Book Winter 2007.Qxd

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Book Winter 2007.Qxd Hilary Rose & Steven Rose The changing face of human nature In 1992, at the start of the surprising- deterministic gene talk and genes for ly short decade’s march toward the se- everything from the most severe dis- quencing of the human genome, one of eases to compulsive shopping and its key initiators, geneticist Walter Gil- homelessness. While the cd played its bert, claimed that “one will be able to part in the popularization of the hgp, pull a cd out of one’s pocket and say, it was the representation of dna’s dou- ‘Here is a human being; it’s me.’”1 ble helix that came to be the dominant Gilbert’s brilliant piece of theater was signi½er of life itself. More subversive- echoed by other leading molecular bi- ly, numbers of graphic artists saw the ologists in their campaign to win pub- potential surveillance powers of geno- lic support and enthusiasm for the Hu- mics, striking a more critical note than man Genome Project (hgp). It seemed the cds or the double helix by, instead, not to matter how often the biologists showing people with bar-coded fore- employed the same theatrical device, heads. Here human nature was reduced whether in California or at London’s to a mere commodity with no agency, Institute for Contemporary Arts: hold- to be read at the checkout counter. ing up a cd to a spellbound audience The explosive growth of genomics, and saying, “this is human life itself” with its relatively subdued cultural de- was a brilliantly chosen trope. The cd, bate, was not alone. Another powerful so familiar to the audience of a high- and expanding ½eld, namely, neurobiol- tech society, was recruited to symbol- ogy, led to the 1990s being nominated ize the merger of molecularization by the National Institutes of Health as and digitalization heralded by the de- the Decade of the Brain. (Europe was veloping hgp. At once a science and slower; its Brain Decade started about a technology, this technoscience of hu- ½ve years later.) By 2009, on both sides man genomics simultaneously offered of the pond, neuroscientists claimed a new de½nition of human nature and that advances in brain science had been new, promethean powers to repair and so substantial that it had become the even redesign that nature. Decade of the Mind. Just as the double dna and genomics dominated the helix became the symbol of the hgp, so media throughout the 1990s, with its have the vivid, false-color skull-shaped images locating the “sites” of brain ac- © 2009 by Hilary Rose & Steven Rose tivity come to symbolize the new neuro- Dædalus Summer 2009 7 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/daed.2009.138.3.7 by guest on 02 October 2021 Hilary science. These sites include not only tions, but with the claims that these Rose & well-understood regions within the technosciences now make: that they Steven Rose brain, such as those associated with vi- can provide a materialist account of on being sion and speech, but also new ones, like human nature itself, whether body human regions thought to be associated with and brain or mind and consciousness. London taxi-drivers’ knowledge of the In this, genomics and neuroscience are London streets,2 for example, or with building on a materialist tradition that “romantic love.”3 Londoners were de- runs back to antiquity, but that gained lighted to learn the location of their increasing authority from the birth of cabbies’ “knowledge,” persuaded by modern science in the seventeenth cen- the high-tech images one could see in tury. Previous materialist claims by phi- any newspaper. For those humanists losophers, such as Hume and la Mettrie, who understand the concept of roman- could not make the power move of of- tic love as originating with the medie- fering an alternative theory; only the val troubadours, the claim by leading cultural authority of the growing natu- imager Semir Zeki that this is a univer- ral sciences provided this. It isn’t possi- sal brain-located human phenomenon, ble to understand and interpret the con- unaffected by culture or history, is dis- struction of human nature by present- tinctly challenging. day genomics and neuroscience without Contemporary genomics and neuro- locating them, however sketchily, histor- science not only claim to explain how ically within this materialist tradition. the brain and, hence, the mind work, but also to put psychiatry on a sound By the late eighteenth century, “ani- scienti½c basis. While the drivers for mal electricity,” mesmerism, and phre- the scientists may primarily be curiosity, nology were attempting to locate men- as the conditions for exploring these lat- tal attributes, and indeed life itself, with- est scienti½c frontiers ripen, the practi- in the explanatory realm of the natural cal