Nonlocality As an Axiom for Quantum Theory*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nonlocality As an Axiom for Quantum Theory* View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CERN Document Server NONLOCALITY AS AN AXIOM FOR QUANTUM THEORY* Daniel Rohrlich and Sandu Pop escu School of Physics and Astronomy, Tel-Aviv University Ramat-Aviv, Tel-Aviv 69978 Israel ABSTRACT Quantum mechanics and relativistic causality together imply nonlo cality: nonlo- cal correlations (that violate the CHSH inequality) and nonlo cal equations of motion (the Aharonov-Bohm e ect). Can weinvert the logical order? We consider a conjecture that nonlo cality and relativistic causality together imply quantum mechanics. We show that correlations preserving relativistic causality can violate the CHSH inequality more strongly than quantum correlations. Also, we describ e nonlo cal equations of motion, preserving rel- ativistic causality, that do not arise in quantum mechanics. In these nonlo cal equations of motion, an exp erimenter \jams" nonlo cal correlations b etween quantum systems. 1. INTRODUCTION Two asp ects of quantum nonlo cality are nonlo cal correlations and nonlo cal equations of motion. Nonlo cal correlations arise in settings such as the one discussed by Einstein, 1 2 Po dolsky and Rosen . As Bell showed (and Asp ect has reviewed in his lecture here) no 3 theory of lo cal variables can repro duce these correlations. The Aharonov-Bohm e ect is also nonlo cal in that an electromagnetic eld in uences an electron in a region where the eld vanishes. The eld induces a relative phase b etween two sets of paths available to an electron, displacing the interference pattern b etween the two sets of paths. Thus, the 4 Aharonov-Bohm e ect implies nonlo cal equations of motion. Both asp ects of quantum non- lo cality arise within nonrelativistic quantum theory.However, the very de nition of a lo cal variable is relativistic: a lo cal variable can b e in uenced only byevents in its backward light cone, and can in uence events only in its forward light cone. In this sense, quantum mechanics and relativity together imply nonlo cality. They co exist b ecause quantum correla- tions preserve relativistic causality (i.e. they do not allow us to transmit signals faster than *Talk presented at 60 Years of E.P.R. (Workshop on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, in honor of Nathan Rosen), Technion, Israel, March 1995 1 light). But quantum mechanics do es not allow us to consider isolated systems as separate, 1 as Einstein, Po dolsky and Rosen assumed. This violation of not the letter but the spirit of sp ecial relativity has left manyphysicists (including Bell) deeply unsettled. Today, quantum nonlo cality seems as fundamental|and as unsettling|as ever. If nonlo cality is fundamen- tal, why not make nonlo cality an axiom of quantum theory rather than a consequence? Can we then invert the logical order, showing that nonlo cality and relativistic causality together imply quantum theory? 2. NONLOCALITY I: NONLOCAL CORRELATIONS Quantum mechanics and relativistic causality together give rise to nonlo cal corre- lations, which manyphysicists regard as a negative asp ect of quantum theory. Here, we regard quantum nonlo cality as a p ositive asp ect of quantum theory. What new p ossibilities do es quantum nonlo cality o er us? In particular, if we make nonlo cality an axiom, what 57 b ecomes of the logical structure of quantum theory? The sp ecial theory of relativity can b e deduced in its entirety from two axioms: the equivalence of inertial reference frames, and 7 the constancy of the sp eed of light. Aharonov has prop osed such a logical structure for quantum theory. Let us take, as axioms of quantum theory, relativistic causality and nonlo- cality. As an initial, immediate result, we deduce that quantum theory is not deterministic, 7 otherwise these two axioms would b e incompatible. Two \negative" asp ects of quantum mechanics|indeterminacy and limits on measurements|then app ear as a consequence of a fundamental \p ositive" asp ect: the p ossibility of nonlo cal action. Moreover, by taking nonlo cality as an axiom, we free ourselves of the need to explain it. Wehave not yet de ned the axiom of nonlo cality. Relativistic causalityiswell de ned, but quantum nonlo cality arises b oth in nonlo cal correlations and in the Aharonov-Bohm e ect. In this section we consider nonlo cal correlations. We ask which theories yield nonlo cal correlations while preserving causality. Our result is indep endent of quantum mechanics or 8 any particular mo del. We nd that quantum mechanics is only one of a class of theories consistent with our two axioms, and, in a certain sense, not even the most nonlo cal theory. 