Paraconsistency and Duality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Paraconsistency and Duality Paraconsistency and duality: between ontological and 1 epistemological views 1 2 WALTER CARNIELLI AND ABILIO RODRIGUES 2 Abstract: The aim of this paper is to show how an epistemic approach to paraconsistency may be philosophically justified based on the duality be- tween paraconsistency and paracompleteness. The invalidity of excluded middle in intuitionistic logic may be understood as expressing that no con- 3 structive proof of a pair of propositions A and :A is available. Analogously, in order to explain the invalidity of the principle of explosion in paraconsis- tent logics, it is not necessary to consider that A and :A are true, but rather that there are conflicting and non-conclusive evidence for both. Keywords: Paraconsistent logic, Philosophy of paraconsistency, Evidence, Intuitionistic logic 4 1 Introduction 5 Paraconsistent logics have been assuming an increasingly important place 6 in contemporary philosophical debate. Although from the strictly techni- 7 cal point of view paraconsistent formal systems have reached a point of 8 remarkable development, there are still some aspects of their philosophi- 9 cal significance that have not been fully explored yet. The distinctive fea- 10 ture of paraconsistent logics is that the principle of explosion, according to 11 which anything follows from a contradiction, does not hold, thus allowing 12 for the presence of contradictions without deductive triviality. Dialetheism 13 is the view according to which there are true contradictions (cf. e.g. Priest 14 1The first author acknowledges support from FAPESP (Fundação de Amparo à Pesquisa do Estado de São Paulo, thematic project LogCons) and from a CNPq (Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico) research grant. 2The second author acknowledges support from FAPEMIG (Fundação de Amparo à Pesquisa do Estado de Minas Gerais, research project 21308). Both authors would like to thank Henrique Almeida, Antonio Coelho, Décio Krause, André Porto, Wagner Sanz and an anonymous referee for some valuable comments on a previous version of this text. 1 Walter Carnielli and Abilio Rodrigues 15 & Berto, 2013). Paraconsistency and dialetheism are not the same thing: the 16 latter implies the former, but one can endorse a paraconsistent logic without 17 being dialetheist. 18 For those who believe in true contradictions, dialetheism does provide a 19 philosophical justification for paraconsistency. If one accepts that reality is 20 intrinsically contradictory, in the sense that in order to truly describe it (s)he 21 needs some pairs of contradictory propositions, then, since reality obviously 22 is not trivial, (s)he needs a logic in which not everything follows from a 23 contradiction, i.e. a paraconsistent logic. 24 The thesis that reality is (in some sense) contradictory is an old philo- 25 sophical quandary, and it has been a position defended by philosophers such 26 as Hegel and, according to some interpreters, also by Heraclitus. This con- 27 fers to contemporary dialetheism a sort of philosophical legitimacy. How- 28 ever, inside and outside philosophy, there is a strong reluctance in accepting 29 that there may be entities that disobey the principle of non-contradiction as 30 it is expressed by Aristotle in book IV of his Metaphysics (1005b19-21): 31 “the same attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the 32 same subject in the same respect” (Aristotle, 1996). Indeed, rejecting any 33 contradiction as false is a basic methodological criterion both in sciences 34 and in philosophy. 35 In order to accept contradictions without endorsing dialetheism, one 36 needs a non-explosive negation not committed to the truth of a pair of propo- 37 sitions A and :A. Such a negation can only occur in a context of reasoning 38 where what is at stake is a property weaker than truth, in the sense that a 39 proposition may enjoy that property without being true. We argue in section 40 4 (and also in Carnielli & Rodrigues, 2016a) that the notion of evidence, in 41 the sense of reasons for accepting and/or believing in a proposition, allows 42 an epistemic reading of contradictions that is useful to describe contexts of 43 reasoning where contradictions occur. It is perfectly feasible to imagine a 44 scenario where non-conclusive evidence for both A and :A is available, 45 while no evidence for a certain B can be found, thus providing a counter- 46 example to the principle of explosion. The notion of evidence is weaker 47 than truth, since evidence for A does not imply that A is true, thus satis- 48 fying our requirement for a property weaker than truth to be attributed to 49 contradictory propositions. 