A Social-Cognitive Approach to Epistemology by Jeremy AB Lent

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Social-Cognitive Approach to Epistemology by Jeremy AB Lent Knowing by Example: A Social-Cognitive Approach to Epistemology by Jeremy A. B. Lent A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2016 Doctoral Committee: Professor Elizabeth S. Anderson, Co-Chair Professor James M. Joyce, Co-Chair Associate Professor Maria Lasonen-Aarnio Professor Richard L. Lewis Professor Peter A. Railton TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER I. Mysterious Knowledge 1 II. Foundation of Trust 20 III. Trouble from Within 55 IV. Trouble from Without 95 V. Beyond the Armchair 137 VI. Social-Cognitive Epistemology 169 BIBLIOGRAPHY 186 ii CHAPTER I: Mysterious Knowledge 1.1 A Puzzle The verb “know” and its cognates are among the most commonly used words in the English language: According to the Corpus of Contemporary American English, “know” is the 49th most common English word, the 10th most common verb, and the most common mental-state verb (Davies and Gardner 2010). Yet some of our “know”-related linguistic habits are quite puzzling—in particular, our habits surrounding “know-that” constructions, such as “I know that ‘know’ is the 10th most common English verb.”1 A particularly striking set of puzzles became widely recognized—at least among philosophers and linguists—in the wake of Edmund Gettier’s 1963 paper, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Until that point, not many philosophers or linguists had put much effort into charting how we use the word “know” in everyday life, let alone developing a general theory about those uses. Gettier took as his foil the theory that when we think about knowledge, we think of something roughly like “a true belief for which the believer has sufficient justification”.2 (By calling a belief “justified”, Gettier and 1 “Know-that” is to be distinguished from “know-how” (e.g., “I know how to search the Corpus of Contemporary American English (COCA)”) and “know-of” (e.g., “I know of the COCA,” or “I know the editors of the COCA”). Except where otherwise noted, when I use “know” and its cognates, I’ll be referring strictly to “know-that”. 2 Despite the lore among epistemologists, it’s not clear how many pre-Gettier philosophers actually endorsed such a theory. For instance, Russell (1948: pp. 170-71) shows clear signs of disagreeing with the “justified true belief” analysis. 1 other philosophers seemed to imply their belief that they would have held the very same belief, had they been in the believer’s shoes.) To demonstrate that knowledge is not equivalent to justified true belief, Gettier posed two now-infamous hypothetical scenarios. In each of them, a believer has a clearly well- justified true belief, yet many of us (Gettier included) are strongly inclined to deny that this believer knows the fact in question. Here, for the sake of tradition, are Gettier’s two cases: Smith and Jones have each applied for a certain job. Smith has strong evidence that Jones will get the job and that Jones has ten coins in his pocket. (Suppose that the president of the company assured Smith that Jones would be selected, and that Smith recently counted the coins in Jones’s pocket.) Smith infers the following proposition from the latter evidence: “The person who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket.” But unknown to Smith, he and not Jones will get the job. Also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his pocket. (ibid., p. 122) Smith has strong evidence that Jones owns a Ford: Jones has at all times in the past within Smith’s memory owned a car, and always a Ford. Smith has another friend, Brown, of whose whereabouts he is totally ignorant. Smith thinks of the city Barcelona quite at random, and constructs the following proposition: “Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona.” Smith realizes the entailment of this proposition from his belief that Jones owns a Ford, and he proceeds to accept it on the basis of this entailment. But in fact, Jones does not own a Ford: He is merely renting one right now. And as it happens, Brown is in fact in Barcelona. (ibid., pp. 122- 23) Epistemologists promptly busied themselves trying to give an account of knowledge—that is, a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for a belief to count as knowledge—which excludes both of Smith’s (justified, true) beliefs but which doesn’t exclude any beliefs (real or hypothetical) which we intuitively do regard as knowledge. (So, for instance, the account shouldn’t deny that we can know what our own names are, or that the derivative of sin(x) is cos(x), or that Ann Arbor is located in the Eastern Time Zone.) Many accounts were proposed which did apparently exclude each of Smith’s beliefs from counting as knowledge. But for each one, some philosopher devised a hypothetical