implications, both for medicine and, sciences. The early-nineteenth-century more disturbingly, as tools for control- materialist accounts of nature and hu- ling and manipulating the mind, are pro- man nature produced by natural philos- found. Patients’ accounts of their experi- ophers (that is, scientists) found a recep- ence of mental illness will become less tive audience among intellectuals. High or even unnecessary as brain scans and up in the Yorkshire Dales, the Brontë sis- gene scans are taken as speaking more ters (Bramwell was probably in the pub) accurately about the underlying causes. would walk the several miles from the Once again the human agent disappears Haworth parsonage down to Keighley, and human nature becomes digitalized. their nearest town, to listen to a lecture In a biotechnological age, where major on phrenology, the hottest materialist funding for genomics and neuroscience account of brain and mind. In the vivid comes from the biotech and pharmaceu- descriptions of the head shapes of Mr. tical industries as well as from venture Rochester and Jane Eyre we ½nd the in- capitalism, and universities move to pro- fluence of the new phrenology in the tect their intellectual property with pat- pen of Charlotte Brontë.5 In distant ents, disinterested curiosity increasing- Cornwall, the young chemist Humphry ly belongs to a distant age of science.4 Davy and the poet Samuel Coleridge However, our concern here is not so formed a lifelong friendship, and Davy’s much with these commercial implica- speculations about electricity as a life 8 Dædalus Summer 2009 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/daed.2009.138.3.7 by guest on 02 October 2021 force lay behind Mary Shelley’s unfor- ist account of nature and human nature The gettable creation of Frankenstein’s mon- –on what it is to be human, from our changing face of ster. Today, novelist Ian McEwan’s En- basic physiology to our powers of cog- human during Love embraces evolutionary psy- nition, our emotions, and our beliefs.10 nature chology; A. S. Byatt’s Babel Tower, genet- The supernatural and, hence, religious ics and neuroscience. Thus the humani- belief became unnecessary to the expla- ties of past and present gesture toward nation of human nature and mind. the new materialist accounts of human Origin set out a theory of evolutionary nature.6 change through natural and sexual selec- By the mid-nineteenth century, a fully tion, displacing the centrality of Judeo- reductive materialism, or to use philoso- Christian theology and the two-page pher Daniel Dennett’s term, a “greedy creation story from the book of Gene- reductionism,”7 had taken a ½rm hold sis. No longer were “kinds” to be under- within the sciences. In 1845, four rising stood as having been created indepen- German and French physiologists–von dently in the brief interlude between Helmholtz, Ludwig, du Bois-Reymond, God’s separating heaven and earth and and Brucke–swore a mutual oath to then resting on the seventh day. Rather prove that all bodily processes could than having been intelligently designed, be accounted for in physical and chem- as the Rev. William Paley had famously ical terms. The Dutch physiologist Ja- insisted half a century previously, spe- cob Moleschott put the position most cies had evolved from a single common strongly, claiming that “the brain se- origin and been transformed by selec- cretes thought like the kidney secretes tion operating on random variation over urine,” while “genius is a matter of long periods of geological time. (Evolu- phosphorus.”8 For the zoologist Thom- tion, according to one outraged oppo- as Huxley, mind was an epiphenome- nent, was “the law of higgledy-piggle- non, like “the whistle to the steam dy.”) Origin stories about who we are train.” But it was above all Charles Dar- and where we come from are central to win who provided the intellectual and the belief systems of human cultures, empirical bedrock for a materialist ac- and Darwin’s contemporaries were count of human origins and human na- quick to recognize that the European ture. On the Origin of Species, published commitment to the Judeo-Christian just 150 years ago, both precipitated origin story, which insisted on the im- and symbolized a transformation in mutability of God-created species, was Western society’s understanding of under challenge from a materialist and human origins. As the geneticist Theo- evidence-based narrative of speciation dosius Dobzhansky con½dently assert- through variation over time and place. ed, “[N]othing in biology makes sense The persistence of belief in creation- except in the light of evolution.”9 Cer- ism/intelligent design in the United tainly, biologists had been challenging States, still the research superpower, the notion of the ½xity of species for a remains an extraordinary anomaly.
