California S·Tate University, Northridge in GEOGRAPHY a Thesis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

California S·Tate University, Northridge in GEOGRAPHY a Thesis California s·tate University, Northridge EPIST~10LOGICAL ~JCERTAINTY IN GEOGRAPHY A thesis submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Geography by Glen David Dalton January, 1980 The Thesis of G. David Dalton is approved: f~obert Hoffpaui \ Gordon.tr. Lewthwai te, Committee Chairman California State University, Northridge ii DEDICATION To my father, Glen Deavers Dalton, in whose footsteps I humbly follow. iii ACKNOWLEDGE~ffiNTS I wish to thank my committee, Dr. Gordon R. Lewthwaite, Dr. Robert Hoffpauir, and Dr. Sidney Luckenbach, for their long and painstaking efforts in the drafting of this thesis. To Dr. W. Timothy Dagodag I give spe­ cial gratitude for always being there and for being the person he is. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Page DEDICATION ........ ~ . • . iii ACKNO~EDGE:r.fEN'rS •••••••••••••••••••••••••-. • • • • • i v ABSTF..ACT . • • • • . • • . • . • . • • • . • . • . • • • vii Chapter I INTRODUCTION . 1 II QUANTITATIVE REVOLUTION .•...••••..••••• 16 a. Introduction ....................... 17 b. Pre-Revolution ..............•....•.• 18 c. Quantitative Revolution ..•.•.....•.. 22 d. Conclusion ......................... 32 e. Footnotes .......................... 33 III LOGICAL POSITIVISM .•.•...••...•..•.••.• 38 a. In troduc ti on ....................... 39 b. History ............................ 40 c. Tenets ............................. 44 d. Judgements ......................... 48 e. Reasons for Failure •....•.•........• 50 f. Conclusion .......................... 56 g. Footnotes .......... ·· ............... 59 IV UNCERTAINTY ....•...........•.....•..... 63 a. In troduc ti on ....................... 64 b. Truth .............................. 67 c. GOdel ............................... 70 d. Imperfect Justification of Kno-v:1edge Claims . ~ ........................... 72 e. Foundations ......................... 82 f. Empiricism Under Fire •.•.•...•..•..• 86 g.. New Directions ...•...•.•.•....•••••• 90 h. Co:t1.clusion ...................... ~ .. 100 i. Footnotes 103 v CONTE!J'.uDORARY GEOGRAPHY ••...•.•.•....••• 108 a. Introduction ....................... 109 b. Problems ........................... 109 c. Solutions .......................... 118 d. Conclusion ................... "' ..... 132 v e. Footnotes 134 VI CONCLUSION • • • • • • • • • • • • • • • 4 • • • • • ~ • • • • • • • • • • • 138 BIBLIOGRAPHY 143 vi I ABSTRACT EPISTEMOLOGICAL UNCERTAINTY IN GEOGRAPHY by Glen David Dalton Master of Arts in Geography Contemporary epistemology yields uncertainty for the foun.dations of our knowledge. The quantitative revolution in geography developed problems when it strove for certain­ ty under the defunct epistemology of logical positivism. Logical positivism, both implicitly and explicitly espoused during the revolution, required verification (later, strict confirmation) of knowledge claims. Any claim that could not meet these criteria would be outside the realm of science and, hence, not cognitively significant. The tenets of logical positivism, however, were soon recogniz­ ed as being too strict. Even the founders of logical posi­ tivism advanced to other positions as it was shown through epistemology, logic, and science that verification and strict confirmation are not possible and that uncertainty is pervasive. Tarski showed that truth is a semantic function, not applicable to real-world claims. Godel sho"llred that any rich axiomatic system is incomplete. vii . I Modern neuropsychology and neurophysiology indicate that . I perception is a process which depends upon the autobiogra- phy of the individual perceiver for its context instead of an unambiguous 11 camera click 11 on a blank state. Thus, the empiricism of logical positivism is shown to be based on the false hope of certainty where none is known to exist. Problems in contemporary geography arise from reliance on the certainty of old epistemology, thus relegating some legitimate geographical studies to so-called pseudo- science. The abandonment of logical positivism for cur- rent epistemology will broaden the spectrum of what geogra­ phers can do. - viii p ' "It is not the function of the geographer to write philosophy; but if he aspires to be more than a competent routine techni­ cian, it is certainly one of his responsi­ bilities at least to be aware of philo­ sophical problems which may bear upon his \'IOrk. nl O.H.K. Spate CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION 1 2 This thesis is concerned with current