ATS1835) IntroducOn to Philosophy B Semester 2, 2017 Dr Ron Gallagher [email protected] Week 10 (1 Le): Knowledge (Epistemology) & ScepCism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

ATS1835) Introduc�On to Philosophy B Semester 2, 2017 Dr Ron Gallagher Ron.Gallagher@Monash.Edu Week 10 (1 Le�): Knowledge (Epistemology) & Scep�Cism Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835) Introduc;on to Philosophy B Semester 2, 2017 Dr Ron Gallagher [email protected] Week 10 (1 le): Knowledge (Epistemology) & Scep;cism What is knowledge? What is jus3fed true belief? What is scepcism? What is doubt? What is jusficaon? Can any knowledge be jus3fied? Can ordinarily accepted statements be jusfied? Radical doubt is nonsensical, selec3ve doubt needs grounds for doubt. Week Beginning Topic Assessment Readings W1 24-Jul Time - Introduction and Time Travel 1.1 & 1.2 Time Travel; Freedom, Determinism, and W2 31-Jul Indeterminism 1.5 & 1.6 Short Answer 1 - W3 07-Aug Logic Primer August 10th 2.1 – 2.2 Mind- Dualism versus Materialism about W4 14-Aug the Mind 3.1 - 3.2 Mind - Can Machines Think? W5 21-Aug Computationalism and the Turing Test 3.3 Mind - Can Machines Think? Objections to Short Answer 2 - 3.4 W6 28-Aug Computationalism Aug 31st Self - Lockean Psychological Theory and W7 04-Sep Identity 4.1 – 4.3 W8 11-Sep Self - Identity, the Body & Person Stages 4.4 – 4.5 Knowledge What is Knowledge and Short Answer 3 – W9 18-Sep Gettier's Account Sep 21st 5.1 – 5.2 25-Sep Mid-semester break Knowledge - Nozick's Account and 5.3 – 5.4 W10 02-Oct Scepticism Essay - October 5.5 W11 09-Oct Knowledge - The Moorean Response 12th W12 16-Oct Revision (no lectures, no tutorials) Assessment Due Date Assessment Task Value Mondays 10am Reading Quizzes (10) 5% (bonus) Thu Aug 10th AT1.1 (@600 words) 10% Thu Aug 31st AT1.2 (@600 words) 10% Thu Sep 21st AT1.3 (@600 words) 10% Thu Oct 12th AT2 Essay (@1250 words) 30% TBA Exam 40% Hurdle Requirements to Pass this Unit Your overall grade for the unit must be at least 50% You must achieve a grade of 40% or more on the final exam You must submit all assessment tasks (not including Reading Quizzes) You must not fail more than one assessment task (not including Reading Quizzes) You cannot miss more than 3 tutorials AT2: Essay Assignment (Due: October 12th, 10am) General Instructions Word Limit: 1250 words Value: 30% Presentation Requirements: Your assignment should be presented in 12-point font and 1.5 or double-spaced. It will require references and a bibliography. Acceptable Formats: .doc or .rtf. (If you want to use some other format, clear it with your tutor beforehand.) Only submit an electronic copy; no hard copy submission required. File Name: Name your file using the following convention: [Question Number] [Surname] Example: "3Silva.doc," "5Smith.rtf", "1Jones.docx" Referencing and Citation: http://artsonline.monash.edu.au/philosophy/resources-for- undergraduate-students/ In your essay, you should try to fulfill the following requirements, especially the first: • The essay must address the question asked. • It should have a structure that is clear and organised to form a coherent argument. • You should explain, in your own words, views and arguments in the prescribed readings that are relevant to the topic. Be careful to present these views fairly and accurately, with adequate citation detail. • You should try to evaluate the arguments you have discussed, and in the process work out your own position. When you criticise a philosopher, try to think how she might reply to your objections. • You must carefully identify all connections between your essay and the writings of others. Chicago style (numerical citation, footnotes) with bibliography at the end. Harvard style (in-text citation) with bibliography at the end. ESSAY MARKING CRITERIA - from ATS1835 Unit Guide ESSAY FAQs • Essay Due Thursday 12th October 10am @1250 words 30% • The word limit is +/- 10% of 1250 words. • You are required to use at least one of the readings (not just the commentary or lecture slides) from the TSM Reader as your primary text. • You can reference the TSM Reader by page number, eg (Kane, 2007,TSM Reader p.56), you do not need to use the original page numbers of the individual papers in the Reader. • Begin the essay with a statement of YOUR thesis (eg You believe that machines do not think, and that Turing is wrong for such and such a reason and that Searle makes some good points) and how you are going to support it with arguments from the TSM Reader Essay Topics Write on one of the following topics. AT2 Essay - Thursday Oct 12th, 10am - @1250 words – 30% 5. Knowledge Gettier raises some serious challenges for the traditional account of knowledge. Nozick develops his tracking account in part to answer the problems identified by Gettier. After explaining both Gettier's challenge and Nozick's proposal, evaluate the