counterexample, involving either (1) a belief which satisfies all the account’s conditions but 2 which doesn’t seem to be knowledge, or (2) a belief which fails one or more of the conditions but which does seem to be knowledge. In the course of this “Gettier game,” dozens of hypothetical cases were constructed involving a true belief which is quite plausibly justified, but which many of us would hesitate to label as knowledge. And today, more than 50 years since Gettier’s paper, there is no account of knowledge which has garnered anything near a consensus among philosophers. In fact, some have abandoned the project of giving non-circular necessary and sufficient conditions as hopeless. For instance, Williamson (2000) proposes that our concept knowledge corresponds to a mental state whose exact nature cannot be expressed in any more-basic terms (at least not of our language). Meanwhile, we’re left with a mountain of often-fanciful hypothetical cases where our willingness (or not) to ascribe knowledge to a particular believer doesn’t seem to fit any detectable, exceptionless pattern. 1.2 A Hypothesis This state of affairs raises quite a puzzle: Why do we humans use the words “know” and “knowledge” in the exact ways that we do? Why, for instance, does it seem wrong to ascribe knowledge to the protagonists in Gettier’s cases and others like them? 3 If some account proposed in Gettier’s wake had succeeded in capturing all of our judgments about knowledge, then perhaps we’d have a good lead on answering the puzzle: We could take the conditions for knowledge in the successful account and, if it weren’t already obvious, try to piece together why humans might have developed a word sensitive to those conditions. However, no account 3 Several recent empirical studies (e.g. Starmans & Friedman 2012) have provided evidence that the apparent philosophical consensus on Gettier’s cases, and others like them, is not shared by a significant proportion of non- philosophers. In Chapter 5, I’ll return to these apparent differences in knowledge ascription patterns between philosophers and non-philosophers, and propose an explanation for them. 3 seems to have succeeded in capturing all of our judgments (or at least those of philosophers) about knowledge. Thus, even if we can determine why humans might have developed a word sensitive to the conditions of an existing account, it will still be a puzzle why we do (or don’t) ascribe knowledge in the cases which the account doesn’t account for. To illustrate: Suppose, counterfactually, that our concept of knowledge was fully captured by the “justified true belief” account. Then we’d still want to ask why humans developed a word specifically to alert each other to the presence of justified true belief, rather than just true belief. Presumably, it’s important to recognize when other people have true beliefs: for purposes of social coordination, for predicting others’ actions (and the consequences of them), etc. But what’s the added value in recognizing that (roughly) we would have believed the same way someone else did had we been in their shoes? What are we thereby at least potentially alerting each other to? Perhaps the reader can begin to see a possible explanation here. But now remember that the “justified true belief” account doesn’t fully capture our knowledge ascription practices. Thus, even if we could determine why humans might have developed a word synonymous with justified true belief, that wouldn’t answer the puzzle we actually have before us. In fact, I believe I’ve found a way to explain why our word “know” functions in all the apparently puzzling ways it does. In essence, my hypothesis is this: Our evolutionary ancestors developed a word which, through linguistic or “memetic” evolution, came to be understood (at least implicitly) by speakers and listeners to convey at least three messages: (1) a given person K is certain of the truth of a particular proposition p (e.g., “The new berries we found are safe to eat”); (2) the speaker is certain of the proposition’s truth too; and (3) the speaker would advise 4 anyone in a position similar to K’s to do the same sort of thing K did in being certain that p (roughly, to “follow K’s example”). 4 My proposal is that our modern-day verb “know” is the descendant of this ancestral word, and that an understanding of the messages it conveys has been transmitted, at least implicitly, through each generation. I’ll spell out the details of this hypothesis in (hopefully not too excruciating) detail in Chapter 2. (For now, I offer this brief statement of the hypothesis as a compass for my reader, so he or she can have a sense of where we’re headed.) After laying out the hypothesis, I’ll spend the rest of Chapter 2 showing how it can account for several potentially puzzling features of our knowledge ascription practices—that is, our uses of the word “know”—among both philosophers and non- philosophers.