50 Truth is the central notion for classical logic. An inference is classically 51 valid if, and only if, it preserves truth. A logic designed to represent contra- 52 dictions as conflicting evidence will not be concerned with preservation of 53 truth but, rather, with preservation of evidence. The situation is analogous 2 Paraconsistency and duality to intuitionistic logic, when it is interpreted epistemically as concerned not 54 with truth, but with the availability of a constructive proof. Our aim here is 55 to show how such an epistemic approach to paraconsistency may be philo- 56 sophically justified based on the duality between the rejection of the princi- 57 ple of explosion by paraconsistent and the rejection of excluded middle by 58 paracomplete logics. 59 This text is structured as follows. In section 2 we discuss the duality 60 between excluded middle and the principle of explosion. The invalidity of 61 these inferences are the distinctive features, respectively, of paracomplete 62 and paraconsistent logics. Section 3 shows that the rejection of the principle 63 of excluded middle by intuitionistic logic may be understood both from an 64 ontological and from an epistemic point of view. In section 4, an epistemic 65 3 approach to paraconsistency is defended. 66 2 On the duality between paraconsistency and paracom- 67 pleteness 68 Let us define two n-ary logical connectives C1 and C2 as dual when 69 ∼C1(A1;A2; :::; An) and C2(∼A1; ∼A2; :::; ∼An) 70 are classically equivalent (∼ meaning classical negation). Thus, 8 and 9, ^ 71 and _ are dual to each other, and ∼ is dual to itself. We also say that the 72 corresponding formulas are dual. It is clear then that the formulas 73 ∼(A ^ ∼A) and A _ ∼A 74 (expressing, respectively, non-contradiction and excluded middle) are dual. 75 However, this duality may be seen from a different, more fundamental view- 76 point, as a duality between rules of inference. 77 The principles of non-contradiction and excluded middle are often pre- 78 sented in books of logic, and philosophy, as fundamental laws of thought 79 and basic tenets of classical logic. However, it is not non-contradiction but 80 rather explosion that is essential to characterize classical negation, and this 81 is a central feature of the classical account of logical consequence. 82 3This text overlaps with other papers of the authors in some points. Parts of section 2 have appeared in (Carnielli & Rodrigues, 2016b). Sections 3 and 4 develop some ideas presented in (Carnielli & Rodrigues, 2015) and (Carnielli & Rodrigues, 2016b). 3 Walter Carnielli and Abilio Rodrigues 83 Classical negation ∼ is defined by the following conditions (for classical 84 _ and ^ ): A ^ ∼A ; (1) 85 A _ ∼A: (2) 86 Condition (1) says that there is no model M such that A^∼A holds in M. (2) 87 says that for every model M, A_∼A holds in M. A negation is paracomplete 88 if it disobeys (2), and paraconsistent if it disobeys (1). Notice that each one 89 of the conditions above corresponds exactly to half of the classical semantic 90 clause for negation: M(∼A) = 1 if and only if M(A) = 0: (3) 91 The only if forbids that both A and :A receive 1, and the if forbids that 92 both receive 0. Given the classical definition of logical consequence (and 93 the usual meanings of ^ and _), from (1) and (2) above it follows that for 94 any A and B: A ^ ∼A B; (4) 95 B A _ ∼A: (5) 96 Inference (4) above is (one version of) the principle of explosion and (5) 97 is (again, one version of) excluded middle. Of course, excluded middle is 98 usually presented as a valid formula or axiom, without the premise B, but 99 this is tantamount to the formulation (5) above, which makes it clear that 100 A _:A follows from anything. It is easy to see, therefore, that from the 101 point of view of classical logic, the fact that excluded middle is not valid in 102 paracomplete logics and the fact that explosion is not valid in paraconsistent 103 logics are mirror images of each other. 104 It is worth noting that non-contradiction and explosion are not equiv- 105 alent in the following sense: one obtains a complete system of classical 106 propositional logic by adding excluded middle and the principle of explo- 4 107 sion to a system of posititive intuitionistic propositional logic , but the sys- 108 tem so obtained turns out to be incomplete if one changes the latter to non- 109 contradiction. 110 Due to the semantic clause (3) above, a central feature of classical nega- 111 tion is that it is a contradictory-forming operator. Applied to a proposition 112 A, classical negation produces a proposition ∼A such that A and ∼A are 4Positive intuitionistic propositional logic may be defined by the usual introduction and elimination natural deduction rules for ^ , _ and !. 4 Paraconsistency and duality contradictories in the sense that they can neither receive simultaneously the 113 value 0, nor simultaneously the value 1.