strength of Nozick's proposal as a response to Gettier's challenge. Required reading: Edmund Gettier, 'Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?' Robert Nozick, 'Knowledge and Skepticism' 1. Knowledge as Justified True Belief There are three components to the traditional (“tripartite”) analysis of knowledge. According to this analysis, justified, true belief is necessary and sufficient for knowledge. The Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge: S knows that p iff p is true; S believes that p; S is justified in believing that p. The tripartite analysis of knowledge is often abbreviated as the “JTB” analysis, for “justified true belief”. From http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/index.html JTB? Derelict Juror: Imagine two Stubborn Evolu;onist: Henry jurors, Jenna and Nalie, has been exposed to a number deliberang about the case of of raonally compelling Mr. Mansour. Both jurors have arguments for the theory of paid close aen;on throughout evolu;on. Despite the trial. As a result, both have understanding these arguments, Henry refuses to accept good reason to believe that [evolu;on], through sheer Mansour is guilty. Each juror stubbornness. One day, Henry’s goes on to form the belief that tarot card reader tells him that, Mansour is guilty, which he in based on a recent tarot reading, fact is. Nalie believes he’s she has determined that the guilty because of the evidence theory of evolu;on is true. presented during the trial. Jenna Henry then finally accepts believes he’s guilty because he evolu;on on the basis of the looks suspicious. tarot reading. QUESTION: Does Harry know QUESTION: Does Jenna know that evolu;on is true? that Mansour is guilty? The Basing Demand General Issue: – S can have terrific evidence to think P true. – S can believe P is true. – But S can fail to believe P because of the evidence. = S can fail to base her belief in P on the evidence. = S can believe P for obviously irrelevant reasons. The Basing Demand: In order to know P one must have a jusfied belief in P. In order to have a jusfied belief one must base that belief on good reasons. Epistemic Luck (Russell) Alice sees a clock that reads two o’clock, and believes that the time is two o’clock. It is in fact two o'clock. There's a problem, however: unknown to Alice, the clock she’s looking at stopped twelve hours ago. Alice thus has an accidentally true, justified belief. Russell 3. The Gettier Problem In his short 1963 paper, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Edmund Gettier presented two effective counterexamples to the JTB analysis (Gettier 1963). One of these goes as follows. Suppose Smith has good evidence for the false proposition (1)Jones owns a Ford. Suppose further Smith infers from (1) the following three disjunctions: (2)Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Boston. (3)Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona. (4)Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Brest-Litovsk. Since (1) entails each of the propositions (2) through (4), and since Smith recognizes these entailments, his beliefs in propositions (2)–(4) are justified. Now suppose that, by sheer coincidence, Brown is indeed in Barcelona. Given these assumptions, we may say that Smith, when he believes (3), holds a justified true belief. However, is Smith's belief an instance of knowledge? Intuitively, Smith's belief cannot be knowledge; it is merely lucky that it is true. In the first example, Gettier supposes that two people, Smith and Jones, have applied for a job. We suppose that Smith has a justified belief that Jones will get the job. The evidence for it is high enough that Smith justifiably believes it, “might be that the president of the company assured him that Jones would in the end be selected” Smith also believes (and indeed, knows) that Jones has ten coins in his pocket, which is true and was demonstrated to him, possibly by Jones counting them himself. From this he believes the logical conseqence of these beliefs, that “the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket”¹ It turns out that Smith was wrong, and that, for some unforseeable reason, it turns out that Smith gets the job, and Jones does not. It also turns out that Smith has ten coins in his pocket, though he didn't realize it. The question is, was Smith's belief that “the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket” knowledge? Gettier and Propositional Knowledge Gettier argues that one could have a true justified belief which is not knowledge in a situation in which one reasons from some already justified beliefs to a new belief that, as it happens, is coincidentally true. Since it would then be a matter of coincidence that one’s belief was correct, it would not count as knowledge, even though it was a justified belief because it was knowingly inferred from already justified beliefs.