9 The Clauser, Horne, Shimony, and Holt (CHSH) form of Bell's inequality, holds in any classical theory (that is, any theory of lo cal hidden variables). It states that a certain 2 combination of correlations lies b etween -2 and 2: 0 0 0 0 2 E (A; B )+E(A; B )+E(A ;B) E(A ;B ) 2 : (1) p 2 and 4, are imp ortant b ounds on the CHSH sum of Besides 2, two other numb ers, 2 correlations. If the four correlations in Eq. (1) were indep endent, the absolute value of the sum could b e as muchas4. For quantum correlations, however, the CHSH sum of p 10 2. Where do es this b ound come from? correlations is b ounded in absolute value by2 Rather than asking why quantum correlations violate the CHSH inequality,we might ask why they do not violate it more. Let us say that of the two axioms prop osed ab ove, the axiom of nonlo cality implies that quantum correlations violate the CHSH inequality at least sometimes. Wemay then guess that the other axiom, relativistic causality, might imply that quantum correlations do not violate it maximally. Could it b e that relativistic causality restricts the violation p 2 instead of 4? If so, then the two axioms determine the quantum violation of the to 2 CHSH inequality. To answer this question, we ask what restrictions relativistic causality imp oses on joint probabilities. Relativistic causality forbids sending messages faster than light. Thus, if one observer measures the observable A, the probabilities for the outcomes A = 1 and A = 1must b e indep endent of whether the other observer cho oses to measure 0 8;11 B or B .However, it can b e shown that this constraint do es not limit the CHSH sum of p 2. For example, imagine a \sup erquantum" correlation function quantum correlations to 2 E for spin measurements along given axes. Assume E dep ends only on the relative angle between axes. For any pair of axes, the outcomes j ""i and j ##i are equally likely, and similarly for j "#i and j #"i. These four probabilities sum to 1, so the probabilities for j "#i and j ##i sum to 1=2. In any direction, the probabilityof j"i or j#i is 1=2 irresp ectiveof a measurement on the other particle. Measurements on one particle yield no information ab out measurements on the other, so relativistic causality holds. The correlation function then satis es E ( )=E(). Now let E ( )have the form (i) E ( ) = 1 for 0 =4; (ii) E ( ) decreases monotonically and smo othly from 1 to -1 as increases from =4 to 3=4; 3 (iii) E ( )=1 for 3=4 . 0 0 ^ ^ Consider four measurements along axes de ned by unit vectorsa ^ , b,^a, and b sepa- rated by successive angles of =4 and lying in a plane. If wenow apply the CHSH inequality Eq. (1) to these directions, we nd that the sum of correlations 0 0 0 0 ^ ^ ^ ^ E (^a; b)+E(^a ; b)+E(^a; b ) E (^a ; b )=3E(=4) E (3=4) = 4 (2) violates the CHSH inequality with the maximal value 4. Thus, a correlation function could satisfy relativistic causality and still violate the CHSH inequality with the maximal value 4. 3. NONLOCALITY I I: NONLOCAL EQUATIONS OF MOTION In one version of the Aharonov-Bohm e ect, an isolated magnetic ux, inserted b e- tween two slits, shifts the interference pattern of electrons passing through the slits. It thereby a ects the electron's momentum, since the electron arrives at a di erent p oint than it would without the electromagnetic eld. Thus, the Aharonov-Bohm e ect implies non- 4 7 lo cal equations of motion. Aharonov has shown that a physical quantity, the modular 12 momentum of the ux, is uncertain exactly as required to keep us from seeing a violation of causality. In general, mo dular momentum is measurable and ob eys a nonlo cal equation of motion. But when the ux is lo cated b etween the slits, its mo dular momentum is completely uncertain. Is quantum mechanics the only relativistically causal theory with nonlo cal equations of motion? As in the last section, wemay approach this question by lo oking for a theory 13 not equivalent to quantum mechanics that ob eys relativisitic causality and nonlo cality. Wehave considered a mo del in which action by an exp erimenter a ects (\jams") nonlo cal correlations b etween systems measured at spacelike separations from the action. For exam- 5 ple, Shimony considers the e ect of a laser b eam crossing the path of one of the photons in a singlet pair, after the photon has already passed. We nd that while nonlo cal \jamming" is not p ossible in quantum mechanics, it could b e consistent with relativisitic causality.If jamming is realized in nature, then p erhaps, as suggested by Grunhaus, it is p ossible to jam nonlo cal quantum correlations.