Recommended publications
  • NSP4 Pragmatist Kant
    Nordic NSP Studies in Pragmatism Helsinki — 2019 Giovanni Maddalena “Anti-Kantianism as a Necessary Characteristic of Pragmatism” In: Krzysztof Piotr Skowronski´ and Sami Pihlstrom¨ (Eds.) (2019). Pragmatist Kant—Pragmatism, Kant, and Kantianism in the Twenty-first Century (pp. 43–59). Nordic Studies in Pragmatism 4. Helsinki: Nordic Pragmatism Network. issn-l 1799-3954 issn 1799-3954 isbn 978-952-67497-3-0 Copyright c 2019 The Authors and the Nordic Pragmatism Network. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported License. CC BY NC For more information, see http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/ Nordic Pragmatism Network, NPN Helsinki 2019 www.nordprag.org Anti-Kantianism as a Necessary Characteristic of Pragmatism Giovanni Maddalena Universit`adel Molise 1. Introduction Pragmatists declared their anti-Cartesianism at the first appearance of the movement, in Peirce’s series on cognition written for the Journal of Specu- lative Philosophy (1867–8). As is well known, the brilliant young scientist characterized Cartesian doubt as a “paper doubt”, by opposing it to sci- entists’ true “living doubt” (Peirce 1998 [1868], 115).1 Some readers have not understood the powerful novelty that his opposition to Cartesianism implies. According to Peirce, research does not proceed from skeptical, “paper” doubt. For Peirce, doubt is possible because of a previous cer- tainty, a position which is similar to the one held by Augustine (Augustine 1970). Research moves from one certainty to another; the abandonment of an initial certainty is only reasonable in the presence of a real and surprising phenomenon that alters one of the pillars on which it stands.
    [Show full text]
  • The Unintended Interpretations of Intuitionistic Logic
    THE UNINTENDED INTERPRETATIONS OF INTUITIONISTIC LOGIC Wim Ruitenburg Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science Marquette University Milwaukee, WI 53233 Abstract. We present an overview of the unintended interpretations of intuitionis- tic logic that arose after Heyting formalized the “observed regularities” in the use of formal parts of language, in particular, first-order logic and Heyting Arithmetic. We include unintended interpretations of some mild variations on “official” intuitionism, such as intuitionistic type theories with full comprehension and higher order logic without choice principles or not satisfying the right choice sequence properties. We conclude with remarks on the quest for a correct interpretation of intuitionistic logic. §1. The Origins of Intuitionistic Logic Intuitionism was more than twenty years old before A. Heyting produced the first complete axiomatizations for intuitionistic propositional and predicate logic: according to L. E. J. Brouwer, the founder of intuitionism, logic is secondary to mathematics. Some of Brouwer’s papers even suggest that formalization cannot be useful to intuitionism. One may wonder, then, whether intuitionistic logic should itself be regarded as an unintended interpretation of intuitionistic mathematics. I will not discuss Brouwer’s ideas in detail (on this, see [Brouwer 1975], [Hey- ting 1934, 1956]), but some aspects of his philosophy need to be highlighted here. According to Brouwer mathematics is an activity of the human mind, a product of languageless thought. One cannot be certain that language is a perfect reflection of this mental activity. This makes language an uncertain medium (see [van Stigt 1982] for more details on Brouwer’s ideas about language). In “De onbetrouwbaarheid der logische principes” ([Brouwer 1981], pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Intuitionistic Three-Valued Logic and Logic Programming Informatique Théorique Et Applications, Tome 25, No 6 (1991), P