problems of fundamental philosophical import arising out of the quantitative revolution in geography in the 1950's. The emplo~~ent of the methodology and techniques of the quantitative revolution is valid only insofar as the more fundamental questions of how and what we can come to know are understood. These fundamental questions deal with theory of knowledge, or epistemology. Thus, the scope of this thesis is the intersection of geography and philosophy at the point where these epistemological questions of how and what 'VIe can come to know are raised. Through the millenia, fundamental questions concern­ ing the quest for knowledge have been debated by philo­ sophers. Various theories of knovrledge have been proposed, becoming more and more coherent with scientific theories in recent centuries, especially in the past generation. Thus, if our knowledge builds at all, epistemology builds and progresses in the manner that disciplines such as physics, neurophysiology, and psychology do. Empiricism is a broad epistemological world-vie~w~~~~~~~­ which has been modified to yield contemporary logical empiricism, logical positivism, and nineteenth century positivism, among other offshoots of the main body of emptricism. Logical positivism, of special interest to us, 3 appeared in the first half of this century and is nO\'/ a dead issue among philosophers of science. It is logical positivism, however, that has become the explicit and implicit philosophical basis of the quantitative revolution. As late as 1975 Amedee and Golledge, .for instance, claim that "since about 1954, scientific work in geography has been almost exclusively logical positivism. Thus we describe what has overwhelm­ i.ngly prevailed in the discipline's recent history. n2 A decade earlier, however, the philosopher Karl Popper had said that "positivism is out of date science ..•. 11 3 A gen­ eration earlier logical positivism had met its demise. Thus, the quantitative revolution, to the extent that it relies on logical positivism, is not viablee The quantitative·revolution, in an attempt to make geography more scientific, ironically put its faith in an epistemological position that had been ignored by physic~ ists because of logical positivism's disastrous conse­ quences for scientific laws. Thus, today grave problems exist for geography both in that the use of sophisticated mathematics in geography is hindered by its association with logical positivism and also in that logical positivism would deny the value of any methodology but its own. Hence, an ideational4 approach in geography would be labeled as pseudo-science, hardly the view of current epistemology. There is great need, then, for geography to abandon logical positivism if it is not to be left alone among the disciplines. The solution to our problems with logical positivism would seem to lie in achieving an acquaintance with current epistemology, arrived at through discussions of (1) the errors during the quantitative revolution that led to our predicament in the first place; (2) the problems of logical positivism; (3) an indication of the great dif- ferences between logical positivism and contemporary epistemological thinking among philosophers of science and scientists; and (4) events in contemporary geography aris­ ing out of indifference to contemporary epistemology. Purpos~: The purpose of this thesis is to show the error of relying on logical positivism as the philosophical basis of geographical inquiry. In pointing out the problems of logical positivism it is hoped that two aims will be achieved: 1) that the use of mathematics in geography, freed from the onus of association with logical positivism, can be enhanced and 2) that the methodological restrictions imposed by logical positivism can be discarded. Although logical positivism is associated with the quantitative revolution, this thesis is not to be under­ stood a.s being critical of the use of mathematics in geography. On the contrary, it would seem that the employ- ment of .£lE£~ epistemological principles would enhance all aproaches to geographic inquiry. What is being criti­ cized in this thesis is the logical positivist position and 5 its exclusion of other approaches. In epistemology d•)Ubt has replaced the rigid tenets of logical positivism. It is hoped that by showing some of the areas of doubt in epistemology, geography can not only profit from a rejection of logical positivism, but also can avoid the trap of trying to catch up with physics, when in fact logical positivism was never accepted in physics. It is of the utmost importance to realize that logical positivism is not equivalent to science and that one does not entail the other. Science has existed through the ages, both before and after logical positivism's brief tenure in philosophy. Logical positivism would repeal the laws of nature or allow nonsense statements to become a part of the body of science, merely because of testing procedures designed to yield certainty where none can exist. It may be this hope for certainty that prompted some geographers to adopt an abandoned