Recommended publications
  • A Critical Survey of Some Recent Philosophical Research in China
    Philosophia DOI 10.1007/s11406-016-9768-x A Critical Survey of Some Recent Philosophical Research in China Xingming Hu1 Received: 12 January 2016 /Revised: 23 March 2016 /Accepted: 16 September 2016 # Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 Abstract In this paper, I survey some recent literature produced by the established Chinese philosophers who regularly publish in Chinese philosophy journals and work in Mainland China. Specifically, I review the recent research of these philosophers in two areas: Chinese Philosophy and epistemology. In each area, I focus on two topics that have caught the attention of a lot of Chinese philosophers. I argue that the Chinese philosophers’ research on these topics has two prevalent problems: (i) a lot of argu- ments they make are weak; (ii) they tend not to critically engage with others. I discuss a metaphilosophical objection that weak argumentation and disengagement are not vices of philosophical research. I also try to make sense of (i) and (ii) in terms of some cultural factors. Keywords The goal of philosophy. Chinese philosophy. The legitimacy problem . Confucian ethics . Epistemology . The Gettier Problem . External World Skepticism 1 Introduction How has the philosophical research been done in Mainland China? In this paper, I survey some recent literature produced by the established Chinese philosophers who regularly publish in Chinese philosophy journals and work in Mainland China. Specifically, I review the recent research of these philoso- phers in two areas: Chinese Philosophy and epistemology. In each area, I focus on two topics that have caught the attention of a lot of Chinese philosophers. I argue that the Chinese philosophers’ research on these topics has some preva- lent problems, which might be explained in terms of some metaphilosophical commitments and cultural factors.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth Analysis of the Gettier Argument
    TRUTH ANALYSIS OF THE GETTIER ARGUMENT YUSSIF YAKUBU Published in: METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 47, No. 3, July 2016, 449-466 Abstract: Gettier (1963) presented the now famous Gettier problem as a challenge to epistemology. The methods Gettier used to construct his challenge, however, utilized certain principles of formal logic that are actually inappropriate for the natural language discourse of the Gettier cases. In that challenge to epistemology, Gettier also makes truth claims that would be considered controversial in analytic philosophy of language. The Gettier challenge has escaped scrutiny in these other relevant academic disciplines, however, because of its fac¸adeas an epistemological analysis. This article examines Gettiers methods with the analytical tools of logic and analytic philosophy of language. Keywords: definite description, Russellian quantification, Edmund Gettier, referents and truth, classical logic. Introduction Gettier cases are hypothetical scenarios that purport to demonstrate, contrary to the standard epistemological view, that justified true belief (JTB) is not a sufficient condition for knowledge. In a typical Gettier- type case, a premise that “justifiably” leads an agent to a belief turns out to be false, but the belief the agent derives turns out “by coinci- dence to be true.” The believing agent in question is thus deemed to have a true belief that is justifiably reached, and he therefore, while satisfying the conditions for knowledge, nevertheless does not have knowledge, because the premise upon which he formed his belief is false. Epistemologists have generally taken Gettiers arguments against JTB to be successful, and have been trying, for the five decades since Gettiers paper, to come up with a definition or conception of knowl- edge that would not be undermined by the Gettier-challenge (Zagzeb- ski 1994; Shope 2002, 33; Sosa 2007; see also Kvanvig 2011, 29).
    [Show full text]
  • Gettier Cases