Recommended publications
  • In Defense of Massive Modularity
    3 In Defense of Massive Modularity Dan Sperber In October 1990, a psychologist, Susan Gelman, and three anthropolo- gists whose interest in cognition had been guided and encouraged by Jacques Mehler, Scott Atran, Larry Hirschfeld, and myself, organized a conference on “Cultural Knowledge and Domain Specificity” (see Hirsch- feld and Gelman, 1994). Jacques advised us in the preparation of the conference, and while we failed to convince him to write a paper, he did play a major role in the discussions. A main issue at stake was the degree to which cognitive development, everyday cognition, and cultural knowledge are based on dedicated do- main-specific mechanisms, as opposed to a domain-general intelligence and learning capacity. Thanks in particular to the work of developmental psychologists such as Susan Carey, Rochel Gelman, Susan Gelman, Frank Keil, Alan Leslie, Jacques Mehler, Elizabeth Spelke (who were all there), the issue of domain-specificity—which, of course, Noam Chomsky had been the first to raise—was becoming a central one in cognitive psychol- ogy. Evolutionary psychology, represented at the conference by Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, was putting forward new arguments for seeing human cognition as involving mostly domain- or task-specific evolved adaptations. We were a few anthropologists, far from the main- stream of our discipline, who also saw domain-specific cognitive pro- cesses as both constraining and contributing to cultural development. Taking for granted that domain-specific dispositions are an important feature of human cognition, three questions arise: 1. To what extent are these domain-specific dispositions based on truly autonomous mental mechanisms or “modules,” as opposed to being 48 D.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction ROBERT AUNGER a Number of Prominent Academics
    CHAPTER 1: Introduction ROBERT AUNGER A number of prominent academics have recently argued that we are entering a period in which evolutionary theory is being applied to every conceivable domain of inquiry. Witness the development of fields such as evolutionary ecology (Krebs and Davies 1997), evolutionary economics (Nelson and Winter 1982), evolutionary psychology (Barkow et al. 1992), evolutionary linguistics (Pinker 1994) and literary theory (Carroll 1995), evolutionary epistemology (Callebaut and Pinxten 1987), evolutionary computational science (Koza 1992), evolutionary medicine (Nesse and Williams 1994) and psychiatry (McGuire and Troisi 1998) -- even evolutionary chemistry (Wilson and Czarnik 1997) and evolutionary physics (Smolin 1997). Such developments certainly suggest that Darwin’s legacy continues to grow. The new millennium can therefore be called the Age of Universal Darwinism (Dennett 1995; Cziko 1995). What unifies these approaches? Dan Dennett (1995) has argued that Darwin’s “dangerous idea” is an abstract algorithm, often called the “replicator dynamic.” This dynamic consists of repeated iterations of selection from among randomly mutating replicators. Replicators, in turn, are units of information with the ability to reproduce themselves using resources from some material substrate. Couched in these terms, the evolutionary process is obviously quite general. for example, the replicator dynamic, when played out on biological material such as DNA, is called natural selection. But Dennett suggests there are essentially no limits to the phenomena which can be treated using this algorithm, although there will be variation in the degree to which such treatment leads to productive insights. The primary hold-out from “evolutionarization,” it seems, is the social sciences. Twenty-five years have now passed since the biologist Richard Dawkins introduced the notion of a meme, or an idea that becomes commonly shared through social transmission, into the scholastic lexicon.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Jerry Fodor, the Mind Doesn't Work That Way