Recommended publications
  • A Close Look at Bunge's Philosophy of Medicine
    philosophies Article Emergence and Evidence: A Close Look at Bunge’s Philosophy of Medicine Rainer J. Klement 1,* and Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay 2 1 Department of Radiation Oncology, Leopoldina Hospital Schweinfurt, Robert-Koch-Straße 10, 97422 Schweinfurt, Germany 2 Department of History & Philosophy, Montana State University, Bozeman, MT, 59717, USA * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +49-9721-7202761 Received: 26 June 2019; Accepted: 14 August 2019; Published: 20 August 2019 Abstract: In his book “Medical Philosophy: Conceptual issues in Medicine”, Mario Bunge provides a unique account of medical philosophy that is deeply rooted in a realist ontology he calls “systemism”. According to systemism, the world consists of systems and their parts, and systems possess emergent properties that their parts lack. Events within systems may form causes and effects that are constantly conjoined via particular mechanisms. Bunge supports the views of the evidence-based medicine movement that randomized controlled trials (RCTs) provide the best evidence to establish the truth of causal hypothesis; in fact, he argues that only RCTs have this ability. Here, we argue that Bunge neglects the important feature of patients being open systems which are in steady interaction with their environment. We show that accepting this feature leads to counter-intuitive consequences for his account of medical hypothesis testing. In particular, we point out that (i) the confirmation of hypotheses is inherently stochastic and affords a probabilistic account of both confirmation and evidence which we provide here; (ii) RCTs are neither necessary nor sufficient to establish the truth of a causal claim; (iii) testing of causal hypotheses requires taking into account background knowledge and the context within which an intervention is applied.
    [Show full text]
  • Physics and Philosophy of Physics in the Work of Mario Bunge
    Chapter 17 Physics and Philosophy of Physics in the Work of Mario Bunge Gustavo E. Romero Abstract This brief review of Mario Bunge’s research on physics begins with an analysis of his masterpiece Foundations of Physics, and then it discusses his other contributions to the philosophy of physics. Following that is a summary of his more recent reactions to scientific discoveries in physics and a discussion of his position about non-locality in quantum mechanics, as well as his changing opinions on the nature of spacetime. The paper ends with a brief assessment of Bunge’s legacy concerning the foundations of physics. 17.1 Introduction Before embarking on a more formal examination of Bunge’s work in philosophy, physics and the overlap of both, I would like to indulge in some personal narrative and reflect on the depth of influence which Mario Bunge has had on my career, as an example of how he has been a central figure in the work of so many others over many decades. Given the purpose of this paper and the context of its inclusion in a larger work recognizing the breadth and depth of his footprint across many fields, such a diversion does not seem misplaced. Following this background story, there is a brief summary of some of the major points in Mario’s own early life and academic career. This provides some context to the subsequent analysis of his works and his Cartesian approach to the development of a fundamental re-construction of the theory and practice of scientific methods. Mario Bunge began academic studies in physics in March 1938.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy Behind Pseudoscience