Recommended publications
  • Socrates and the Theaetetus
    THE ORIGIN OF THE ‘GETTIER’ PROBLEM: SOCRATES AND THE THEAETETUS Michael JENKINS ABSTRACT: This article discusses the origin of what has become known as the Gettier Problem. It examines the claim put forward, though not expounded or defended, by J. Angelo Corlett in Analyzing Social Knowledge that the basis for Edmund Gettier’s article “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” was originally argued for in Plato’s Theaetetus. In his article, Gettier argues that the Justified True Belief condition is not sufficient for knowledge. However, Corlett questions the originality of this argument. This article examines Gettier’s article followed by the Theatetus. After which, the two articles are compared, and the claim is shown to be correct in accusing Gettier of failing consider the full work of the Theaetetus. Socrates also argued that the Justified True Belief condition was not sufficient for knowledge. However, this article concludes by arguing that Socrates went further with his examination than Gettier did. Socrates not only put forward the claim that this condition was insufficient for knowledge, he also tried to supply answers to the problem. KEYWORDS: Gettier, Theaetetus, epistemology, Socrates, coherentism, justification 1. Introduction In Analyzing Social Knowledge, J. Angelo Corlett states that Edmund L. Gettier, in his infamous article “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”1 seems to merely reiterate what Socrates (in Plato’s Theaetetus) already articulates: that “simple justified true belief is insufficient for knowledge.”2 In this article, I will argue that Corlett’s statement is correct. I will argue that it originated not with Gettier, but at least as far back into the writing of western philosophy as Socrates.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Reflections on Gettier's Problem
    Some Reflections on Gettier’s Problem Golam Azam * It is one of the basic problems of epistemology to define knowledge. Epistemology is one of the branches of philosophy that discusses about the definition, sources, validity and limitations of knowledge. From Socrates to till date this problem is being discussed by most of the eminent philosophers; ancient, medieval, modern or contemporary- eastern or western- Indian, Muslim, Chinese or Buddhist philosophers. Why knowledge is important, what the criterion of truth is, are also the basic issues of discussion of the philosophers of the ages. E. Gettier, an American epistemologist, published a paper of only three pages entitled “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” in 1963 where he challenged the age-old definition of knowledge. Traditionally knowledge is defined as ‘justified true belief’. Gettier showed that these three conditions are not enough for the definition of knowledge. In this paper, Gettier’s conception regarding the definition of knowledge will be analyzed and in this connection the reaction of the contemporary epistemologists will also be interpreted and analyzed. It will be showed that now a day the fundamental problem of knowledge is not to define ‘knowledge’ rather the problem is mainly regarding the justification of the statement of knowledge. I Before the publication of Gettier's paper knowledge was widely defined as justified true belief. It is the pre-Gettier definition of knowledge. After the publication of Gettier’s paper the term ‘Gettier problem’ has become well known to the contemporary philosophers. Gettier problems or cases are named in honor of the American philosopher Edmund Gettier.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth Analysis of the Gettier Argument