    The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology (review) Ray Jackendoff Language, Volume 78, Number 1, March 2002, pp. 164-170 (Review) Published by Linguistic Society of America DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2002.0024 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/19286 [ Access provided at 10 May 2020 20:12 GMT from Linguistic Society of America ] 164 LANGUAGE, VOLUME 78, NUMBER 1 (2002) malist studies as the brief summary of the chapters has hopefully shown. All articles complement the work of the festschrift’s honoree, are well-written, and contain interesting data as well as intriguing analyses, pushing the minimalist spirit further ahead. REFERENCES BOSˇKOVIC´,Zˇ ELJKO. 1994. D-structure, theta-criterion, and movement into theta-positions. Linguistic Analysis 24.247–86. MM. 1997. Superiority effects with multiple wh-fronting in Serbo-Croatian. Lingua 102.1–20. CHOMSKY,NOAM. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. MM. 2001. Derivation by phase. Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 1–52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. GRIMSHAW,JANE, and ARMIN MESTER. 1988. Light verbs and ␪-marking. Linguistic Inquiry 19.205–32. HORNSTEIN,NORBERT. 1995. Logical form: From GB to minimalism. Oxford: Blackwell. KAYNE,RICHARD S. 1994. The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ZAS Ja¨gerstr. 10–11 10117 Berlin Germany [[email protected]] The mind doesn’t work that way: Thescopeand limits of computational psychology. By JERRY FODOR. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2000. Pp. 126. Reviewed by RAY JACKENDOFF, Brandeis University* As has been his wont in recent years, Jerry Fodor offers here a statement of deepest pessimism about the possibility of doing cognitive science except in a very limited class of subdomains.
    [Show full text]
  • States in Mind Anthony C. Lopez, Rose Mcdermott, and Michael
    States in Mind States in Mind Anthony C. Lopez, Rose McDermott, and Evolution, Coalitional Psychology, and Michael Bang International Politics Petersen One of the most com- monly studied puzzles in international politics is the recurrence of coalitional competition and aggression between political groups such as states. Indeed, this pattern constitutes an enduring and central feature of all politics. Yet de- spite the tragic endurance of this leitmotif throughout history, its manifestation varies through time and space. Some wars are fought for honor or revenge, whereas others are ignited for mere opportunism or as a consequence of vari- ous misperceptions, whatever their source. We argue that evolutionary theory provides a theoretical framework that can explain both the stubborn endur- ance and dynamic diversity of coalitional behavior. Debate on the relevance of “human nature” and biological factors for explaining political behavior is not new.1 Yet the comprehensive value of evo- lutionary theory for explaining important aspects of international politics has not been adequately explicated. As we discuss below, this has in part been a consequence of general skepticism about the validity and scope of evolution- ary theory for explaining political behavior. We argue, however, that evolu- tionary psychology can generate falsiªable ex ante predictions that are of central interest to the study of international politics, and we offer several hy- potheses derived from this model to illustrate the depth of this approach. Evo- lutionary psychologists have already generated a large body of work that suggests that the human brain contains webs of psychological mechanisms, or adaptations, each designed to operate in domains relevant to modern politics, and which emerged as a product of natural selection.