Recommended publications
  • Arxiv:2002.00255V3 [Quant-Ph] 13 Feb 2021 Lem (BVP)
    A Path Integral approach to Quantum Fluid Dynamics Sagnik Ghosh Indian Institute of Science Education and Research, Pune-411008, India Swapan K Ghosh UM-DAE Centre for Excellence in Basic Sciences, University of Mumbai, Kalina, Santacruz, Mumbai-400098, India ∗ (Dated: February 16, 2021) In this work we develop an alternative approach for solution of Quantum Trajectories using the Path Integral method. The state-of-the-art technique in the field is to solve a set of non-linear, coupled partial differential equations (PDEs) simultaneously. We opt for a fundamentally different route. We first derive a general closed form expression for the Path Integral propagator valid for any general potential as a functional of the corresponding classical path. The method is exact and is applicable in many dimensions as well as multi-particle cases. This, then, is used to compute the Quantum Potential (QP), which, in turn, can generate the Quantum Trajectories. For cases, where closed form solution is not possible, the problem is formally boiled down to solving the classical path as a boundary value problem. The work formally bridges the Path Integral approach with Quantum Fluid Dynamics. As a model application to illustrate the method, we work out a toy model viz. the double-well potential, where the boundary value problem for the classical path has been computed perturbatively, but the Quantum part is left exact. Using this we delve into seeking insight in one of the long standing debates with regard to Quantum Tunneling. Keywords: Path Integral, Quantum Fluid Dynamics, Analytical Solution, Quantum Potential, Quantum Tunneling, Quantum Trajectories Submitted to: J.
    [Show full text]
  • Simulation of the Bell Inequality Violation Based on Quantum Steering Concept Mohsen Ruzbehani
    www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN Simulation of the Bell inequality violation based on quantum steering concept Mohsen Ruzbehani Violation of Bell’s inequality in experiments shows that predictions of local realistic models disagree with those of quantum mechanics. However, despite the quantum mechanics formalism, there are debates on how does it happen in nature. In this paper by use of a model of polarizers that obeys the Malus’ law and quantum steering concept, i.e. superluminal infuence of the states of entangled pairs to each other, simulation of phenomena is presented. The given model, as it is intended to be, is extremely simple without using mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics. However, the result completely agrees with prediction of quantum mechanics. Although it may seem trivial, this model can be applied to simulate the behavior of other not easy to analytically evaluate efects, such as defciency of detectors and polarizers, diferent value of photons in each run and so on. For example, it is demonstrated, when detector efciency is 83% the S factor of CHSH inequality will be 2, which completely agrees with famous detector efciency limit calculated analytically. Also, it is shown in one-channel polarizers the polarization of absorbed photons, should change to the perpendicular of polarizer angle, at very end, to have perfect violation of the Bell inequality (2 √2 ) otherwise maximum violation will be limited to (1.5 √2). More than a half-century afer celebrated Bell inequality 1, nonlocality is almost totally accepted concept which has been proved by numerous experiments. Although there is no doubt about validity of the mathematical model proposed by Bell to examine the principle of the locality, it is comprehended that Bell’s inequality in its original form is not testable.