    TRUTH ANALYSIS OF THE GETTIER ARGUMENT YUSSIF YAKUBU Published in: METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 47, No. 3, July 2016, 449-466 Abstract: Gettier (1963) presented the now famous Gettier problem as a challenge to epistemology. The methods Gettier used to construct his challenge, however, utilized certain principles of formal logic that are actually inappropriate for the natural language discourse of the Gettier cases. In that challenge to epistemology, Gettier also makes truth claims that would be considered controversial in analytic philosophy of language. The Gettier challenge has escaped scrutiny in these other relevant academic disciplines, however, because of its fac¸adeas an epistemological analysis. This article examines Gettiers methods with the analytical tools of logic and analytic philosophy of language. Keywords: definite description, Russellian quantification, Edmund Gettier, referents and truth, classical logic. Introduction Gettier cases are hypothetical scenarios that purport to demonstrate, contrary to the standard epistemological view, that justified true belief (JTB) is not a sufficient condition for knowledge. In a typical Gettier- type case, a premise that “justifiably” leads an agent to a belief turns out to be false, but the belief the agent derives turns out “by coinci- dence to be true.” The believing agent in question is thus deemed to have a true belief that is justifiably reached, and he therefore, while satisfying the conditions for knowledge, nevertheless does not have knowledge, because the premise upon which he formed his belief is false. Epistemologists have generally taken Gettiers arguments against JTB to be successful, and have been trying, for the five decades since Gettiers paper, to come up with a definition or conception of knowl- edge that would not be undermined by the Gettier-challenge (Zagzeb- ski 1994; Shope 2002, 33; Sosa 2007; see also Kvanvig 2011, 29).
    [Show full text]
  • THE UNIVERSITY of WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT of PHILOSOPHY Graduate Course Outline 2016-17
    THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Graduate Course Outline 2016-17 Philosophy 9653A: Proseminar Fall Term 2016 Instructor: Robert J. Stainton Class Days and Hours: W 2:30-5:30 Office: StH 3126 Office Hours: Tu 2:00-3:00 Classroom: TBA Phone: 519-661-2111 ext. 82757 Web Site: Email: [email protected] http://publish.uwo.ca/~rstainto/ Blog: https://robstainton.wordpress.com/ DESCRIPTION A survey of foundational and highly influential texts in Analytic Philosophy. Emphasis will be on four sub-topics, namely Language and Philosophical Logic, Methodology, Ethics and Epistemology. Thematically, the focal point across all sub-topics will be the tools and techniques highlighted in these texts, which reappear across Analytic philosophy. REQUIRED TEXT A.P. Martinich and David Sosa (eds.)(2011) Analytic Philosophy: An Anthology. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [All papers except the Stine and Thomson are reprinted here.] OBJECTIVES The twin objectives are honing of philosophical skills and enriching students’ familiarity with some “touchstone” material in 20th Century Analytic philosophy. In terms of skills, the emphasis will be on: professional-level philosophical writing; close reading of notoriously challenging texts; metaphilosophical reflection; and respectful philosophical dialogue. COURSE REQUIREMENTS Twelve weekly “Briefing Notes” on Selected Readings: 60% Three “Revised Brief Notes”: 25% Class Participation: 15% COURSE READINGS Language and Philosophical Logic Gottlob Frege (1892), “On Sense and Reference” Gottlob Frege (1918), “The Thought” Bertrand Russell (1905), “On Denoting” Ludwig Wittgenstein (1933-35 [1958]), Excerpts from The Blue and Brown Books Peter F. Strawson (1950), “On Referring” H. Paul Grice (1957), “Meaning” H. Paul Grice (1975), “Logic and Conversation” Saul Kripke (1971), “Identity and Necessity” Hilary Putnam (1973), “Meaning and Reference” Methodology A.J.
