<<

Chapter 3 . Practiceand the possibility of

“The ethical life belongs to human ,livingtogether in ever largergroups, and work- ing out their shared liveswith one another.’stask is to facilitatethis working out.” — P. Kitcher

1Cosmopolitanism as apersonal wayoflife

Cosmopolitanism and are not onlytheoretical normative ideals. They can become alived practice when theyare endorsed by individual agents, shape theirethos, and influencehow agents feel and think, talk and act about global issues. The third essential feature of my of cosmopolitan responsi- bility is its pragmatic for which Itake some inspiration from the rich and diverse philosophical of US-Americanpragmatism, notablyfrom the works of .¹⁴⁵ Although the inspiration is more general thansystemat- ic, the following chapter will introduce several elements of apragmatist ap- proach to that Isuggest to integrate into the proposed theory of cosmopol- itan responsibility. To be clear,Ido not aspire to develop acomprehensive account of pragmatic ethics, which is admittedlyinitself less acoherent moral than aspecific perspective on the means and aims of ethics.¹⁴⁶ Neither do Ipropose afull pragmatist account of (global) .¹⁴⁷

 The that Dewey’sbiography shows him personallyanactive cosmopolitan, involved in manyprogressive social movements around the world, shall onlybebrieflymentioned here. For his engagement in Turkey,China, Mexicoand elsewhere, cf. the biographybyMartin (2002).— Dewey himself does not particularlystress the cosmopolitan implications of his ethics himself. Nevertheless,therehavebeen several attempts in the literaturetoreadhim as acosmopolitan in general, as wellasavaluable contributortothe project of aglobal ethics (Waks 2009,Hickman 2010). Particularly fruitful, in this regard, wereattempts to takeupDewey’sthinkinginpolitical theory and of (Cochran 1999,Bray2011).  overviews areprovided by LaFollette(2000), Anderson (2010a), Pappas (1998), Serra (2009) and Welchman (1995).– Yet, even for asingle pragmatist likeDewey,itisdif- ficulttoidentify the concretecontentofhis ethics.AsPappas has it: “When reading Dewey […]it is importanttoresist the philosophical habitoftryingtofind a ‘system.’ Abetterapproach is to become acquaintedwith his moral vision. But this task is complicated by the fact that Dewey did not consolidatehis about ethics in asingle work. He scatteredhis ideas throughouthis manybooks and essays.Insome cases he even presented them in aparagraphortwo placed

OpenAccess. ©2020 Jan-Christoph Heilinger,published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110612271-005 120 Pragmatism

In asomewhat piecemeal approach then, Isimplyseek to present selected ele- ments of pragmatist and neo-pragmatist reasoningabout ethics which together point towardsaplausible alternative to avariety of conventional philosophical thinking about the role and goals of ethics. Central to the pragmatic approach is the role of individual experience,the importance of personal habits and pat- terns of conduct as away to turn considered values into justified action, asys- tematic method for moralinquiry that makes room for normative pluralism, and an optimisticbelief in the possibilityofprogress in living together.These ele- ments also shape the ethos of cosmopolitan responsibility. Pragmatism is often metwith reproach of refusingtoprovide asubstantial normative criterion for decision making and assessment and concerned in- stead simply with ‘whatever works’.Iftrue, anarrowfocus on ‘whatever works’ would make for avery uninteresting view,particularlyinethics, since ethics should provide appropriatereasons for the normative views held and actions un- dertaken. While astrict ‘whatever works’ hence cannot constituteaworthwhile aim of the ethical project (nor of anyphilosophical undertaking), the reproach against pragmatism nevertheless catches well one distinctive feature of pragma- tist ethics:namelythat philosophicalreasoninginethics should take into ac- count how the theoretical tools employed make adifferenceinpractice. Acentral claim in pragmatism is that ideas, includingnorms and values, cannot prove their “” independentlyfrom practical implementation, i.e. they have to be put to ‘work’.Inthe words of James: “truth happens to an ” (James 1909, 574). Truth,onthis understanding,isnothing but the successful use of ideas in practice.Pragmatism is hence concerned, first,with the acute circumstances under which certain problems appear;and,secondly, with the impact theories and ideas actuallyhaveinsuch circumstances, i.e., how they work with regard to overcomingordealing with perceivedproblems. In this pragmatic sense,moralityisnot adetached intellectual enterprise of establishing adeterminate and substantiveset of rules and to guide human behaviour,but should be understood as acollective,social undertaking, as acontinuingprocess, an ongoingchallengetofigureout how to deal best with the givenproblems in the context of humans living together.