    [Show full text]
  • Violation of Bell Inequalities: Mapping the Conceptual Implications
    International Journal of Quantum Foundations 7 (2021) 47-78 Original Paper Violation of Bell Inequalities: Mapping the Conceptual Implications Brian Drummond Edinburgh, Scotland. E-mail: [email protected] Received: 10 April 2021 / Accepted: 14 June 2021 / Published: 30 June 2021 Abstract: This short article concentrates on the conceptual aspects of the violation of Bell inequalities, and acts as a map to the 265 cited references. The article outlines (a) relevant characteristics of quantum mechanics, such as statistical balance and entanglement, (b) the thinking that led to the derivation of the original Bell inequality, and (c) the range of claimed implications, including realism, locality and others which attract less attention. The main conclusion is that violation of Bell inequalities appears to have some implications for the nature of physical reality, but that none of these are definite. The violations constrain possible prequantum (underlying) theories, but do not rule out the possibility that such theories might reconcile at least one understanding of locality and realism to quantum mechanical predictions. Violation might reflect, at least partly, failure to acknowledge the contextuality of quantum mechanics, or that data from different probability spaces have been inappropriately combined. Many claims that there are definite implications reflect one or more of (i) imprecise non-mathematical language, (ii) assumptions inappropriate in quantum mechanics, (iii) inadequate treatment of measurement statistics and (iv) underlying philosophical assumptions. Keywords: Bell inequalities; statistical balance; entanglement; realism; locality; prequantum theories; contextuality; probability space; conceptual; philosophical International Journal of Quantum Foundations 7 (2021) 48 1. Introduction and Overview (Area Mapped and Mapping Methods) Concepts are an important part of physics [1, § 2][2][3, § 1.2][4, § 1][5, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Nonlocality Explained
    Quantum Nonlocality Explained Ulrich Mohrhoff Sri Aurobindo International Centre of Education Pondicherry 605002 India [email protected] Abstract Quantum theory's violation of remote outcome independence is as- sessed in the context of a novel interpretation of the theory, in which the unavoidable distinction between the classical and quantum domains is understood as a distinction between the manifested world and its manifestation. 1 Preliminaries There are at least nine formulations of quantum mechanics [1], among them Heisenberg's matrix formulation, Schr¨odinger'swave-function formu- lation, Feynman's path-integral formulation, Wigner's phase-space formula- tion, and the density-matrix formulation. The idiosyncracies of these forma- tions have much in common with the inertial reference frames of relativistic physics: anything that is not invariant under Lorentz transformations is a feature of whichever language we use to describe the physical world rather than an objective feature of the physical world. By the same token, any- thing that depends on the particular formulation of quantum mechanics is a feature of whichever mathematical tool we use to calculate the values of observables or the probabilities of measurement outcomes rather than an objective feature of the physical world. That said, when it comes to addressing specific questions, some formu- lations are obviously more suitable than others. As Styer et al. [1] wrote, The ever-popular wavefunction formulation is standard for prob- lem solving, but leaves the conceptual misimpression that [the] wavefunction is a physical entity rather than a mathematical tool. The path integral formulation is physically appealing and 1 generalizes readily beyond the domain of nonrelativistic quan- tum mechanics, but is laborious in most standard applications.