    [Show full text]
  • A Lego Model of the Modularity of the Mind Steven J
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Faculty Research and Creative Activity Psychology January 2004 A Lego Model of the Modularity of the Mind Steven J. Scher Eastern Illinois University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://thekeep.eiu.edu/psych_fac Part of the Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Scher, Steven J., "A Lego Model of the Modularity of the Mind" (2004). Faculty Research and Creative Activity. 32. http://thekeep.eiu.edu/psych_fac/32 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Research and Creative Activity by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A LEGO MODEL OF THE MODULARITY OF THE MIND STEVEN J. SCHER Eastern Illinois University Abstract. In this paper I propose that the dominant form of evolutionary psychology (which I term “cognitive adaptationism”) can be improved by adopting an alternative version of the concept of mental modularity. I suggest a metaphor of mental modules as Lego blocks. The Lego blocks represent a relatively small set of elementary operations that the mind/brain can carry out. These Lego blocks are repeatedly assembled in different ways to execute a wide variety of different functions. These repeated assemblies correspond more closely to the things that cognitive adaptationists have asserted are modules. Arguments in favor of the Lego model include the fact that the localized neural systems identified in the brain appear to carry out elementary operations, rather than higher-level functions, and the fact that evolution by natural selection occurs by the gradual modification of small-level features.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Psychology: a Primer
    Evolutionary Psychology: A Primer Leda Cosmides & John Tooby Center for Evolutionary Psychology UC Santa Barbara http://www.psych.ucsb.edu/research/cep/ Introduction The goal of research in evolutionary psychology is to discover and understand the design of the human mind. Evolutionary psychology is an approach to psychology, in which knowledge and principles from evolutionary biology are put to use in research on the structure of the human mind. It is not an area of study, like vision, reasoning, or social behavior. It is a way of thinking about psychology that can be applied to any topic within it. In this view, the mind is a set of information-processing machines that were designed by natural selection to solve adaptive problems faced by our hunter-gatherer ancestors. This way of thinking about the brain, mind, and behavior is changing how scientists approach old topics, and opening up new ones. This chapter is a primer on the concepts and arguments that animate it. Debauching the mind: Evolutionary psychology's past and present In the final pages of the Origin of Species, after he had presented the theory of evolution by natural selection, Darwin made a bold prediction: "In the distant future I see open fields for far more important researches. Psychology will be based on a new foundation, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation." Thirty years later, William James tried to do just that in his seminal book, Principles of Psychology, one of the founding works of experimental psychology (James, 1890). In Principles, James talked a lot of "instincts".
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Psychology – 2007
    Evolutionary Psychology www.epjournal.net – 2007. 5(4): 683-695 ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ Original Article What’s in a Name: Is “Evolutionary Psychology” Eclipsing “Sociobiology” in the Scientific Literature? Gregory D. Webster, Department of Psychology, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Champaign, IL 61820, USA. Email: [email protected] (Corresponding author) Abstract: Is the term “evolutionary psychology” supplanting “sociobiology” in the scientific literature? How influential was E. O. Wilson’s (1975) book, Sociobiology, in establishing the discipline of the same name? Similarly, how influential were the two Tooby-Cosmides chapters appearing in The Adapted Mind (Cosmides and Tooby, 1992; Tooby and Cosmides, 1992) in establishing evolutionary psychology as a viable outgrowth of sociobiology? The purpose of the present research was to answer these questions using quantitative analyses of publication trends. The Internet search engine Google Scholar was used to count the number of hits (i.e., the number of scholarly works, citations, etc.) for “sociobiology” and “evolutionary psychology” separately per year from 1960 to 2003. Interrupted time-series analyses revealed significant increases (intercept shifts) for sociobiology hits between 1974 and 1975, and for evolutionary psychology hits between 1991 and 1992. Evolutionary psychology hits also experienced a significant increase in change-over-time (a slope shift) between 1991 and 1992. Growth curve analyses revealed that the rate of growth for evolutionary psychology, which
    [Show full text]
  • How Human Evolutionary Psychology Can Inform Adaptive Behavior Research Geoff
    A bottom-up approach with a clear view of the top: How human evolutionary psychology can inform adaptive behavior research Geoffrey F. Miller School of Cognitive and Computing Sciences University of Sussex Falmer, Brighton BN1 9QH, England (Now at Department of Psychology, University of Nottingham; [email protected]) Peter M. Todd Department of Psychology University of Denver 2155 S. Race Street Denver, CO 80208 USA [email protected] The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. Edited by Jerome H. Barkow, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby. New York: Oxford University Press (1992). ISBN 0-19- 506023-7, xii + 666 pp., $55 hardback. Introduction Psychologists have long paid lip service to Darwin, conceding that the human brain did arise through the course of evolution (for whatever, often unspecified, reason). But the full power of Darwinian theory is almost never used in day-to-day psychology research. This is peculiar, given the successful, integrated nature of evolutionary biology, and the typically fragmented and incomplete visage of modern psychology: one would think that a theory that explains the origin and maintenance of complex behavioral adaptations across all species (evolution) could inform and unify the study of human behavior (psychology) just as productively as it does the study of animal behavior (ethology and comparative cognition). But the emergence of a genuinely evolutionary psychology of humans (HEP) has been a slow, painful, and quite recent occurrence, marked at last by the publication of a flagship volume, The Adapted Mind. This work is of great importance not only for researchers in all branches of human psychology, but also for those in the field of adaptive behavior as well, because it demonstrates that the operation of even the most sophisticated and seemingly general behavioral system we know of -- the human brain -- can only be understood as the conglomeration of a great variety of specific mental mechanisms, each finely tuned to a particular adaptive problem.