almost parentheticallyinthe midst of apassagedevoted to another philosophical topic” (Pap- pas 1998, 100).  It has been notedthat the notion of justiceislargely absent in Dewey’swritings (Dieleman, Rondel et al. 2017). While recentlysome have started to address this lacuna (Talisse 2017,Rondel 2018), my own attempttoadvance the project of aglobal can, as is explained in this chapter,drawdirectlyfrommanypragmatist insights. Cosmopolitanismasapersonal way of life 121

This first,tentative characterisation invites abrief recapitulation of the con- creteproblem for which the turn towardpragmatism seems to me particularly useful. At issue in this book is, ultimately, the problem of how humans should live together under conditions of globalisation, which are currentlyshaped by enormousinequalities in distribution, massive asymmetries in power and influ- ence, and persisting domination and structuralinjustice. In this context it is still unclear how exactlyindividuals should act and institutional arrangements should look like in order to allow and support good livesfor all and agood living together of all. This is the massive,current ethical challengeofthe ethical proj- ect.Inaddressingit, Kitcher,for example, foresees also arole for moral philos- ophy: “The ethical life belongstohuman beings, living togetherineverlarger groups,and workingout their shared liveswith one another.Philosophy’stask is to facilitatethis workingout.” (Kitcher 2012,2). Iagree and my writing thus aspires to contribute to the task of figuring out how individuals should think and act in order to live well together underthe de facto circumstances of cosmo- politanism. These global circumstances generate ajointlyshared sphere of interaction that can alsobecaputured in pragmatic perspective.For Dewey,the actual inter- actionsbetween people who live together,beitinsmaller or largergroups,give rise to what he calls “the public”.The public is constituted by all who are in one wayoranother influenced or affected by the other’sactions. In ThePublic and Its Problems,Dewey writes

We take then our point of departurefromthe objective fact that human acts have conse- quences upon others,that some of these consequences areperceived, and that their percep- tion leads to subsequent effort to control action so as to securesome consequences and avoid others.Followingthis clew,weare led to remark that the consequences areoftwo kinds,those which affect the persons directlyengaged in atransaction, and those which affect others beyond those immediatelyconcerned. In this distinctionwefind the germ of the distinction between the privateand the public. When indirect consequences arerec- ognized and thereiseffort to regulatethem, somethinghavingthe traits of astate comes into . (Dewey 1927,244)

This distinction givesalay of the land in which problems of global justice and global ethics are embedded: the fact that some of our actions impact on others, even if this is in amediated and indirect manner, generates awide-rangingand inclusive field of interaction in which there is aneed for individual actions (and thus their consequences) to be regulated. Iamlessconcerned here with Dewey’s notion thatthis bringsabout alreadysomething similar to “astate”.The estab- lishmentofajoint interactional sphere—in which there is mutualinfluence, the consequences of which are perceivable, and hence at least some effort is 122 Pragmatism made to regulate individual actions—is sufficient.Dewey further specifies “the public” by stating that it “consists of all those who are affected by the indirect consequences of transactions to such an extent thatitisdeemed necessary to have thoseconsequences systematicallycared for” (Dewey 1927,245 – 246). Such adefinition of “the public” as unconstrained by nationalboundaries is of fundamental importance to my purpose here. The relevant form of apublicis created by the interactions and relationships between agents; and particularlyso when the impact of some agent’saction on others is harmful or damaging.¹⁴⁸ Dewey defends auniversal egalitarianism when he assumesthat all persons mat- ter equally, since “other persons are selvestoo” and “the good is the same in wherever it is found” (Dewey 1922, 202).All this points to apotentially global scope of the Deweyan public—albeit one comprised of several subsets of particularlyintense interaction and influence. Dewey can plausiblyberegarded as a “relational egalitarian” for the combi- of his commitment to aglobal public, constituted by the relations and in- teractions between people, and his commitment to the equal moral importance of all.¹⁴⁹ Anderson, for example, ascribes to Dewey the idea “that afreesociety of equals is asociety of mutuallyaccountable individuals who regulate their claims on one another accordingtoprinciples thatexpress and sustain their social equality” (Anderson 2010b, 3, fn. 4).¹⁵⁰ And Dewey himself writes,inthe context of an earlydefense of an Ethics of Democracy, “Thetruemeaning of equalityis synonymous with the definition of democracy […]. It is the form of society in which every man has achance and knows that he has it—and we mayadd, a chance to which no possible limits can be put,achance which is trulyinfinite, the chance to become aperson. Equality,inshort, is the of humanity; an ideal in the of which democracy livesand moves.” (Dewey 1888, 246).