    [Show full text]
  • REP Knowledge
    Knowledge, Concept of Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Michael Hannon University of Nottingham Keywords: knowledge; ignorance; justification; scepticism Article Summary The word ‘know’ is exceptional for a number of reasons. It is one of the 10 most commonly used verbs in English, alongside basic verbs like ‘be,’ ‘do,’ ‘say,’ ‘have,’ and ‘go.’ It is also the most frequently used term in epistemic evaluation: we speak of ‘knowing’ far more often than we speak of ‘justification,’ ‘reliability,’ ‘understanding,’ ‘wisdom,’ and other intellectual traits or epistemic properties. Perhaps most strikingly, the word ‘know’ allegedly has a meaning-equivalent in every human language. Unlike almost every other word in English, linguists have identified ‘know’ as one of a very small number of words that are culturally universal (Goddard 2010). These facts suggest that knowledge is deeply important to human life. Knowledge has also held a central place in epistemology. Indeed, the word ‘epistemology’ comes from the Greek word epistêmê, which is often translated as ‘knowledge.’ This is not to say that epistemologists are only interested in knowledge. They also investigate epistemic virtues like open- mindedness and intellectual humility, as well as properties of belief like being rational and justified (among many other things). Still, the enterprise of epistemology has largely been an investigation into the nature, significance, sources, and extent of human knowledge. But what is knowledge? Why do we value it? How is it acquired? And how much of it do we have? In the late 20th century, one of the central questions asked by epistemologists was: When does a true belief count as knowledge? It was widely assumed that knowledge is a form of true belief plus some additional requirement(s), such as justification or reliability.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Gettier in Edmund Gettier's Essay, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge
    Gettier In Edmund Gettier’s essay, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge,” Gettier argues that JTB (Plato’s theory of Justified True Belief) does not necessarily guarantee knowledge. This means that the necessary but not the sufficient conditions for “S knows P” to be true have been met. What follows is a discussion of necessary and sufficient conditions, the conditions that satisfy JTB, and Gettier’s reasoning of why JTB does not necessarily guarantee knowledge. A necessary condition for some state of affairs P is a condition that must be satisfied in order for P to obtain. For example, what are the necessary conditions (P) that must be satisfied in order for some student (S) to pass a course at some college or university? Let’s say that those necessary conditions for S to pass are: (1) S must submit all of their assignments, and (2) take all of the exams and quizzes. However, submitting all of the assignments and taking all of the exams and quizzes will not guarantee that S will obtain P (pass the course). So how can S guarantee that they will pass the course? The conditions that will guarantee that’s S will pass the course are referred to as sufficient conditions. A sufficient condition for some state of affairs P is a condition that, if satisfied guarantees that P obtains. For example, the sufficient conditions for P are: (1) S must get a passing grade on all assignments, and (2) pass all of exams and quizzes. If these conditions are satisfied, this guarantees that S will pass the course.
    [Show full text]
  • Classics of Analytic Philosophy First Year Seminar Princeton University Fall 2008
    Classics of Analytic Philosophy First Year Seminar Princeton University Fall 2008 Delia G. Fara [email protected] Thomas Kelly [email protected] Wednesdays, 2:30-4:30. Each week we will read a seminal work of twentieth century analytic philosophy and try to make as much sense of it as we can together. We will attempt to reconstruct and evaluate the author's argument, but we will be no less concerned to place the work in historical context and to understand why it achieved landmark status. Students will make presentations and write short (2-3 page) papers on a regular basis (roughly, every other week). Please bring two hard copies of your paper to class. Schedule of Readings (subject to change at discretion of the instructors). Week 1, 9/17. G.E. Moore, “The Subject Matter of Ethics”, chapter 1 of his Principia Ethica (1903). Week 2, 9/24. Bertrand Russell, “On Denoting”. Mind, New Series, vol.14, No.56 (Oct. 1905), pp.479-493. Available via JSTOR. Reprinted in his Logic and Knowledge. Russell, “Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge By Description”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series), Vol.XI, (1910-1911), pp.108-128. Reprinted in his Mysticism and Logic. Week 3, 10/1. A.J. Ayer, “The Elimination of Metaphysics”, “The Function of Philosophy”, and “The A Priori”, Chapters 1, 2, and 4 of his Language, Truth, and Logic (1936), pp.33- 58, 71-87. 2 Week 4, 10/8. Ayer, “Critique of Ethics and Theology”, chapter 6 of Language, Truth, and Logic, pp.102-120. J.L.Mackie, “The Subjectivity of Values”, chapter 1 of his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (1977), pp.15-49.