    SI J-A 2006 pgs 5/30/06 1:42 PM Page 29 The Philosophy behind Pseudoscience Every intellectual endeavor, whether authentic or bogus, has an underlying philosophy. Science, for example, involves six kinds of philosophical ideas. These differ totally from those behind pseudoscience. Evaluating a field’s underlying philosophy is a revealing way to make distinctions and judge worth. MARIO BUNGE SKEPTICAL INQUIRER July / August 2006 29 SI J-A 2006 pgs 5/30/06 1:42 PM Page 30 tions and torture sessions of political opponents during the osé López-Rega was the evil gray eminence behind 1973–76 period, when he was at the peak of his political General Perón in his dotage, as well as that of Perón’s power. Thus, El Brujo (“the Wizard”), as the Minister of Jsuccessor, his wife, Isabelita. He had been a failed singer, Public Welfare was popularly known, had the backing of mil- a police officer, a bodyguard, and the author of best sellers on lennia of philosophical myths. business and the stars, love and the stars, and the like. He was Every intellectual endeavor, whether authentic or bogus, a firm believer in the occult and a practicing black magician. has an underlying philosophy and, in particular, an ontology López-Rega believed not only in astral influences and in the (a theory of being and becoming) and an epistemology (a the- spirit world but also in his own ability to conjure up spirits ory of knowledge). For example, the philosophy behind evo- and manipulate them. Once, he attempted to transfer the soul lutionary biology is naturalism (or materialism) together with of the dead Juan Perón into his dim-witted successor, Isabelita.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Author Version (PDF)
    Chemistry Education Research and Practice Accepted Manuscript This is an Accepted Manuscript, which has been through the Royal Society of Chemistry peer review process and has been accepted for publication. Accepted Manuscripts are published online shortly after acceptance, before technical editing, formatting and proof reading. Using this free service, authors can make their results available to the community, in citable form, before we publish the edited article. We will replace this Accepted Manuscript with the edited and formatted Advance Article as soon as it is available. You can find more information about Accepted Manuscripts in the Information for Authors. Please note that technical editing may introduce minor changes to the text and/or graphics, which may alter content. The journal’s standard Terms & Conditions and the Ethical guidelines still apply. In no event shall the Royal Society of Chemistry be held responsible for any errors or omissions in this Accepted Manuscript or any consequences arising from the use of any information it contains. www.rsc.org/cerp Page 1 of 22 Chemistry Education Research and Practice 1 2 3 AN ONTOLOGICAL AND EPISTEMOLOGICAL ANALYSIS OF THE PRESENTATION OF THE 4 FIRST LAW OF THERMODYNAMICS IN SCHOOL AND UNIVERSITY TEXTBOOKS 5 6 Joaquín Castillo Poblete, Rocío Ogaz Rojas, Cristian Merino Rubilar and Waldo Quiroz Venegas* 7 8 9 Abstract 10 11 Considering the relevance of thermodynamics to the scientific discipline of chemistry and the 12 curriculum of the Western school system, the philosophical system of Mario Bunge, particularly his 13 ontology and epistemology, is used herein to analyze the presentation of the first law of 14 thermodynamics in 15 school and university textbooks.
    [Show full text]
  • A SCIENTIFIC ONTOLOGY* 1. Introduction in the Last Decades
    A SCIENTIFIC ONTOLOGY* 1. Introduction In the last decades, doing ontology or metaphysics has become a respectable business again, even on the Anglo-Saxon philosopbical scene. Professor Mario Bunge's system of ontological conceptions and theories fits into tbis trend. It fills two volumes (01, Oll), wbich form part of an ambitious seven-volume pro­ ject, bis Treatise on Basic Philosophy. It "encompasses what the author takes to be the nuc1eus of contemporary philosophy, namely semantics (theories of meaning and truth), epistemology (theories of knowledge), metaphysics (general theories of the world), and etbics (theories of value and of right ac­ tion)" (General Preface to the Treatise, e.g. 01 v). Together with the previously published volumes on semantics (SI, SII), four volumes are available so far. Spec­ ifically, Bunge's philosophy is meant to be "systematic and, to some extent, also exact and scientific. That is, the philosophical theories formulated in these vol­ umes are (a) formulated in certain exact (mathemacial) languages and (b) hoped to be consistent with contemporary science" (e.g. 01 v). The relationsbip between science and his ontological theories is intended to be especially tight: not only are they to be consistent with science, but "more­ over rather elose to science - or rather the bulk of it" (01 xiii). Tbis elose rela­ tionsbip is not a fanciful notion, but rather already present in the fact that "every scientific theory, if extermely general, is ontological; and every ontologi­ ca1 theory, if exact and in tune with science, is scientific" (01 21, also 15f.). 'Exact' and 'scientific' are not identified: "the latter implies the former but the converse is false" (01 8).