 As Iargued above, in chaptertwo,also abstainingfromcertain (inter‐)actions can be of moral relevance.  Cf. chapters one and twoabove.  Cf. Young, in asimilar ,onthe link between individual experiences with the complex- ities of asocial life and the need for a ‘democratic’ engagement amongequals: “We makeour moral and political ,then, not onlybytakingaccount of one another’sinterests and perspectives, but also by consideringthe social processesand relationships that lie between us and which we have come to know together by discussingthe world. […] Just because social life consists of pluralexperiences and perspectives, atheory of communica- tive ethics must endorsearadicallydemocratic conception of moral and political . Normative judgement is best understood as the product of dialogueunder conditions of equality and mutual respect.Ideally, the outcome of such dialogueand judgement is just and legitimate onlyifall the affected perspectiveshaveavoice” (Young 1997, 59). From criterial to pragmatic pluralism 123

Dewey’sclaim about the role of the ideal of democracy can also bear on the ideal of moral : democratic ideas and ideals should, he claims, translate into “apersonal,anindividual, wayoflife,” which includes “the pos- session and continual use of certain attitudes, forming personal character and determiningdesire and purpose in all the relations of life. Instead of thinking of our own dispositions and habits as accommodatedtocertain we have to learn to think of the latter as expressions,projections and extensions of habituallydominant personal attitudes” (Dewey 1939,226). This is as impor- tant in adomesticasinthe globalsetting.¹⁵¹ In the balance of this shortchapter,Ihope to draw attention to certain key features of the (neo‐)pragmatist tradition that appear to me to be helpful with regard to the project of contributing to atheory of global ethics by developing amore nuanced understandingofmoral cosmopolitanism which can serveas the coreofsuch an ethics. Yet, all this is meant onlyasamodest proposal. Noth- ing hingesonthe distinctive historic influenceofthe pragmatist tradition when it comes to assessing whether the Idevelop in later parts of this book are sound.

2Fromcriterial monism to pragmatic pluralism

Before illustrating the distinctively pragmatic approach to ethics thatunderlies my account of acosmopolitan ethos, it is important to sketch what could be con- sidered the ‘standard view’ of ethics, and to identify some of its troublesome fea- tures that motivated the earlypragmatists’ efforts to define an alternative view. The features of the ‘standard view’ are still very widespread in modern philo- sophical ethics, even if they are often held more implicitly than defendedexplic- itly.¹⁵² The coreofthe pragmatic criticism of the standard view in ethics is that it understands moral theories to be “about abstract structures that sort agents, ac- tions, or outcomes into appropriate categories” (Jamieson 1991, 477). The job of the philosopher or moraltheorist within this view is to “make particularmoral theories explicit,todescribe their universality,and to make vivid their coercive

 Cf. also Green (2011, 61– 62).  Amongothers, Kitcher has distinguished such two different “visions in normativeethics” (Kitcher 2011,285 – 288), one beingwhat Icall the ‘standardview,’ the other the pragmatist al- ternative (cf. also LaFollette2000). Asimilar critique to the one developped hereonpragmatist terms has been suggestedbyHutchings, whobuilds on resources fromvirtue ethics,feminist eth- ics and postmodernist for her account of global ethics (Hutchings2018). 124 Pragmatism power” (ibid.). Often, asingle basic moralprinciple is identifiedthat functionsas the morallyrelevant criterion; for example the categorical imperative or the prin- ciple of utility.Such “criterial” views establish the relevanceofaparticularper- spective (or ) for moralthinkingatthe cost of other morallysalient as- pects with the promise of aconclusive,transcendental account of .Such an approach to making ethical judgements can be described as top-down, or the direct application of abstract theory to concrete problems (Arras 2010): theory comes first,and then in asecond step it is applied to concrete moral problems to yield justified moral judgements. Such universalistic, criterial moral theories standardlyassume—in one way or another—that their morallyrelevant criteria are logicallyprior,fixed, com- plete, and directlyapplicable (LaFollette 2000,401). LaFollette pointedlyillus- tratesthe assumption, using as an example:

Although the of utility might be revealed through experience, its truth is thought (a) to be logicallyprior to experience and (b)toprovide ameasurefor determiningwhat is moral for all people,atall .Moreover,this principle (c) does not need to be supple- mented, and (d) can be directlyapplied to specific cases.(LaFollette2000,401)