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Diversity in Epistemology
    CONCEPTUAL DIVERSITY IN EPISTEMOLOGY RICHARD FOLEY Rational belief belongs to a cluster of normative concepts that also includes reasonable, justified, and warranted belief. Each of these notions is commonly used by epistemologists, and along with the notion of knowledge, they form a central part of the subject matter of epistemology. However, there is no generally agreed way of understanding these notions. Nor is there even agreement as to whether they are equivalent. Some epistemologists employ them interchangeably; other epistemologists choose to express their conclusions using only one of the above notions and avoid making use of the other notions; yet other epistemologists distinguish among two or more of the notions. It is generally agreed, however, that beliefs are the appropriate focus for epistemological investigations into these notions, or for some epistemologists, degrees of belief. Decisions, actions, plans, intentions, strategies and many other phenomena are assessed in terms of how rational, reasonable, justified, or warranted they are, but when doing epistemology, the aim is to understand what it takes for a belief to be rational, reasonable, justified, or warranted. To be sure, epistemologists also often refer to propositions, statements, claims, hypotheses, and theories as being rational, reasonable, justified, or warranted, but in general these uses are best understood as derivative. To say, for example, that a theory is reasonable is to say (very roughly) that the relevant evidence is such that were an individual acquainted with this evidence, it would be reasonable for the individual to believe the theory. Despite the centrality of the above notions for epistemology (again, along with the notion of knowledge), there is an under appreciation of the fact that these notions are often used in the literature in strikingly different ways and a corresponding lack of explicit discussion of what desiderata the accounts of these notions should be satisfying.
    [Show full text]
  • DISCOURSES: a PHILOSOPHY READINGS DATABASE Edited by Donald C
    Discourses Fall 2011 DISCOURSES: A PHILOSOPHY READINGS DATABASE Edited by Donald C. Abel There are 284 Topical Readings; some are listed under more than one topic. Each Topical Reading is available with or without study questions. The section Classic Works: Complete Texts contains 63 works, with longer works subdivided into separate sections. See pp. 11-13 for a list of these works. All the readings may be used in a custom printed book; most of the readings (313 out of 347) may also be used in a custom eBook. All the eBook readings are viewable online. WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY? Donald C. Abel, “Glossary of Philosophical Terms” (complete) eBook Option! Aristotle, “Metaphysics” (selection) eBook Option! Mary Midgley, “Philosophical Plumbing” (complete) eBook Option! Josef Pieper, “The Philosophical Act” (selection) Plato, “Apology” (complete) eBook Option! Plato, “Crito” (complete) eBook Option! Plato, “Euthyphro” (complete) eBook Option! Bertrand Russell, “The Problems of Philosophy” (selection) eBook Option! J. J. C. Smart, “Philosophy and Scientific Realism” (selection) PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Robert Merrihew Adams, “Must God Create the Best?” (selection) eBook Option! Anselm, “Monologion” (selection) eBook Option! Anselm, “Proslogion and Exchange with Gaunilo” (selection) eBook Option! Thomas Aquinas, “Summa Theologiae” (selection 1) eBook Option! Augustine, “The Free Choice of the Will” (selection) Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, “The Consolation of Philosophy” (selection) eBook Option! C. D. Broad, “Arguments for the Existence of God” (selection) NEW! Samuel Clarke, “A Demonstration of the Being and Attributes of God” (selection) eBook Option! W. K. Clifford, “The Ethics of Belief” (selection) eBook Option! NEW! William Lane Craig, “The Existence of God and the Beginning of the Universe” (selection) eBook Option! Thomas D.