    The University of Manchester Research Gettier Cases Document Version Accepted author manuscript Link to publication record in Manchester Research Explorer Citation for published version (APA): Blouw, P., Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2018). Gettier Cases: A Taxonomy. In R. Borges, C. de Almeida, & P. D. Klein (Eds.), Explaining knowledge: new essays on the Gettier problem (pp. 242-252). Oxford University Press. https://global.oup.com/academic/product/explaining-knowledge-9780198724551?cc=gb&lang=en&# Published in: Explaining knowledge: new essays on the Gettier problem Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on Manchester Research Explorer is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Proof version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Explorer are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Takedown policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please refer to the University of Manchester’s Takedown Procedures [http://man.ac.uk/04Y6Bo] or contact [email protected] providing relevant details, so we can investigate your claim. Download date:05. Oct. 2021 * Gettier Cases: A Taxonomy Peter Blouw [email protected] Wesley Buckwalter [email protected] John Turri [email protected] Short Abstract: The term “Gettier Case” picks out a wide array of thought experiments involving a justified true belief that, many philosophers allege, is intuitively not knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge and Its Limits Professor Wesley Holliday MWF 10-11 UC Berkeley, Spring 2013 101 Barker
    PHIL 4 - Knowledge and Its Limits Professor Wesley Holliday MWF 10-11 UC Berkeley, Spring 2013 101 Barker Syllabus Description In this course, we will investigate questions about the nature and limits of knowledge: Is knowledge compatible with the possibility of human error? Is the structure of our knowledge like a building that rests on a foundation or like a web held together by its connections? What are the requirements for knowledge? Can one know by accident? How can we acquire knowledge and avoid misinformation from others? Whom can we trust? Prerequisites There are no official prerequisites for this course. Success in the course will require the patience to carefully read, re-read, and think about difficult philosophical texts, as well as the willingness to work on developing your skills for clear and rigorous analytical writing. Readings There is a reader for the course sold by Copy Central. Versions of most readings are hyperlinked from this syllabus or bSpace, but the official versions are in the reader. Requirements { Section participation (including Piazza) and quizzes (10% of grade) { In-class exam on February 22 (15% of grade) { 3-5 page paper due on bSpace by March 17, 5pm (20% of grade) { 3-5 page paper due on bSpace by April 14, 5pm (25% of grade) { In-class final exam on May 14, 3-6pm (30% of grade) In-class participation will be taken into account in cases of borderline grades. (CDC recommendation: if you are sick, stay home until 24 hours after symptoms stop.) Sections All enrolled students must attend a weekly discussion section.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism December 13, 2013
    Reason & Explanation: A defense of explanatory coherentism Ted L. Poston University of South Alabama December 13, 2013 ii Contents Preface vii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 A brief history of coherentism . 2 1.2 Two traditional objections to coherentism . 7 1.2.1 The Input Objection . 7 1.2.2 Alternative Systems Objection . 9 1.3 Overview . 11 2 Epistemic Conservatism 17 2.1 The anti-conservative probability argument . 19 2.2 Conservative Justification & Warranted Assertion . 26 2.3 Conservatism & Autobiographical Epistemology . 28 2.4 The `Extra Boost' and Conversion objections . 32 2.4.1 The \Extra Boost" Objection . 32 2.4.2 Conversion objections . 33 2.5 Conservatism & the perspectival character of justification . 35 2.5.1 The argument from perspective . 36 2.5.2 Two challenges . 38 2.6 Conclusion . 40 3 Reasons without first philosophy 41 3.1 The Basic Reasons Dilemma . 42 3.1.1 The First Horn . 42 3.1.2 The Second Horn . 44 3.2 The argument against first philosophy . 45 3.2.1 The nature of basic reasons . 45 3.2.2 No First Philosophy . 48 3.3 Framework Reasons . 51 iii iv CONTENTS 3.4 Weak foundationalism & framework reasons . 56 3.5 Bergmann on foundationalism and epistemic circularity . 58 3.6 Conclusion . 62 4 Explanation & Justification 63 4.1 Explanation & its virtues . 64 4.1.1 Three arguments for primitiveness . 67 4.1.2 The virtues of explanation . 73 4.2 An explanationist theory of justification . 78 4.2.1 The goal . 78 4.2.2 The Ex-J account . 79 4.2.3 Ex-J & Mentalism .