    [Show full text]
  • Cosmic Bell Test Using Random Measurement Settings from High-Redshift Quasars
    PHYSICAL REVIEW LETTERS 121, 080403 (2018) Editors' Suggestion Cosmic Bell Test Using Random Measurement Settings from High-Redshift Quasars Dominik Rauch,1,2,* Johannes Handsteiner,1,2 Armin Hochrainer,1,2 Jason Gallicchio,3 Andrew S. Friedman,4 Calvin Leung,1,2,3,5 Bo Liu,6 Lukas Bulla,1,2 Sebastian Ecker,1,2 Fabian Steinlechner,1,2 Rupert Ursin,1,2 Beili Hu,3 David Leon,4 Chris Benn,7 Adriano Ghedina,8 Massimo Cecconi,8 Alan H. Guth,5 † ‡ David I. Kaiser,5, Thomas Scheidl,1,2 and Anton Zeilinger1,2, 1Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information (IQOQI), Austrian Academy of Sciences, Boltzmanngasse 3, 1090 Vienna, Austria 2Vienna Center for Quantum Science & Technology (VCQ), Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, Boltzmanngasse 5, 1090 Vienna, Austria 3Department of Physics, Harvey Mudd College, Claremont, California 91711, USA 4Center for Astrophysics and Space Sciences, University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, California 92093, USA 5Department of Physics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139, USA 6School of Computer, NUDT, 410073 Changsha, China 7Isaac Newton Group, Apartado 321, 38700 Santa Cruz de La Palma, Spain 8Fundación Galileo Galilei—INAF, 38712 Breña Baja, Spain (Received 5 April 2018; revised manuscript received 14 June 2018; published 20 August 2018) In this Letter, we present a cosmic Bell experiment with polarization-entangled photons, in which measurement settings were determined based on real-time measurements of the wavelength of photons from high-redshift quasars, whose light was emitted billions of years ago; the experiment simultaneously ensures locality. Assuming fair sampling for all detected photons and that the wavelength of the quasar photons had not been selectively altered or previewed between emission and detection, we observe statistically significant violation of Bell’s inequality by 9.3 standard deviations, corresponding to an estimated p value of ≲7.4 × 10−21.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Nonlocality As an Axiom
    Foundations of Physics, Vol. 24, No. 3, 1994 Quantum Nonlocality as an Axiom Sandu Popescu t and Daniel Rohrlich 2 Received July 2, 1993: revised July 19, 1993 In the conventional approach to quantum mechanics, &determinism is an axiom and nonlocality is a theorem. We consider inverting the logical order, mak#1g nonlocality an axiom and indeterminism a theorem. Nonlocal "superquantum" correlations, preserving relativistic causality, can violate the CHSH inequality more strongly than any quantum correlations. What is the quantum principle? J. Wheeler named it the "Merlin principle" after the legendary magician who, when pursued, could change his form again and again. The more we pursue the quantum principle, the more it changes: from discreteness, to indeterminism, to sums over paths, to many worlds, and so on. By comparison, the relativity principle is easy to grasp. Relativity theory and quantum theory underlie all of physics, but we do not always know how to reconcile them. Here, we take nonlocality as the quantum principle, and we ask what nonlocality and relativistic causality together imply. It is a pleasure to dedicate this paper to Professor Fritz Rohrlich, who has contributed much to the juncture of quantum theory and relativity theory, including its most spectacular success, quantum electrodynamics, and who has written both on quantum paradoxes tll and the logical structure of physical theory, t2~ Bell t31 proved that some predictions of quantum mechanics cannot be reproduced by any theory of local physical variables. Although Bell worked within nonrelativistic quantum theory, the definition of local variable is relativistic: a local variable can be influenced only by events in its back- ward light cone, not by events outside, and can influence events in its i Universit6 Libre de Bruxelles, Campus Plaine, C.P.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Nonlocality Does Not Exist
    Quantum nonlocality does not exist Frank J. Tipler1 Department of Mathematics, Tulane University, New Orleans, LA 70118 Edited* by John P. Perdew, Temple University, Philadelphia, PA, and approved June 2, 2014 (received for review December 30, 2013) Quantum nonlocality is shown to be an artifact of the Copenhagen instantaneously the spin of particle 2 would be fixed in the op- interpretation, in which each observed quantity has exactly one posite direction to that of particle 1—if we assume that [2] col- value at any instant. In reality, all physical systems obey quantum lapses at the instant we measure the spin of particle 1. The mechanics, which obeys no such rule. Locality is restored if observed purported mystery of quantum nonlocality lies in trying to un- and observer are both assumed to obey quantum mechanics, as in derstand how particle 2 changes—instantaneously—in re- the many-worlds interpretation (MWI). Using the MWI, I show that sponse to what has happened in the location of particle 1. the quantum side of Bell’s inequality, generally believed nonlocal, There is no mystery. There is no quantum nonlocality. Particle is really due to a series of three measurements (not two as in the 2 does not know what has happened to particle 1 when its spin is standard, oversimplified analysis), all three of which have only measured. State transitions are entirely local in quantum me- local effects. Thus, experiments confirming “nonlocality” are actu- chanics. All these statements are true because quantum me- ally confirming the MWI. The mistaken interpretation of nonlocal- chanics tells us that the wave function does not collapse when ity experiments depends crucially on a question-begging version the state of a system is measured.