    INFORMATIQUE THÉORIQUE ET APPLICATIONS J. VAUZEILLES A. STRAUSS Intuitionistic three-valued logic and logic programming Informatique théorique et applications, tome 25, no 6 (1991), p. 557-587 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=ITA_1991__25_6_557_0> © AFCET, 1991, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Informatique théorique et applications » im- plique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam. org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la présente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ Informatique théorique et Applications/Theoretical Informaties and Applications (vol. 25, n° 6, 1991, p. 557 à 587) INTUITIONISTIC THREE-VALUED LOGIC AMD LOGIC PROGRAMM1NG (*) by J. VAUZEILLES (*) and A. STRAUSS (2) Communicated by J. E. PIN Abstract. - In this paper, we study the semantics of logic programs with the help of trivalued hgic, introduced by Girard in 1973. Trivalued sequent calculus enables to extend easily the results of classical SLD-resolution to trivalued logic. Moreover, if one allows négation in the head and in the body of Hom clauses, one obtains a natural semantics for such programs regarding these clauses as axioms of a theory written in the intuitionistic fragment of that logic. Finally^ we define in the same calculus an intuitionistic trivalued version of Clark's completion, which gives us a déclarative semantics for programs with négation in the body of the clauses, the évaluation method being SLDNF-resolution. Resumé. — Dans cet article, nous étudions la sémantique des programmes logiques à l'aide de la logique trivaluée^ introduite par Girard en 1973.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructivity in Homotopy Type Theory
    Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy Constructivity in Homotopy Type Theory Author: Supervisors: Maximilian Doré Prof. Dr. Dr. Hannes Leitgeb Prof. Steve Awodey, PhD Munich, August 2019 Thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Logic and Philosophy of Science contents Contents 1 Introduction1 1.1 Outline................................ 3 1.2 Open Problems ........................... 4 2 Judgements and Propositions6 2.1 Judgements ............................. 7 2.2 Propositions............................. 9 2.2.1 Dependent types...................... 10 2.2.2 The logical constants in HoTT .............. 11 2.3 Natural Numbers.......................... 13 2.4 Propositional Equality....................... 14 2.5 Equality, Revisited ......................... 17 2.6 Mere Propositions and Propositional Truncation . 18 2.7 Universes and Univalence..................... 19 3 Constructive Logic 22 3.1 Brouwer and the Advent of Intuitionism ............ 22 3.2 Heyting and Kolmogorov, and the Formalization of Intuitionism 23 3.3 The Lambda Calculus and Propositions-as-types . 26 3.4 Bishop’s Constructive Mathematics................ 27 4 Computational Content 29 4.1 BHK in Homotopy Type Theory ................. 30 4.2 Martin-Löf’s Meaning Explanations ............... 31 4.2.1 The meaning of the judgments.............. 32 4.2.2 The theory of expressions................. 34 4.2.3 Canonical forms ...................... 35 4.2.4 The validity of the types.................. 37 4.3 Breaking Canonicity and Propositional Canonicity . 38 4.3.1 Breaking canonicity .................... 39 4.3.2 Propositional canonicity.................. 40 4.4 Proof-theoretic Semantics and the Meaning Explanations . 40 5 Constructive Identity 44 5.1 Identity in Martin-Löf’s Meaning Explanations......... 45 ii contents 5.1.1 Intensional type theory and the meaning explanations 46 5.1.2 Extensional type theory and the meaning explanations 47 5.2 Homotopical Interpretation of Identity ............