Problems with moral theories of this criterial type are at least threefold. First,the standard view is based on de-contextual thinking,wherein moral principles are deduced from “pure” thought and under idealised circumstances, rather than de- velopedfrom real world situations and plausible approachestotheir ameliora- tion. This transcendental approach relies on forms of ideal theory thatare fre- quentlyrather remote from, and even alien to, the problems people face in real life. Second, the standard view does not allow for amendment or correction. Itscriteria are static, and are by definition foreverright and thus inflexible and never evolving.All alternative ways of reasoning are hence neglectedand ex- cluded as being morallyirrelevant.But if there remains, as there does,always the possibilitythat atheory has it partlyorwhollywrong (), yet amendments and corrections are ruled out by it,these theories reveal themselves to inhabit the realm of dogmatic absolutist ideological thinking. Third, theories of the standard view type are (most often) incapable of applying their theoretical insights to real world situations in away that actually helps agents to solve the moral problems at hand. Instead, amoral method thatisboth intellectuallyand practicallyresponsible should not relyonamonistic standard of moral judgment but integrate the complexity of the initial challengeinto the moral method. In addition to these fundamental internal problems that plague all variants of the standard view,the incommensurability of competingcriterial views causes even more problems for such theories. What could one provide to adhere Elements of apragmatic ethics 125 to only one or the other of saydeontology and , for example? Shouldone not aspire to put the different available tools to use when it comes to understandingthe moralcomplexities of right and wrong? Dewey pointedlysummarises the net effect of these objections against stan- dard moral theory and starts to identify an alternatieapproach:

Moral theory cannot emerge when thereispositive as to what is right and what is wrong,for then thereisnooccasion for reflection. It emergeswhen men are confronted with situations in which different desirespromise opposed and in which incompat- ible courses of action seem to be morallyjustified. Onlysuch aconflict of good ends and of standards and rules for right and wrong calls forth personal intothe bases of mo- rals. (Dewey and Tufts 1932, 164)

Dewey here embeds moral theorisinginconcrete circumstances in which agents, confronted with challenges in theirown personal experience,havetomake up their minds about what to do. Applying one single type of moral consideration, as stipulated by all the standard moral theories, shutsout entirelythe insights offered by the others. From apragmatic ethical perspective,such thinkingis too narrow,too constrained to single criteria assessment,inorder to be of any actual use in the making of moral evaluations in response to complex moral problems.Because of their complexity,the moral challenges almostinvariably have different salient facets so that onlyaplurality of normative perspectives will be able to capturethem.¹⁵³

3Elementsofapragmatic ethics

In the following section Ipoint out four keyelements of apragmatic ethics, as suggested in the writingsofDewey:the role of individual experience,apragmat- ic focus on acts and habits,adistinctive pragmatic methodofinquiry and abe- lief in the possibility of progress. (1) Theroleofindividual experience. The “ordinary experience” of people lies at the centreofDewey’sphilosophy(cf. Jung 2014). Experiencesare an anthro-

 The task for pragmatists consists not in integratingalternative criterial views intoone which is consideredtobefundamental,asitisundertaken in the attempts to “consequentialise” moral theories (Portmore2007) or to stipulatea“threshold deontology” (Alexander 2010). Such approaches retain their distinctive theoretical affiliation to consequentialism or deontology re- spectively.From apragmatic perspective the different types of moral should, however, be considered as genuinelydifferent, “independent factors” in morality (Dewey 1930), requiring thus for agenuine plurality in normativeperspectives. 126 Pragmatism pological universaland as such fundamental to the human existence. Experi- ence is the bridgebetween individual persons and the worldaround them.InEx- perience and Nature,Dewey analyses in great detail the intricate relationship be- tween mind and world, and shows the relevanceofexperienceinmany dimensions of human lives—such as in art,inscience,and in society (Dewey 1925). Dewey’snotion of “experience” is immenselyrich and in the present con- text Ican onlyshedsome light on the role of experience in the realm of human action.Starting from the experience of people matters in several different ways for the present exploration of cosmopolitan responsibility. The complex experi- ence of deprivation, disadvantage,oppression, etc. lies at the origin of what causes moral concern; the experience of irritation and uncertainty about how to respond to such triggers of moralconcern shapes the situation of all those who become aware of it and could be doing something about it.Concretely, ac- cording to Dewey,the triggerfor doing ethics is the experience of conflict,of “being torn between twoduties,” such as of having to “make achoice between competingmoral loyalties and convictions,” often because of aconflictbetween “incompatible values” (Dewey and Tufts 1932,165). Thisdistinctive moral expe- rience is initiallycharacterised by uncertainty and irritation, it disruptsthe usual orientation guiding an agent’shabitual conduct,and thereby, for Dewey,calls for moral “inquiry”.Onthe role of moral theory with regard to the experience of conflicts,Dewey writes:

Moral theory can (i) generalize the types of moral conflicts which arise, thus enablingaper- plexed and doubtful individual to clarify his own particular problem by placingitinalarg- er context;itcan (ii) statethe leadingwaysinwhich such problems have been intellectually dealtwith by those whohavethoughtupon such matters; it can (iii) render personal reflec- tion moresystematicand enlightened, suggestingalternativesthat might otherwise be over- looked, and stimulatinggreaterconsistencyinjudgment.(Dewey and Tufts 1932, 166)