    [Show full text]
  • Astronomical Random Numbers for Quantum Foundations Experiments
    Astronomical random numbers for quantum foundations experiments The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Leung, Calvin et al. "Astronomical random numbers for quantum foundations experiments." Physical Review A 97, 4 (April 2018): 042120 As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.97.042120 Publisher American Physical Society Version Final published version Citable link http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/115234 Terms of Use Creative Commons Attribution Detailed Terms http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0 PHYSICAL REVIEW A 97, 042120 (2018) Featured in Physics Astronomical random numbers for quantum foundations experiments Calvin Leung,1,* Amy Brown,1,† Hien Nguyen,2,‡ Andrew S. Friedman,3,§ David I. Kaiser,4,¶ and Jason Gallicchio1,** 1Harvey Mudd College, Claremont, California 91711, USA 2NASA Jet Propulsion Laboratory, Pasadena, California 91109, USA 3University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, California 92093, USA 4Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139, USA (Received 7 June 2017; published 24 April 2018) Photons from distant astronomical sources can be used as a classical source of randomness to improve fundamental tests of quantum nonlocality, wave-particle duality, and local realism through Bell’s inequality and delayed-choice quantum eraser tests inspired by Wheeler’s cosmic-scale Mach-Zehnder interferometer gedanken experiment. Such sources of random numbers may also be useful for information-theoretic applications such as key distribution for quantum cryptography. Building on the design of an astronomical random number generator developed for the recent cosmic Bell experiment [Handsteiner et al. Phys. Rev. Lett. 118, 060401 (2017)], in this paper we report on the design and characterization of a device that, with 20-nanosecond latency, outputs a bit based on whether the wavelength of an incoming photon is greater than or less than ≈700 nm.
    [Show full text]
  • There Are No Particles, There Are Only Fields
    Downloaded 07 Mar 2013 to 130.184.202.223. Redistribution subject to AAPT license or copyright; see http://ajp.aapt.org/authors/copyright_permission There are no particles, there are only fields Art Hobsona) Department of Physics, University of Arkansas, Fayetteville, Arkansas 72701 (Received 18 April 2012; accepted 15 January 2013) Quantum foundations are still unsettled, with mixed effects on science and society. By now it should be possible to obtain consensus on at least one issue: Are the fundamental constituents fields or particles? As this paper shows, experiment and theory imply that unbounded fields, not bounded particles, are fundamental. This is especially clear for relativistic systems, implying that it’s also true of nonrelativistic systems. Particles are epiphenomena arising from fields. Thus, the Schr€odinger field is a space-filling physical field whose value at any spatial point is the probability amplitude for an interaction to occur at that point. The field for an electron is the electron; each electron extends over both slits in the two-slit experiment and spreads over the entire pattern; and quantum physics is about interactions of microscopic systems with the macroscopic world rather than just about measurements. It’s important to clarify this issue because textbooks still teach a particles- and measurement-oriented interpretation that contributes to bewilderment among students and pseudoscience among the public. This article reviews classical and quantum fields, the two-slit experiment, rigorous theorems showing particles are inconsistent with relativistic quantum theory, and several phenomena showing particles are incompatible with quantum field theories. VC 2013 American Association of Physics Teachers.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Test of Quantum Nonlocality in Three-Photon
    letters to nature electrons could be employed to probe atoms and molecules ................................................................. remotely while minimizing the perturbing in¯uences of a nearby Experimental test of quantum local probeÐthese unwanted interactions might be chemical in nature or result from electric or magnetic ®elds emanating from an nonlocality in three-photon STM tip or other probe device. Our results also suggest altered geometries such as ellipsoids con®ning bulk electrons, or specially Greenberger±Horne±Zeilinger shaped electron mirrors (such as parabolic re¯ectors) electronically coupling two or more points. One might additionally envision entanglement performing other types of `spectroscopy-at-a-distance' beyond electronic structure measurements, for example, detecting Jian-Wei Pan*, Dik Bouwmeester², Matthew Daniell*, vibrational16 or