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Mario Bunge
    CURRICULUM VITAE OF MARIO BUNGE I. PERSONAL Born September 21, 1919, Buenos Aires, Argentina. Canadian citizen. Physics student, University of La Plata, 1938-44. Doctor of physico-mathematical sciences. University of La Plata, 1952. 2. FELLOWSHIPS AND A WARDS Fellow, Conselho Nacional de Pesquisas (Brazil), 1953. Fellow, Fundaci6n Ernesto Santa marina, Buenos Aires, 1954. Research Fellow, Alexander von Humboldt-Stiftung, Freiburg i. Br., 1965-66. Fellow, John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation, Aarhus and Zurich, 1972-73. Award of merit, University of Wisconsin (Green Bay), 1979. Doctor of Laws, honoris causa, Simon Fraser University, 1981. Guest of honor, symposium on 'Science and Philosophy in the Work of Mario Bunge', Pefiiscola, Spain, 1981. 3. POSITIONS HELD Founder and secretary general, later headmaster, Universidad Obrera Argentina, 1938-43. Teaching assistant, Experimental Physics, University of La Plata, 1941. Secretary general, Federaci6n Argentina de Sociedades Populares de Educacion, 1942-44. Teaching assistant, Mathematical Physics, University of Buenos Aires, 1947-52. Subdirector, Biophysics Laboratory, Direcci6n de Medicina Tecnol6gica, Ministerio de Salud Publica de la Naci6n, 1949. Lecturer, Inter American Course on Modern Physics organized by UNESCO, Univer- sidad Mayor de San Andres, La Paz, Bolivia, 1955. Lecturer, Physics Department and Instituto Pedagogico, Universidad de Chile, 1955. Editor, Asociaci6n Fisica Argentina, 1956-63. Assistant Professor of Theoretical Physics, University of Buenos Aires, 1956. Assistant Professor of Theoretical Physics, University of La Plata, 1956. Professor of Theoretical Physics, University of Buenos Aires, 1956-58. Professor of Theoretical Physics, University of La Plata, 1956-59. Professor of Philosophy, University of Buenos Aires, 1957-62. Councillor, Facultad de Filosofia y Letras, Universidad de Buenos Aires, 1958 Visiting Professor of Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania, 1960-61.
    [Show full text]
  • Mario Bunge: Physicist, Philosopher and Defender of Science1
    REVISTA ELECTRÓNICA DE INVESTIGACIÓN EN EDUCACIÓN EN CIENCIAS Mario Bunge: Physicist, philosopher and defender of science1 Mario Bunge: Físico, filósofo y defensor de la ciencia Michael R. Matthews School of Education, University of New South Wales, Sydney 2052, Australia Resumen Mario Bunge nació en Argentina el último año de la Primera Guerra Mundial. Aprendió física atómica y mecánica cuántica de un refugiado austriaco que había sido estudiante de Heisenberg. Adicionalmente, aprendió en forma autodidacta filosofía moderna en un entorno que era hostil. Fue el primer filósofo de la ciencia sudamericano con formación inicial en ciencias. Sus publicaciones en física, filosofía, psicología, sociología y fundamentos de la biología son sorprendentemente numerosas, e incluyen en extenso Tratado de Filosofía en ocho volúmenes. La línea unificadora de su producción es la constante y vigorosa defensa del Iluminismo, y la crítica a los movimientos culturales y académicos que niegan o devalúan sus fundamentos: su naturalismo, la búsqueda de la verdad, la universalidad de la ciencia, la racionalidad y el respeto por los individuos. En un tiempo en que se alaba ampliamente la especialización y son reconocidos sus efectos sobre la ciencia, la filosofía de la ciencia, la investigación educativa y la enseñanza de las ciencias, es saludable ver los frutos del empeño de una persona por construir una ‘gran’ imagen científica y filosófica. Abstract Mario Bunge was born in Argentina in the final year of the First World War. He learnt atomic physics and quantum mechanics from an Austrian refugee who had been a student of Heisenberg. Additionally he taught himself modern philosophy in an environment that was a philosophical backwater.