It is important to stress that,for Dewey,the experiences that call for moralanal- ysis are ordinary experiencesofagents going about their lives, affected by some state of affairs (Pappas 1998, 102–104,Jung 2014). Dewey further stipulates that the means for dealing with identifiedproblems can also be found with the help of such ordinary experience: the three abilitiesofmoral theories quoted above do not resultfrom esoteric expert and competencies; rather,they are based in the ordinary capacities of ordinary people in ordinary circumstan- ces.¹⁵⁴ Dewey argues thatwithin an appropriate institutional framework, ordina-

 Kitcher has,followingDewey,questioned the need for or existencespecial ethical expertise Elements of apragmatic ethics 127 ry citizens (equipped with qualitative resources stemmingfrom their experien- ces) are fullycapable of deliberation about complex moral and social issues.¹⁵⁵ (2) Acts and habits. Moral actionisonlyrarelythe resultofabstract rational deliberation; most often, it is embedded in collective as well as individual habits, which are mostlypre-conscious. This is not meant to downplaythe role of reflex- ivity and reason, but its importance for most of an agent’s(moral) actions must not be overestimated. ForDewey,reason standardlydoes not precede moralac- tion but reason is onlydeployed in problematic situations to help shape the for- mationofnew,intelligent (as opposed to unreflected) conduct that mayturn into habit over . Consequently, apragmatic ethics focusses generallymuch less on single acts and more on patterns of action, which are called habits (Dewey 1922).Habits are dispositions to respond to certain stimuli in aspecific wayand most often our acts, no matterwhether they are of aparticularmoral quality or take place out- side of the moral realm, are shaped by habits. These habits mirror our commit- ments as well as the expectations of our social environment.The importantin- sight underlying the focus on habit is that habitual action is executed in a stable wayand with little, if any, reflective effort.Wejust act and do not have to engageintime- and energy-consumingreflection before we do so. Habits shape our conduct as long as they are not perceivedtobeproblematic, but in some situations agents start to experience frictions and the formerlyunques- tioned patterns of behaviour fail to satisfy.Here, areconsideration and restruc- turing of one’shabits becomes necessary—not onlyaone time execution of adif- ferent type of action.¹⁵⁶ Thus, the central question of pragmatic ethics is not the narrow ‘what action should Itake?’ but ‘what habit is appropriate for addressing problems of this type, how can it be developed, and how can it be incorporated as the stable fu- ture of conduct?’ (cf. Hildebrand 2008, 68). Analysingaconcrete, single chal- lengeabout what to do in agiven situation onlyserves as aproxy for addressing ageneral problem. And if the solution to the problem at hand is found and suc- cessfullyenacted, this counts in favour of acting alike in similar situations. Here is an example: Should one come to the conclusion that it is morallydemanded to donate some percentageofone’sdisposable income to ,itisnot enough

that goes beyond what “ordinary” citizens can do guided by an intelligent method of ethical in- quiry (Kitcher 2001,2011).  Cf. Cochran whoexplains how for Dewey “apublic is an instrument throughwhich prob- lem-solvingissociallycoordinated” (Cochran 2010,325).  In this regard, Dewey agrees with who, in Nicomachean Ethics,argued that “one swallow does not make asummer” (Aristotle NE, 1098a17). 128 Pragmatism to donate once. Forasingle such act does not sufficientlyaddress the relevant ethical challenge, which deals with patterns of (inter‐)action. Ethics for Dewey is not about one-off choices,but about forming stable character traits, dispositions to act in acertain way, for the origin of manyofthe social prob- lems—also and particularlyinthe context of global structuralinjustice—do not result from single acts but from repeated acts and patterns of action that re- sult from morallyproblematic habits. Since the single individual act alone is too meagretobring about lasting change, onlychangeinthe habits can.¹⁵⁷ This point demonstrates how apragmatist ethics takes an important interest in the entire character of the person who is acting,rather than in individual acts alone. Pragmatists emphasise the importance of persons acting as the person they wanttobecome alsointhe light of theirconsidered moral judgements. As Dewey has it:

it is proper to saythat in choosingthis object rather than that,one is in choosing what kind of person or self one is goingtobe. Superficially, the deliberation which termi- natesinchoiceisconcerned with weighingthe values of particular ends.Below the surface, it is aprocess of discoveringwhatsort of beingaperson most wants to become. (Dewey and Tufts 1932, 287)