    [Show full text]
  • Externalism and Epistemic Responsibility
    Colby Quarterly Volume 27 Issue 2 June Article 6 June 1991 Externalism and Epistemic Responsibility Jennifer Armstrong Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.colby.edu/cq Recommended Citation Colby Quarterly, Volume 27, no.2, June 1991, p.88-99 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Colby. It has been accepted for inclusion in Colby Quarterly by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Colby. Armstrong: Externalism and Epistemic Responsibility Externalism and Epistemic Responsibility by JENNIFER ARMSTRONG A CCORDING to Lawrence Bonjour, an adequate theory of empirical knowl­ rt edge must provide two things: (1) an account of epistemic justification, and (2) a metajustification for the proposed account showing the proposed standards to be truth-conducive (Bonjour, p. 9). His attempt to use coherence in the long run as the latter exposes what I take to be one of the central problems in contemporary epistemology: "hooking up"justifiedbeliefwith knowledge. In thinking about this problem and the various attempts Bonjour and others have made to overcome it, it occurs to me that this difficulty is remarkably like a parallel problem in utilitarian normative ethics. This paper is an attempt to draw the parallel convincingly and to suggest that similar responses to those made by the utilitarian ethicist are available to the epistemologist. The Ethical Line Total Utility Utilitarianism (TUU): Act A is morally right if A produces as much or more total utility than any alternative to A. U TIL ITY here is a term ofgeneric intrinsic value. Exactly what thing or things are intrinsically valuable is left unspecified, but a state of affairs has positive utility to the degree that it includes what is intrinsically good and negative utility to the degree that in includes what is intrinsically bad.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge Before Gettier1
    KNOWLEDGE BEFORE GETTIER1 Pierre Le Morvan Published (2017) in the BRITISH JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 25(6): 1-23 According to a historical claim oft-repeated by contemporary epistemologists, the “traditional” conception of knowledge prevailed in Western philosophy prior to the publication in 1963 of Edmund’s Gettier’s famous three-page article “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” On this conception, knowledge consists of justified true belief. In this article, I critically consider evidence for and against this historical claim, and conclude with a puzzle concerning its widespread acceptance. KEYWORDS: Knowledge; Justified True Belief; Gettier “For much of the history of Western philosophy, the dominant account of knowledge was that knowledge is justified true belief. But in a short paper published in 1963, Edmund Gettier challenged this traditional account by offering a pair of hypothetical counter-examples.” Machery et al. (2015, 1) 1 For very helpful and constructive comments on earlier drafts, I wish to thank Katherine Le Morvan, Stephen Hetherington, two anonymous referees of this journal and its editor. 2 1. Introduction You have probably heard this story. For several decades, many epistemologists have retold it in their books, articles, and classrooms. Composed of two key claims, it runs as follows. In the ages prior to 1963 reigned the “traditional” (or “standard” or “classical”) conception or analysis of knowledge according to which justified true belief is both necessary and sufficient for knowing that p. In 1963, however, Edmund Gettier, with two famous counter-examples, overturned this conception, or at least seriously challenged it, and epistemology has never been the same.
    [Show full text]
  • ARE GETTIER CASES MISLEADING? Philip ATKINS
    ARE GETTIER CASES MISLEADING? Philip ATKINS ABSTRACT: The orthodox view in contemporary epistemology is that Edmund Gettier refuted the JTB analysis of knowledge, according to which knowledge is justified true belief. In a recent paper Moti Mizrahi questions the orthodox view. According to Mizrahi, the cases that Gettier advanced against the JTB analysis are misleading. In this paper I defend the orthodox view. KEYWORDS: analysis of knowledge, Gettier cases, semantic reference, speaker’s reference The orthodox view in contemporary epistemology is that Edmund Gettier refuted the JTB analysis of knowledge, according to which knowledge is justified true belief.1 In a recent paper Moti Mizrahi questions the orthodox view.2 According to Mizrahi, the cases that Gettier advanced against the JTB analysis are misleading. For, according to Mizrahi, they are cases of semantic failure (i.e., failure to refer to something) rather than epistemic failure (i.e., failure to know something). In this paper I defend the orthodox view. I should mention that Mizrahi discusses several ‘Gettier cases’ besides the two that Gettier originated. Mizrahi discusses Roderick Chisholm’s sheep case, Alvin Goldman’s fake barn case, and Bertrand Russell’s stopped clock case.3 It is Mizrahi’s opinion that all these cases are misleading. I disagree across the board, but for the sake of brevity I focus exclusively on Gettier’s two cases. These are genuine counterexamples to the JTB analysis, or so I contend. In Gettier’s first case, Smith comes to have strong evidence for believing that Jones is the man who will get the job and that Jones has ten coins in his pocket.
    [Show full text]