    [Show full text]
  • Intuitionistic Logic
    Intuitionistic Logic Nick Bezhanishvili and Dick de Jongh Institute for Logic, Language and Computation Universiteit van Amsterdam Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Intuitionism 3 3 Kripke models, Proof systems and Metatheorems 8 3.1 Other proof systems . 8 3.2 Arithmetic and analysis . 10 3.3 Kripke models . 15 3.4 The Disjunction Property, Admissible Rules . 20 3.5 Translations . 22 3.6 The Rieger-Nishimura Lattice and Ladder . 24 3.7 Complexity of IPC . 25 3.8 Mezhirov's game for IPC . 28 4 Heyting algebras 30 4.1 Lattices, distributive lattices and Heyting algebras . 30 4.2 The connection of Heyting algebras with Kripke frames and topologies . 33 4.3 Algebraic completeness of IPC and its extensions . 38 4.4 The connection of Heyting and closure algebras . 40 5 Jankov formulas and intermediate logics 42 5.1 n-universal models . 42 5.2 Formulas characterizing point generated subsets . 44 5.3 The Jankov formulas . 46 5.4 Applications of Jankov formulas . 47 5.5 The logic of the Rieger-Nishimura ladder . 52 1 1 Introduction In this course we give an introduction to intuitionistic logic. We concentrate on the propositional calculus mostly, make some minor excursions to the predicate calculus and to the use of intuitionistic logic in intuitionistic formal systems, in particular Heyting Arithmetic. We have chosen a selection of topics that show various sides of intuitionistic logic. In no way we strive for a complete overview in this short course. Even though we approach the subject for the most part only formally, it is good to have a general introduction to intuitionism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Proper Explanation of Intuitionistic Logic: on Brouwer's Demonstration
    The proper explanation of intuitionistic logic: on Brouwer’s demonstration of the Bar Theorem Göran Sundholm, Mark van Atten To cite this version: Göran Sundholm, Mark van Atten. The proper explanation of intuitionistic logic: on Brouwer’s demonstration of the Bar Theorem. van Atten, Mark Heinzmann, Gerhard Boldini, Pascal Bourdeau, Michel. One Hundred Years of Intuitionism (1907-2007). The Cerisy Conference, Birkhäuser, pp.60- 77, 2008, 978-3-7643-8652-8. halshs-00791550 HAL Id: halshs-00791550 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00791550 Submitted on 24 Jan 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution - NonCommercial| 4.0 International License The proper explanation of intuitionistic logic: on Brouwer’s demonstration of the Bar Theorem Göran Sundholm Philosophical Institute, Leiden University, P.O. Box 2315, 2300 RA Leiden, The Netherlands. [email protected] Mark van Atten SND (CNRS / Paris IV), 1 rue Victor Cousin, 75005 Paris, France. [email protected] Der … geführte Beweis scheint mir aber trotzdem . Basel: Birkhäuser, 2008, 60–77. wegen der in seinem Gedankengange enthaltenen Aussagen Interesse zu besitzen. (Brouwer 1927B, n. 7)1 Brouwer’s demonstration of his Bar Theorem gives rise to provocative ques- tions regarding the proper explanation of the logical connectives within intu- itionistic and constructivist frameworks, respectively, and, more generally, re- garding the role of logic within intuitionism.
    [Show full text]
  • Consistency, Contradiction and Negation. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science Series
    BOOK REVIEW: CARNIELLI, W., CONIGLIO, M. Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency, Contradiction and Negation. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science Series. (New York: Springer, 2016. ISSN: 2214-9775.) Henrique Antunes Vincenzo Ciccarelli State University of Campinas State University of Campinas Department of Philosophy Department of Philosophy Campinas, SP Campinas, SP Brazil Brazil [email protected] [email protected] Article info CDD: 160 Received: 01.12.2017; Accepted: 30.12.2017 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2018.V41N2.HV Keywords: Paraconsistent Logic LFIs ABSTRACT Review of the book 'Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency, Contradiction and Negation' (2016), by Walter Carnielli and Marcelo Coniglio The principle of explosion (also known as ex contradictione sequitur quodlibet) states that a pair of contradictory formulas entails any formula whatsoever of the relevant language and, accordingly, any theory regimented on the basis of a logic for which this principle holds (such as classical and intuitionistic logic) will turn out to be trivial if it contains a pair of theorems of the form A and ¬A (where ¬ is a negation operator). A logic is paraconsistent if it rejects the principle of explosion, allowing thus for the possibility of contradictory and yet non-trivial theories. Among the several paraconsistent logics that have been proposed in the literature, there is a particular family of (propositional and quantified) systems known as Logics of Formal Inconsistency (LFIs), developed and thoroughly studied Manuscrito – Rev. Int. Fil. Campinas, v. 41, n. 2, pp. 111-122, abr.-jun. 2018. Henrique Antunes & Vincenzo Ciccarelli 112 within the Brazilian tradition on paraconsistency. A distinguishing feature of the LFIs is that although they reject the general validity of the principle of explosion, as all other paraconsistent logics do, they admit a a restrcited version of it known as principle of gentle explosion.
