation.

Solving equations

2 I Solve for x ∈ C: x + 1 = 0.

I A field F is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some field extension of F already holds in F .

I This is first order definable: F is existentially closed iff for every non-constant polynomial p, F |= ∃xp(x) = 0.

∗ I A T -structure A is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some T -structure extending A already holds in A.

∗ If the class of T -structures does not have amalgamation, a more complicated definition is needed. 19 / 26 Solving equations

2 I Solve for x ∈ C: x + 1 = 0.

I A field F is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some field extension of F already holds in F .

I This is first order definable: F is existentially closed iff for every non-constant polynomial p, F |= ∃xp(x) = 0.

∗ I A T -structure A is existentially closed if any existential sentence that becomes true in some T -structure extending A already holds in A.

I This property is often first order definable:

I Linear orders without endpoints: density;

I Boolean algebras: atomless;

I Heyting algebras: mimick fields, use uniform interpolation.

∗ If the class of T -structures does not have amalgamation, a more complicated definition is needed. 19 / 26 T and T ∗ are co-theories

T ∗ is model complete

Model companion

A first order theory T ∗ which captures the existentially closed models for a universal theory T is called a model companion of T .

Theorem. The theory T ∗, if it exists, is the unique theory such that:

1. T and T ∗ believe the same universal sentences;

2. T ∗ believes any sentence to be equivalent to an existential sentence.

Robinson, 1963

20 / 26 Model companion

A first order theory T ∗ which captures the existentially closed models for a universal theory T is called a model companion of T .

Theorem. The theory T ∗, if it exists, is the unique theory such that:

1. T and T ∗ believe the same universal sentences;

T and T ∗ are co-theories

2. T ∗ believes any sentence to be equivalent to an existential sentence.

T ∗ is model complete

Robinson, 1963

20 / 26 Model companions and languages

Theorem.

The first order theory T ∗ of an algebra for word languages, P(ω),

is the model companion of

a theory T of algebras for a linear temporal logic.

Ghilardi & G. JSL 2017

21 / 26 I Axioms for temporal logic → a first order theory T .

Theorem. The theory T ∗ of P(ω) is the model companion of T .

i.e., T ∗ is model complete and T ∗ is a co-theory of T .

Proof idea: set-up

Skip

I Enrich the Boolean algebra P(ω) with temporal operators:

I Xa := {t ∈ ω | t + 1 ∈ a}, 0 0 I Fa := {t ∈ ω | ∃t ≥ t : t ∈ a},

I I := {0}.

22 / 26 Theorem. The theory T ∗ of P(ω) is the model companion of T .

i.e., T ∗ is model complete and T ∗ is a co-theory of T .

Proof idea: set-up

Skip

I Enrich the Boolean algebra P(ω) with temporal operators:

I Xa := {t ∈ ω | t + 1 ∈ a}, 0 0 I Fa := {t ∈ ω | ∃t ≥ t : t ∈ a},

I I := {0}.

I Axioms for temporal logic → a first order theory T .

22 / 26 Proof idea: set-up

Skip

I Enrich the Boolean algebra P(ω) with temporal operators:

I Xa := {t ∈ ω | t + 1 ∈ a}, 0 0 I Fa := {t ∈ ω | ∃t ≥ t : t ∈ a},

I I := {0}.

I Axioms for temporal logic → a first order theory T .

Theorem. The theory T ∗ of P(ω) is the model companion of T .

i.e., T ∗ is model complete and T ∗ is a co-theory of T .

22 / 26 I If t(p) 6= > in some T -structure A, consider its dual space X .

I By carefully using filtration-type techniques, we may read off from X a valuation p →P (ω) which invalidates t(p) = >.

Proof idea: co-theories

I Need to show: any equation of the form t(p) = > that is valid in P(ω) is valid in all T -structures.

I The theory T axiomatizes linear temporal logic on X, F, I:

I Boolean algebra axioms, X is a homomorphism, Fa is the least fix point of the function x 7→ a ∨ Xx.

I I is an atom and I ≤ Fa whenever a 6= ⊥.