magnetic excitations. Harald Weinfurter³ & Anton Zeilinger* We conclude with some remaining questions. Our calculations show that ellipses have a class of eigenmodes that possess strongly * Institut fuÈr Experimentalphysik, UniversitaÈt Wien, Boltzmanngasse 5, peaked probability amplitude near the classical foci (Fig. 3e and f are 1090 Wien, Austria good examples). Our experiments reveal that the strongest mirages ² Clarendon Laboratory, University of Oxford, Parks Road, Oxford OX1 3PU, UK ³ Sektion Physik, Ludwig-Maximilians-UniversitaÈtofMuÈnchen, occur when one of these eigenmodes is at EF and therefore at the energy of the Kondo resonance. When perturbed by a focal atom, Schellingstrasse 4/III, D-80799 MuÈnchen, Germany this eigenmode still has substantial density surrounding both foci; it .............................................................................................................................................. is therefore plausible that this quantum state `samples' the Kondo Bell's theorem1 states that certain statistical correlations predicted resonance on the real atom and transmits that signal to the other by quantum physics for measurements on two-particle systems focus.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List on Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics David Wallace, June 2018
    Reading list on philosophy of quantum mechanics David Wallace, June 2018 1. Introduction .............................................................................................................................................. 2 2. Introductory and general readings in philosophy of quantum theory ..................................................... 4 3. Physics and math resources ...................................................................................................................... 5 4. The quantum measurement problem....................................................................................................... 7 4. Non-locality in quantum theory ................................................................................................................ 8 5. State-eliminativist hidden variable theories (aka Psi-epistemic theories) ............................................. 10 6. The Copenhagen interpretation and its descendants ............................................................................ 12 7. Decoherence ........................................................................................................................................... 15 8. The Everett interpretation (aka the Many-Worlds Theory) .................................................................... 17 9. The de Broglie-Bohm theory ................................................................................................................... 22 10. Dynamical-collapse theories ................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Making Sense of Bell's Theorem and Quantum Nonlocality
    Making Sense of Bell's Theorem and Quantum Nonlocality∗ Stephen Boughny Princeton University, Princeton NJ 08544 Haverford College, Haverford PA 19041 LATEX-ed April 3, 2017 Abstract Bell's theorem has fascinated physicists and philosophers since his 1964 paper, which was written in response to the 1935 paper of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen. Bell's theorem and its many extensions have led to the claim that quantum mechan- ics and by inference nature herself are nonlocal in the sense that a measurement on a system by an observer at one location has an immediate effect on a distant entangled system (one with which the original system has previously interacted). Einstein was repulsed by such \spooky action at a distance" and was led to ques- tion whether quantum mechanics could provide a complete description of physical reality. In this paper I argue that quantum mechanics does not require spooky action at a distance of any kind and yet it is entirely reasonable to question the arXiv:1703.11003v1 [quant-ph] 31 Mar 2017 assumption that quantum mechanics can provide a complete description of physical reality. The magic of entangled quantum states has little to do with entanglement and everything to do with superposition, a property of all quantum systems and a foundational tenet of quantum mechanics. Keywords: Quantum nonlocality · Bell's theorem · Foundations of quantum me- chanics · Measurement problem ∗This is an expanded version of a talk given at the 2016 Princeton-TAMU Symposium on Quantum Noise Effects in Thermodynamics, Biology and Information [1]. [email protected] 1 2 1 Introduction In the 80 years since the seminal 1935 Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paper (EPR)[2], physi- cists and philosophers have mused about what Einstein referred to as \spooky action at a distance".
    [Show full text]