    [Show full text]
  • Phil. 159: Epistemology Oct. 2, 2018 Lecture 9: Zagzebski on the Gettier Problem I
    Phil. 159: Epistemology Oct. 2, 2018 Lecture 9: Zagzebski on the Gettier Problem I. The Gettier Problem (Recap) Two more Gettier cases: Fake Barn Country (Ginet): I’m driving through the countryside with my son. I look to my right and see a (real) barn in broad daylight, under good viewing conditions, etc. As a result, I come to believe that I just passed a barn. However, in the vicinity there are a large number of fake, papier-mâché barns, any of which would have fooled me into thinking it was a real barn. Two Viruses (Zagzebski): I’m a doctor and have very good inductive evidence that my patient, Smith, is suffering from virus X: he exhibits all of the symptoms of this virus, a blood test has shown that his antibody levels against virus X are extremely high, and his symptoms are not compatible with any other known virus. As a result, I come to believe that Smith has virus X. However, Smith’s symptoms are due to a distinct and unknown virus Y, and he exhibits high antibody levels to virus X because of various idiosyncratic features of his biochemistry that cause him to maintain unusually high antibody levels long after a past infection. As it turns out, though, Smith has very recently contracted virus X, but so recently that he does not yet exhibit symptoms caused by X, nor has there been time for a change in the antibody levels due to this infection. In each of these cases, I seem to have a justified true belief that doesn’t count as knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • The Gettier Problem and Legal Proof
    Alabama Law Scholarly Commons Working Papers Faculty Scholarship 4-29-2010 The Gettier Problem and Legal Proof Michael S. Pardo University of Alabama - School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.ua.edu/fac_working_papers Recommended Citation Michael S. Pardo, The Gettier Problem and Legal Proof, (2010). Available at: https://scholarship.law.ua.edu/fac_working_papers/288 This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Alabama Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Alabama Law Scholarly Commons. THE UNIVERSITY OF ALABAMA SCHOOL OF LAW The Gettier Problem and Legal Proof Michael S. Pardo 16 Legal Theory (forthcoming 2010) This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1596709 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1596709 16 Legal Theory (forthcoming 2010) THE GETTIER PROBLEM AND LEGAL PROOF Michael S. Pardo∗ University of Alabama School of Law Abstract This article explores the relationships between legal proof and fundamental epistemic concepts such as knowledge and justification. A survey of the legal literature reveals a confusing array of seemingly inconsistent proposals and presuppositions regarding these relationships. This article makes two contributions. First, it reconciles a number of apparent inconsistencies and tensions in accounts of the epistemology of legal proof. Second, it argues that there is a deeper connection between knowledge and legal proof than is typically argued for or presupposed in the legal literature. This connection is illustrated through a discussion of the Gettier problem in epistemology.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Knowledge, Definition Of
    Propositional Knowledge, Deõnition Of Views 1,984,645 Updated Apr 30 2020 Print this article PROPOSITIONAL KNOWLEDGE, DEFINITION OF The traditional "denition of propositional knowledge," emerging from Plato's Meno and Theaetetus, proposes that such knowledge— knowledge that something is the case—has three essential components. These components are identied by the view that knowledge is justied true belief. Knowledge, according to the traditional denition, is belief of a special kind, belief that satises two necessary conditions: (1) the truth of what is believed and (2) the justication of what is believed. While oering various accounts of the belief condition, the truth condition, and the justication condition for knowledge, many philosophers have held that those three conditions are individually necessary and jointly sucient for propositional knowledge. The belief condition requires that one accept, in some manner, any proposition one genuinely knows. This condition thus relates one psychologically to what one knows. It precludes that one knows a proposition while failing to accept that proposition. Some contemporary philosophers reject the belief condition for knowledge, contending that it requires a kind of mentalistic representation absent from many cases of genuine knowledge. Some other contemporary philosophers endorse the belief condition but deny that it requires actual assent to a proposition. They propose that, given the belief condition, a knower need only be disposed to assent to a proposition. Still other philosophers hold that the kind of belief essential to propositional knowledge requires assent to a known proposition, even if the assent need not be current or ongoing. The traditional belief condition is neutral on the exact conditions for belief and for the objects of belief.