    [Show full text]
  • THE LOOICAL ATOMISM J. D. MACKENZIE Date Submitted Thesis
    THE LOOICAL ATOMISM OF F. P. RAMSEY J. D. MACKENZIE Date submitted Thesis submitted for the Degree of Master of Arts in the School of Philosophy University of New South Wales (i) SYNOPSIS The first Chapter sets Ramsey in histor:iealperspective as a Logical Atomist. Chapter Two is concerned with the impasse in which Russell found himself ,d.th general propositions, Wittgenstein's putative solution in terms of his Doctrine of Showing, and Ramsey's "Wittgensteinian" solution, which is not satisfactory. An attempt is then ma.de to describe a Ramseian solution on the basis of what he says about the Axiom of Infi- nity, and to criticize this solution. In Chapter Three Ramsay's objections to the Pl4 definition of identity are considered, and consequences of his rejection of that definition for the Theory of Classes and the Axiom of Choice are drawn. In Chapter Four, Ramsey•s modifications to Russell's Theory of Types are discussed. His division of the Paradoxes into two groups is defended, but his redefinition of 'predicative' is rejected. Chapter Five deals with Ra.msey's analysis of propositional attitudes and negative propositions, and Chapter Six considers the dispute between Russell and Ramsey over the nature and status of universals. In Chapter Seven, the conclusions are summarized, and Ramsay's contribution to Logical Atom.ism are assessed. His main fail­ ing is found to be his lack of understanding of impossibility, especially with regard to the concept of infinity. (ii) PREFACE The thesis is divided into chapters, which are in turn divided into sections.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Intuitionism
    Understanding Intuitionism by Edward Nelson Department of Mathematics Princeton University http:==www.math.princeton.edu= nelson=papers.html ∼ Intuitionism was the creation of L. E. J. Brouwer [Br], and I like to think that classical mathematics was the creation of Pythagoras. Imag- ine a conversation between a classical mathematician and an intuitionist, say a woman and a man respectively. She speaks first: I have just proved xA. Congratulations! What9 is it? I don't know. I assumed x A and derived a contradiction. Oh. You proved x A.8 : That's what I said.:8 : Or another: I have proved A B. Good. Which did_ you prove? What? You said you proved A or B; which did you prove? Neither; I assumed A & B and derived a contradiction. Oh, you proved [ :A & :B]. That's right. It's: another: : way of putting the same thing. But he does not agree with her last statement; they have a different semantics and a different notion of proof. This paper is an attempt to understand the differences between them. I am grateful to Mitsuru Yasuhara for stimulating discussions of this material and for pinpointing errors and obscurities in earlier drafts. I also wish to thank Simon Kochen and Per Martin-L¨offor helpful comments. 1. Incomplete communications For a classical mathematician, a closed formula, true in a given structure, is a complete communication. It expresses an objective state of affairs in the universe of discourse; it is an ontological assertion. But 1 2 1. INCOMPLETE COMMUNICATIONS to an intuitionist, a closed true formula may be an incomplete communi- cation.