Concretely, acts are hence on the one hand voluntary consequences of knowing and choosing,and, as such, are also contributions to and expressions of arather stable yetconstantlyevolving character (Dewey and Tufts 1932, 166,167). In this light,evenseemingly trivial acts—the everydayacts we perform withoutany ex- plicit decisions— agreat deal morally, since they result from character. Dewey specifies: “If we omitted from our estimate of moral character all the deeds done in the performance of dailytasks, satisfaction of recurrent needs, meeting of responsibilities,each slight perhaps in itself but enormousin mass, morality would be aweak and sicklything indeed.” Hence: “Such acts, non-moral in isolation, derivemoral significance from the ends to which they lead” (Dewey and Tufts 1932, 168). Generally, the pragmatist perspective thus places significant weight on the relatively stable dispositions of people to respond in certain situations with a specific sort of action. Identifying and then cultivatingthe right kind of disposi- tion—alsothrough intelligent structuringofthe social and factual environment

 “Our moral measurefor estimatingany existingarrangement or anyproposed reform is its effect upon impulse and habits. Does it liberate or suppress,ossify or render flexible, divide or unify interest?” (Dewey1922, 202). Elements of apragmatic ethics 129 of an agent or agroup in order to support the considered habit—is an important goal of pragmatic ethics. (3) Method of inquiry. In order to address aproblem, to find out how to act and which habits to form, Dewey advocates apluralist method of inquiry.This method,that is applicable alsotothe realm of ethics, was originallydeveloped to analyse and guide the process of solving problems in the context of the scien- ces (Dewey 1938, 105–122).Inquiry is for Dewey,a“rule governedactivity—an activity of developing hypotheses, predictions,and ; of assessing what is to count as for or against ahypothesis or prediction; of decid- ing which explanations should be adopted and acted upon” (Misak 2013,129). What are the steps of this sort of—moral—inquiry for Dewey?First,anagent experiencessome general unease in asituation, adiffuseirritation, without being able to concretelydelineate the sourceofthat feeling.The second step con- sists in attemptingtoidentify and specify exactlythe concrete problem that is so vexing. This step is particularlyimportant,since often it is unclear what exactly was at the origin of the initial experience of unease and irritation. This second step is for Dewey alreadyexperimental, insofar as it is by definition tentative,al- ways open to further revision. The third step consists in consideringone or sev- eral possiblesolutions thatmay promise to overcome the initial confusion. After this heuristic step, the next one consists in experimentallyimaginingthe impli- cationsofthe candidate solutions by predictingand comparingtheirdifferent multidimensional consequences and implications. This is the point at which Dewey proposes to use conventional moralphilosophical principles: He ac- knowledgesthat these principles and rules contain important ethical knowledge that should be taken into consideration when it comestoanticipating the impli- cationsofcertain acts. It is onlythe last,fifth step, that leads to actual action performedbythedeliberating agent.Action, however,isalso experimental and as such provisional. Onlyafter acting does it become possibletoassess the factual consequences and implications of an act.The experiencesgained by actual action become, in turn, crucial for orienting actions in analo- gous circumstances. If such actions are positively assessed, they mayasaresult contributetothe formation of ahelpful habit. To locate vexing problems and identify(moral) conflicts, it is essential to be able to identify and to name the respective values that mayclash.Interestingly, as Ipointed out,the existing moral principles can function here as heuristic tools in the moral inquiry,evenfor pragmatists.However,the “all toohuman loveofcertainty” (Dewey 1922, 242) should not lead to the isolation of principles from empirical investigations which acknowledge the contingency of concrete 130 Pragmatism situations. Forpragmatists,principles are onlyindispensable empirical general- isations in need of aconstant readjustment to changingconditions.¹⁵⁸ This is onlythe roughest sketch of what Dewey has spelled out in his and Iwill not discuss it further.¹⁵⁹ It remains simplytobestated that much of the work Iwill undertakeinlaterchapters is best understood as contributingtothe second and third steps of Dewey’spragmatic moralmethod: Iattempt to locate the problem, and then to reveal the conflictingvalues that gave rise to the initial- ly diffuseexperience of irritation, the “healthydissatisfaction with the familiar,” as Nagel has called it (Nagel 1991, 8). (4) Thepossibility of progress. Iwould like to conclude this brief introduction to pragmatic ethics with awordonthe role of ideals and ends. In pragmatism, and particularlyinDewey’sversion, one finds asophisticatedaccount of melio- rism, perfectionism and progress.The fundamental idea of pragmatic progress, however,isnot one of teleological progress wherehumanitywould constantly getcloser to some fixed ideal end state.Instead, progress is understood in prag- matic terms:itconsists in (evolutionary,not necessarilyrevolutionary) incremen- tal improvements of the human capacities to live togetherbyovercoming limita- tions and problems.Thiscan occur in the form of progress in our abilities to reason about the relevant challenges at hand and, of cours,importantlyalso of progress ‘in practice’,inthe form of improved individual behaviour or politi- cal and institutional reform.Pragmatic progress hence does not have to be un- derstood as progress to some ideal, but as progress from an imperfect and prob- lematic status quo(Kitcher 2011, 288, Kitcher 2016).¹⁶⁰ Forits belief in the possibility of achieving meaningful progress,pragmatism can also be called a “philosophyofhope.” It truststhat thoughtful inquiry and the joint search for solutions in acooperative, multi-perspective effort can ac- tuallyhelp make thingsbetter (Rondel2018, xii). Defending the possibility of progress in this sense amounts to the optimistic assumption that solutions to so- cial problems can eventuallybefound, despite the fact thatcurrentlyavailable