    [Show full text]
  • Mario Bunge's Philosophy of Mathematics: an Appraisal
    Sci & Educ DOI 10.1007/s11191-011-9409-5 Mario Bunge’s Philosophy of Mathematics: An Appraisal Jean-Pierre Marquis Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Abstract In this paper, I present and discuss critically the main elements of Mario Bunge’s philosophy of mathematics. In particular, I explore how mathematical knowledge is accounted for in Bunge’s systemic emergent materialism. To Mario, with gratitude. 1 Philosophy of Mathematics The philosophy of mathematics is mostly a collection of interesting open problems and of ill- grounded opinions. Moreover, it is fragmentary rather than systematic. What is worse, it is quite isolated from the other branches of philosophy; in particular, none of the well-known philosophies of mathematics is a component of a philosophical system consonant with contemporary mathematics and factual science. There is not even consensus on the problematics of the philosophy of mathe- matics. … In sum, philosophy of mathematics is in poor shape. Therefore it poses one of the most interesting and pressing challenges to any philosopher who is aware that the most advanced and exact of all sciences has the most backward, woolly and dogmatic of all philosophies. (Bunge 1985a, p. 17) This was written more than 25 years ago. I suspect that Bunge would probably make the same claim today. The traditional philosophies of mathematics, namely logicism, intuitionism and formalism, have taken new shapes under the name of neo-logicism, various schools of constructivism and, well, it is hard to say what formalism really amounted to in the first place, even today.1 What can still be said is that even the new variants are not part of philosophical systems and neo-logicism, despite its claims, is certainly not consonant with contemporary mathematics and factual science.
    [Show full text]
  • Piaget, Bunge, and the Future of General Philoso- Phy in Latin America
    ISSN: 1984-1655 PIAGET, BUNGE, AND THE FUTURE OF GENERAL PHILOSO- PHY IN LATIN AMERICA Tristan Guillermo Torriani1 Abstract The current state of Philosophy and the Humanities is widely acknowledged to be endangered. This historical essay addresses epistemological reasons and ins- titutional causes of this malaise in light of Piaget’s and Bunge’s scientistic critique of humanistic approaches. As my discussion is sensitive to concrete social reali- ties (or territorialized), I limit myself to the Latin American context, which was highly influenced by Catholicism, Positivism and Marxism. Although Piaget and Bunge are justified in claiming that Philosophy disassociated from Science is too speculative, Bunge’s proposal of reconstructing it as a holistic system is unviable because it goes way beyond a normal research program, as if it were a supersci- ence. However, a closer examination of Piaget’s and Bunge’s practice suggests a second, more modest possibility: Analytical Philosophy can focus on methodo- logical, conceptual and ethical problems within specific scientific disciplines. This prevents the outright extinction of Philosophy, which could in itself be con- ceptually incoherent besides being unwise, and instead proposes its subordina- tion, articulation, fragmentation and diaspora among the Sciences. A third option would be historical-theoretical reconstruction, which Piaget also accepted as an honorable exit. In addition, curricular and institutional changes would be needed in undergraduate education for Philosophy students to acquire at least basic sci- entific training that would break what Piaget described as the spell of holistic reflection (holology). Keywords: Piaget, J.; Bunge, M.; Metaphilosophy; Scientism; Latin America. 1 Professor Doutor na Universidade Estadual de Campinas (UNICAMP), Faculdade de Ciências Aplicadas (FCA), campus Limeira, São Paulo, Brasil.