    [Show full text]
  • Gettier and the Problem of Induction by Ean Maloney
    Gettier and the Problem of Induction by Ean Maloney Introduction (4) Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Fifty-four years have passed since Edmund Barcelona. Gettier’s short treatise undercut philosophers’ Let us ignore the fact that the “either…or” formulation complacent confidence in the justified true belief seems to neglect the possibility that Jones could own (JTB) definition of knowledge. Subsequent attempts a Ford and Brown could be in Boston, as we could to redeem, modify, or replace JTB have made easily reformulate (4) to account for this. Gettier tells progress towards these goals but are still inadequate. us that Smith is mistaken that Jones owns a Ford, but I propose that the reason for these deficiencies lies in in fact Brown is in Barcelona. an overestimation of the human capacity to possess The SJB cases reveal that the JTB model fails propositional knowledge. Accordingly, a theory of to account for “epistemic luck,” instances where a knowledge not subject to Gettier problems must conclusion is true for purely coincidental reasons assume a more limited scope of knowledge than not initially considered by the subject (or at least usually considered. Specifically, it is necessary to not believed to exist). These reasons in the SJB reconsider our implicit trust in the possibility and Cases are, respectively, that Smith has ten coins in accessibility of inductive knowledge. his pocket and that Brown is in Barcelona. Though the obvious option for amending the JTB model is Gettier’s Dilemma to explicitly exclude epistemically lucky cases from being considered instances of knowledge, this seems Though I will present several scenarios for 1 consideration in this paper, we ought to keep in a rather ad hoc approach.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatic Gettier: Brandom on Knowledge and Belief
    The Pragmatic Gettier: Brandom on Knowledge and Belief MARÍA JOSÉ FRÁPOLLI §1. Gettier’s insight and its pragmatic1 reading ERE IS ONE OF THE DEFINITIONS of knowledge as justified true belief (JTB) that H Gettier famously defied (Gettier 1966, p. 121): (JTB) S knows that p iff (i) p is true, (ii) S believes that p, and (iii) S is justified in believing that p. His argument to defend that the definition is faulty rests on the following two assumptions and two examples. The assumptions are: (α) “… in that sense of ‘justified’ in which S’s being justified in believing P is a necessary condition of S’s knowing that P, it is possible for a person to be justified in believing a proposition that is in fact false” (loc. cit.), and 1 From my pragmatist perspective, in which I wholeheartedly endorse Wittgenstein’s slogan that meaning is use, and its Brandomian version, that semantics should answer to pragmatics, I consider the line between semantics and pragmatics fuzzy and theory–laden. If semantics answers to pragmatics, I cannot see how to draw a clear–cut distinction between force and semantic content. Differences in force should imply differences in content, and for this reason I do not make a big issue of the distinction. In most of what follows, semantics and pragmatics will refer to aspects of basically the same theoretical enterprise: that of individuating what is said in communicative action and, derivatively, of pinning down the contribution of concepts. This task requires bringing together aspects that are linguistically codified and others belonging to narrow and broad contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Brains and Barns : the Role of Context in Epistemic Attribution
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-2005 Brains and barns : the role of context in epistemic attribution. Julie M. Petty University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Petty, Julie M., "Brains and barns : the role of context in epistemic attribution." (2005). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2387. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2387 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BRAINS AND BARNS: THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN EPISTEMIC ATTRIBUTION A Dissertation Presented by JULIE M. PETTY Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY February 2005 Department of Philosophy © Copyright by Julie M. Petty 2005 All Rights Reserved BRAINS AND BARNS: THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN EPISTEMIC ATTRIBUTION A Dissertation Presented by JULIE M. PETTY Approved as to style and content by: *7 Fred Feldman, Chair '7 Edmund L. Gettier, Member r> - Phillip Bricker, Department Head Philosophy ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank my advisor, Fred Feldman, for the many, many years of excellent philosophical instruction and for his caring and personal support of my efforts to complete my doctorate. I also thank my committee members - Ed Gettier, Jonathan Schaffer, and Angelika Kratzer — for their time and their contributions to this work.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge Before Gettier1
    KNOWLEDGE BEFORE GETTIER1 Pierre Le Morvan Published (2017) in the BRITISH JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 25(6): 1-23 According to a historical claim oft-repeated by contemporary epistemologists, the “traditional” conception of knowledge prevailed in Western philosophy prior to the publication in 1963 of Edmund’s Gettier’s famous three-page article “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” On this conception, knowledge consists of justified true belief. In this article, I critically consider evidence for and against this historical claim, and conclude with a puzzle concerning its widespread acceptance. KEYWORDS: Knowledge; Justified True Belief; Gettier “For much of the history of Western philosophy, the dominant account of knowledge was that knowledge is justified true belief. But in a short paper published in 1963, Edmund Gettier challenged this traditional account by offering a pair of hypothetical counter-examples.” Machery et al. (2015, 1) 1 For very helpful and constructive comments on earlier drafts, I wish to thank Katherine Le Morvan, Stephen Hetherington, two anonymous referees of this journal and its editor. 2 1. Introduction You have probably heard this story. For several decades, many epistemologists have retold it in their books, articles, and classrooms. Composed of two key claims, it runs as follows. In the ages prior to 1963 reigned the “traditional” (or “standard” or “classical”) conception or analysis of knowledge according to which justified true belief is both necessary and sufficient for knowing that p. In 1963, however, Edmund Gettier, with two famous counter-examples, overturned this conception, or at least seriously challenged it, and epistemology has never been the same.
    [Show full text]