 Cf. also Hildebrand: “Dewey promotes the capacity of pragmatic moral inquiry to sort out the natureofaproblem and its possible solutions. Inquiry also has the ability to reconsider and reconstruct even the moral values and ends at stake, questioningthe purposes people use to direct their conduct,and whysuch purposes aregood […]. Moral inquiry not onlydiscovers mor- ality,itmakes it” (Hildebrand 2008, 79).  But cf. also Hildebrand (2008, 53 – 58) and Heilinger (2016a, 155–158) for amoredetailed presentation. Foracritical take on the transfer of Dewey’sgeneral method of inquiry to the field of ethics,cf. Grimm (2010,120).  Sen, for example, has distinguished in asimilar wayhis own “comparative,”“non-ideal” approach to justice from Rawls’s “transcendental,”“ideal” approach(Sen 2009). The roleofphilosophy 131 patterns of thinkingand actionfall short of providing them. The rejection of both the possibility of, and the need for,perfect,complete, converging and final an- swers—an imaginary accordingtoDewey and his followers—is what per- mits this confidenceinthe never-ending search for stepwise improvements.¹⁶¹

4The role of philosophy

With regard to the present problems of global injusticeand global inequality, what is the role of philosophy? Mightn’titbejust plainlyabsurdtoturn to phi- losophers for answers to such urgent and pressingethical questions, and for sol- utions to the unknown challenges that layahead?Inasense,itishard to disa- gree with such asuggestion, for several reasons.First,philosophyisnot directly concerned with practical solutions to concrete problems.Itwould be follytoturn to aphilosopher quaphilosopher in order to identify what exactlyshould be done by whom, for example, to fight food shortages or drought and starvation in aparticular regionofthe world. have few skills related to such matters;vast amountsofempirical knowledge are needed that they gener- allydonot possess. Secondly, it would be similarlyabsurdtoturn to philoso- phers alone with an expectation of receiving conclusive answers even to the con- ceptual theoretical questions (such as about how responsibilityshould be distributed or which social and political institutions should generallyexist on the global level) in which philosophers do specialise, and for which they do pos- sess pertinent skills,ortoexpect philosophytodecree solutions to acute chal-

 Ifind these ideas helpfully spelled out in Moody-Adams’swork on TheIdeaofMoral Prog- ress which also stands in apragmatist tradition (Moody‐Adams 1999). She distinguishes be- tween twoforms of ,one beingmoral progress “in belief” the other moral prog- ress “in practices”.The former consists in adeepened understanding of particular moral ,such as equality or justice; the latter consists in bringingsuch newlydeepened moral understandingtoinfluenceindividual behaviour or shape social institutions. In both cases,asMoody-Adams points out,progress is local, i.e. it always proceeds by departing from and improvingupon agiven status quo. The willingness and ability for critical self-scrutiny of numbers of individuals is acondition sine qua non for actual progress in practice, yet, on her view,academic philosophyand progress “in beliefs” alone will onlyhaveavery limited impact here. Even the important “advocacyofengaged moral inquirers” whoput to use “the richness and complexity of their conceptions of rationality and rational ”,can be successful onlyifthe “main obstacletomoral progress in social practices” is overcome:the tendencyto “widespread affected ignorance of what can and should alreadybeknown”.Yet,such self-scru- tinyinanexaminedlife is frequentlyavoided, particularlyifpeople “expect it to yield insights that [they] arenot preparedtoobey” (180). 132 Pragmatism lenges. Here, abroader cooperationinvolving others—politicians, political and social scientists, and the public—is needed. Nevertheless,philosophers can and should playadistinctive role in the con- text of cosmopolitan and otherethical challenges. But not for their specific eth- ical knowledge,nor for their ability to provide answers and solutions.Instead, the role of philosophyismore modest.For Kitcher—and others, includingSocra- tes—philosophyshould be understood to provide aform of dialectic midwifery:

Philosophers can make proposals,attempting to facilitatethe conversation that would de- liveranswers.[…]The most obvious forms of philosophical midwifery consist in proposing topics for consideration (places on our common vessel where planks might deserveatten- tion) and suggestions about those topics (specific ways of rearrangingthe timber in those places). (Kitcher 2011,370)