    [Show full text]
  • Intuition As Evidence in Philosophical Analysis: Taking Connectionism Seriously
    Intuition as Evidence in Philosophical Analysis: Taking Connectionism Seriously by Tom Rand A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Ph.D. Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto (c) Copyright by Tom Rand 2008 Intuition as Evidence in Philosophical Analysis: Taking Connectionism Seriously Ph.D. Degree, 2008, by Tom Rand, Graduate Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto ABSTRACT 1. Intuitions are often treated in philosophy as a basic evidential source to confirm/discredit a proposed definition or theory; e.g. intuitions about Gettier cases are taken to deny a justified-true-belief analysis of ‘knowledge’. Recently, Weinberg, Nichols & Stitch (WN&S) provided evidence that epistemic intuitions vary across persons and cultures. In- so-far as philosophy of this type (Standard Philosophical Methodology – SPM) is committed to provide conceptual analyses, the use of intuition is suspect – it does not exhibit the requisite normativity. I provide an analysis of intuition, with an emphasis on its neural – or connectionist – cognitive backbone; the analysis provides insight into its epistemic status and proper role within SPM. Intuition is initially characterized as the recognition of a pattern. 2. The metaphysics of ‘pattern’ is analyzed for the purpose of denying that traditional symbolic computation is capable of differentiating the patterns of interest. 3. The epistemology of ‘recognition’ is analyzed, again, to deny that traditional computation is capable of capturing human acts of recognition. 4. Fodor’s informational semantics, his Language of Thought and his Representational Theory of Mind are analyzed and his arguments denied. Again, the purpose is to deny traditional computational theories of mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructive Logic for All
    Constructive Logic for All Greg Restall∗ Philosophy Department Macquarie University June 14, 2000 Abstract It is a commonplace in recent metaphysics that one's logical commit- ments go hand in hand with one's metaphysics. Brouwer, Heyting and Dummett have each championed the move to constructive (intuitionistic) reasoning on the grounds of anti-realism. I hope to break this close connec- tion, to explain why a realist ought to reason constructively. 1 Introduction Let me start by explaining the terms of the discussion. In this area of philo- sophical logic there seems to be some confusion in the use of terms such as “intuitionistic” and “constructive.” It will help to get the use of these terms somewhat fixed before I start to argue my case. 1.1 Logic First, logic. The subject Logic is the study of logical consequence. Logical con- sequence is a matter of the validity and invalidity of arguments. An argument is valid just when in any case in which the premises of the argument are true, so is the conclusion. It is often helpful, in discussing logical consequence, to have a formal language in which to express the premises and conclusions of ar- guments. One such language is the language of first-order logic, with primitive expressions for the connectives and quantifiers ^ conjunction _ disjunction conditional ⊃ ∼ negation x universal quantifier 8 (with x a variable) x existential quantifier 9 (with x a variable) For some, logic is at heart the study of the behaviour of these connectives. For others, the singling out of particular parts of the language is an incidental mat- ter.
    [Show full text]
  • Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume 1: the Dawn of Analysis Princeton University Press, 2003
    Philos Stud (2006) 129:637–643 DOI 10.1007/s11098-006-0015-3 DISCUSSION Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century: Volume 1: The Dawn of Analysis Princeton University Press, 2003 R.M. Sainsbury Accepted: 27 March 2006 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2006 The jacket of this first volume of the two volume work tells us that this is a history of analytic philosophy from 1900 to mid-century. Accordingly, we can properly eval- uate it under three heads: (1) the care and accuracy of the scholarship; (2) the light it throws on the relationships among the various activities it describes; and (3) the quality of the philosophical argumentation. Evaluated under the third, the book deserves high praise. It provides serious philosophy: arguments are carefully set out and taken to pieces, objections and possible responses are developed in an orderly way. Most readers will learn something of philosophical value, and even on the issues about which they disagree with Soames, they will find him a worthy and helpful opponent. In this respect the text provides a model to which students should aspire. Every page demonstrates one way in which philosophy can be done excel- lently, as will be no surprise to those familiar with Soames’s other work. Evaluated under the other two heads, however, the book in my judgement falls short. Not only are there historical inaccuracies, the approach to reading, evaluating and interpreting texts is one I find uncongenial; and the attempt to impose some kind of overall developmental themes on the material under discussion strikes me as unsuccessful.
    [Show full text]