    [Show full text]
  • 978-1-5275-6764-1-Sample.Pdf
    We live beneath our level of knowledge thats the human comedy. (Braun 2019, 136; translated by Tom Cheesman) The only way to resist powers determined madness is with determined reason. (Braun 2019, 294; translated by Tom Cheesman) We have to speak clearly, no matter how uncomfortable that may be. ( ) You are not mature enough to tell it like is. Even that burden you leave to us children. ( ) We have not come here to beg world leaders to care. You have ignored us in the past and you will ignore us again. We have run out of excuses and we are running out of time. We have come here to let you know that change is coming, whether you like it or not. (Greta Thunberg 2018; see also Thunberg 2019a) We dont have the courage nor the capacity to admit that meaning for our individual and collective lives cannot be provided anymore by a religion or an ideology, cannot be given to us as a gift; that we have to create it ourselves. (Castoriadis 2005, 327; my translation) One by one, we will see that past certainties are being dismantled. (Rippon 2019, xix) Some people would like to persuade the curious to keep their hands off the beloved mysteries, not realizing that a mystery solved is even more ravishing than the ignorant fantasies. (Dennett 2017, 10) Atheism is more than just the knowledge that gods do not exist, and that religion is either a mistake or a fraud. Atheism is an attitude, a frame of mind that looks at the world objectively, fearlessly, always trying to understand all things as a part of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Popper's Forgotten Role in the Quantum Debate at the Edge
    Karl Popper’s Forgotten Role in the Quantum Debate at the Edge between Philosophy and Physics in 1950s and 1960s Flavio Del Santo Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information – Vienna (IQOQI), Austrian Academy of Sciences Basic Research Community for Physics (BRCP) Abstract. It is not generally well known that the philosopher Karl Popper has been one of the foremost critics of the orthodox interpretation of quantum physics for about six decades. This paper reconstructs in detail most of Popper’s activities on foundations of quantum mechanics (FQM) in the period of 1950s and 1960s, when his involvement in the community of quantum physicists became extensive and quite influential. Thanks to unpublished documents and correspondence, it is now possible to shed new light on Popper’s central –though neglected– role in this “thought collective” of physicists concerned with FQM, and on the intellectual relationships that Popper established in this context with some of the protagonists of the debate over quantum physics (such as David Bohm, Alfed Landé and Henry Margenau, among many others). Foundations of quantum mechanics represented in those years also the initial ground for the embittering controversy between Popper and perhaps his most notable former student, Paul Feyerabend. I present here novel elements to further understand the origin of their troubled relationship. 1. Introduction: motivations, methods and goals. Karl R. Popper (1902-1994) has been one of the most preeminent philosophers of science of the twentieth century. He is generally known for his views on scientific method, having introduced falsifiability as the demarcation criterion between scientific and non-scientific theories, and as a matter of fact still today “many scientists subscribe to some version of simplified Popperianism” (Kragh 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Mario Bunge's Worldview and Its Implications for the Modernization
    Mario Bunge’s Worldview and its Implications for The Modernization of Arabic-Islamic Philosophy Ahmad Zahaadden Obiedat Faculty of Religious Studies McGill University, Montreal May, 2011 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research of McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Ahmad Zahaadden Obiedat, 2011 ii Abstract Zahaadden Obiedat, Ahmad. “Mario Bunge’s Worldview and its Implications for The Modernization of Arabic-Islamic Philosophy.” Ph.D. dissertation: McGill University, 2011. This study relates philosophy of science and philosophy of religion. It compares a system of western thought and its implications for contemporary Arab-Islamic philosophy. The basis for this approach lies in the concept of worldview as rooted in the process of systematization of available human knowledge in a harmonious way. Actually, many secularists attack the religious outlook but fail to provide a coherent and systematic worldview of their own. Mario Bunge (b. 1919) overcomes such a deficiency and offers a coherent modern worldview. The philosophy of Taha ‘Abd al-Rahman (born 1945), which attempts to modernize Arab-Islamic philosophy, is taken as the religious counterpart to Bunge’s modern worldview. Since the late 1950s, Mario Augusto Bunge, a widely read and influential Argentinean-Canadian philosopher of science, has become a leading figure of what might be called the scientific humanist project. This project aims at rethinking Kant’s combining of reason and experience, and this is why Bunge calls his new orientation ratio-empiricism. His philosophical endeavours culminate in a system of philosophy epitomized in the monumental nine-part Treatise on Basic Philosophy (1974-1989).
    [Show full text]