The allusion to Otto Neurath’scomparison of the epistemologicalchallengeof improvingknowledge with sailors constantlyrebuildingthe vessel on which they sail, underlines the anti-foundationalviews of pragmatism: the constructive role of philosopherslies primarily in acareful contribution to identifying worth- while topics and facilitation of processes for discussing them. Prior ethical knowledge can help here, but it is not on the grounds of such ethical knowledge that answers to new challenges will be found. The role of philosophyasmidwifery hence consists mostlyinbringingcer- tain ideas into the conversation, in explaining,exploring,developing,and nur- turing them, so that they matter for ongoing challenges and debates and are alive and available to be put to use when the time is ripe. Implicit in understanding philosophyasdialectic midwifery is the view that philosophyisnosingle man or woman’swork, but ajoint undertaking,anever- ending pursuit to improvethe status quo.What is necessary to deal appropriately with the challenges at hand is acoordinated and socially embeddedapproach. Philosophers contribute to it,but philosophersalone are in no wayableorex- pected to provide definitive solutions.Progress can onlyoccur in incremental steps,and, if it takes place at all, thatwill be because certain ideas and solutions gain broad acceptance: truth then, to quote James again, happens to an idea (James 1909,574). Such apursuit,toimprovethe human lot, is not an elitist proj- ect,but an inclusive and collaborativeone involving all, and all on equal terms. , in apragmatic understanding,isnot afeature of individuals but a cooperativepraxis. If there are intelligent solutions to problems,they cannot but be found experimentallyand cooperatively.Prior established knowledge alone, be it philosophical or scientific, is insufficient. It is in this spirit that Iwill pursue my reasoninginthis book.Central ideas— equality, impartiality,, and responsibility—are here understood as tools for The roleofphilosophy 133 tackling the problems of acosmopolitan scope. The minor contribution Ihope to make to largerrelateddebates will consist of scrutinisingphilosophical ideas in order to assess their meaning and relevance in the context of aglobal ethics. If these ideas are helpful, and if they gain somyacceptance among thoseaffect- ed¹⁶² by the problems at hand, they hold the potential to inform choicesand mo- tivateaction, both in individual agents and in . They are thus present- ed here as potential part of the largerproject of finding better ways for humans to live together. This shortchapter wasmeant to provide an for how Icame to hold some of the views underlying the reasoninginthe following chapters, namelythe views that moralityisanongoing, collective social undertaking in which the experiences of all individuals matter and in which all thosewho are affected should have an equal sayinthe matter;that attemptingtofind so- lutions for contemporary challenges of global justiceand global ethics will re- quire aplurality of moral standards,since onlysuch aphilosophicalbuffet will be sufficient to capture the manyethical dimensions of the many complex social problems at issue; thatmoral progress,inthe sense of an improved social practice, is actuallypossible, most likelyasincremental progress that builds upon actual experiences bothpositive and negative and abetter understanding of the normative concepts employed; and that the progressive changewill be ad- vanced by people comingjointlytoholdcertain views and to endorse acertain type of ethos that promotes coordinated, collective action and institutional, sys- temic change. Furthermore, acting togethercan function as an external social scaffold which promotes and supports the newlyacquired, intelligent habits by ultimatelytaking the psychological burden of acting in unusual ways from the shoulders of individual agents. On apragmatic account it is not necessary to spellout how an ideal world would look like or to provide principles that,ifrespected, would make the world perfectlyjust.But it is necessary and possible to identify instances in which the livesofmanypeople are hindered by removable, social obstaclesthatprevent them from pursuing their lives. Domination and exclusion from participating in the social processes that influencetheir livesare among them. Here, achange in the habits of the more powerful,whose behaviour,evenifwithout malevolent intent,frequentlyisatthe origin of such and domination, is ur- gentlyneeded. Apragmatic ethics can hint towards changes in acts and habits of individuals, and subsequentlyalso towards social reform, thatwould count as

 In the present context of our globalised world, arguably all areaffected in one wayorthe other,asagents,patients,disadvantagedoradvantagedetc. 134 Pragmatism progressive insofar as more people will be enabled to live as equals in the global order.

This chapter has introducedapragmatic perspective as the third central charac- teristic of my proposed theory of cosmopolitan responsibility. Conceiving of hu- mans as citizens of the world thatmorallyought to relatetoand interact with one another as moral equals is not primarilyatheoretical exercise, but has adis- tinctively practical side to it.This side can be captured well from apragmatic perspective:the normative commitments we have,plural as they maybe, should support the living togetherofall humans by shaping alsoindividual habits and patterns of action.Without an ambition to discover moral truth, but in search of solutions to practical problems thatappear in the living together of humans,the pragmatic side of cosmopolitan responsibility offers guidance for action and the formationofhabits,and points towards the need and the possibility to make cos- mopolitanismapersonal wayoflife.