23 / 26 Proof idea: co-theories

I Need to show: any equation of the form t(p) = > that is valid in P(ω) is valid in all T -structures.

I The theory T axiomatizes linear temporal logic on X, F, I:

I Boolean algebra axioms, X is a homomorphism, Fa is the least fix point of the function x 7→ a ∨ Xx.

I I is an atom and I ≤ Fa whenever a 6= ⊥.

I If t(p) 6= > in some T -structure A, consider its dual space X .

I By carefully using filtration-type techniques, we may read off from X a valuation p →P (ω) which invalidates t(p) = >.

23 / 26 Proof idea: co-theories

I Need to show: any equation of the form t(p) = > that is valid in P(ω) is valid in all T -structures.

I The theory T axiomatizes linear temporal logic on X, F, I:

I Boolean algebra axioms, X is a homomorphism, Fa is the least fix point of the function x 7→ a ∨ Xx.

I I is an atom and I ≤ Fa whenever a 6= ⊥.

I If t(p) 6= > in some T -structure A, consider its dual space X .

I By carefully using filtration-type techniques, we may read off from X a valuation p →P (ω) which invalidates t(p) = >.

23 / 26 I This MSO formula Φ defines a LΦ.

I Build an automaton A for Φ.

I Describe the automaton A with an existential first order formula ϕ0 in the temporal algebra P(ω).

I Conclusion. P(ω) believes that any first order formula ϕ is equivalent to an existential formula ϕ0.

Proof idea: model completeness

I Any first order formula ϕ(p) in the temporal algebra P(ω) translates to an MSO formula Φ(P) in logic on words.

24 / 26 I Build an automaton A for Φ.

I Describe the automaton A with an existential first order formula ϕ0 in the temporal algebra P(ω).

I Conclusion. P(ω) believes that any first order formula ϕ is equivalent to an existential formula ϕ0.

Proof idea: model completeness

I Any first order formula ϕ(p) in the temporal algebra P(ω) translates to an MSO formula Φ(P) in logic on words.

I This MSO formula Φ defines a regular language LΦ.

24 / 26 I Describe the automaton A with an existential first order formula ϕ0 in the temporal algebra P(ω).

I Conclusion. P(ω) believes that any first order formula ϕ is equivalent to an existential formula ϕ0.

Proof idea: model completeness

I Any first order formula ϕ(p) in the temporal algebra P(ω) translates to an MSO formula Φ(P) in logic on words.

I This MSO formula Φ defines a regular language LΦ.

I Build an automaton A for Φ.

24 / 26 I Conclusion. P(ω) believes that any first order formula ϕ is equivalent to an existential formula ϕ0.

Proof idea: model completeness

I Any first order formula ϕ(p) in the temporal algebra P(ω) translates to an MSO formula Φ(P) in logic on words.

I This MSO formula Φ defines a regular language LΦ.

I Build an automaton A for Φ.

I Describe the automaton A with an existential first order formula ϕ0 in the temporal algebra P(ω).

24 / 26 Proof idea: model completeness

I Any first order formula ϕ(p) in the temporal algebra P(ω) translates to an MSO formula Φ(P) in logic on words.

I This MSO formula Φ defines a regular language LΦ.

I Build an automaton A for Φ.

I Describe the automaton A with an existential first order formula ϕ0 in the temporal algebra P(ω).

I Conclusion. P(ω) believes that any first order formula ϕ is equivalent to an existential formula ϕ0.

24 / 26 Model companions and languages

Theorem.

The first order theory T ∗ of an algebra for word languages, P(ω),

is the model companion of

a theory T of algebras for a linear temporal logic.

Ghilardi & G. JSL 2017

25 / 26 Model companions and languages

Theorem.

The first order theory T ∗ of an algebra for tree languages, P(2∗),

is the model companion of

a theory T of algebras for a fair computation tree logic.

Ghilardi & G. LICS 2016

25 / 26 The future

I From FO to MSO

I Model companions for more logics

I Using ordered spaces

26 / 26