    [Show full text]
  • Education and the New Sciences of Human Nature: How Evolutionary Psychology Can Inform the Education of Young People Charles Smith and Kevin Goff
    Journal of Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives in Education Vol. 3, No. 1 (May 2010), 9-18 Education and the New Sciences of Human Nature: How Evolutionary Psychology Can Inform the Education of Young People Charles Smith and Kevin Goff The driving purpose of the entire educational Social Constructionism versus an Integrated enterprise is to cultivate changes in the cognitive Causal Model capacities, conceptual schemata, character, and In a seminal 1992 paper, anthropologist John conduct of young people. Underlying this mission is Tooby and psychologist Leda Cosmides – vanguard a deep optimism that educational environments and proponents of the emerging field of evolutionary experiences can shape and reshape a student’s psychology – heralded the approaching “twilight of developmental trajectory. Of course, every student, learning as a social science explanation”: no matter how young, comes to school already molded in important ways by parents, peers, and Advocates of the Standard Social Science prevailing cultural norms. Thus each student’s Model have believed for nearly a century that developmental trajectory always bears a certain they have a solid explanation for how the social inertia, a socially-conditioned momentum, that world inserts organization into the psychology educators must not only seize upon, but also of the developing individual….Individuals redirect and sometimes even counteract. Just as “learn” their language, they “learn” their engineers develop technologies that both utilize and culture, they “learn” to walk, and so on. All contend with the physical forces of inertia and problems – whether they are long-enduring momentum, so do educational researchers strive to adaptive problems or evolutionarily engineer potent practices that both employ and unprecedented problems – are solved by combat social forces, with the goal of sculpting the “learning”….Of course, as most cognitive thought and behavior of young people.
    [Show full text]
  • LEDA COSMIDES Focus of Research Employment Education Honors
    LEDA COSMIDES Department of Psychology Born May 7, 1957 University of California Philadelphia, PA Santa Barbara, CA 93106 tel: (805) 893-8720 fax: 805-965-1163 [email protected] Focus of Research Evolutionary psychology and cognitive science. Using evolutionary theory to develop computational theories of adaptive information-processing problems. Testing for presence of evolutionarily predicted information-processing mechanisms, their neural basis, and cultural sequelae. Empirical work focuses on cooperation, threat, coalitional psychology, incest avoidance, intuitive statistics. Employment 2000- Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara 1994-2000 Associate Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara 1994- Affiliate, Dept. of Anthropology, University of California, Santa Barbara 1994- Co-Director, Center for Evolutionary Psychology, UCSB (1994-present) 1991-1994 Assistant Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara 1990-1991 Visiting Assistant Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara 1989-1990 Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences. Stanford, CA. Education Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts A.B. Biology, 1979 (magna cum laude). Advisor: Robert L. Trivers. Senior Honors Thesis: "Mental Rotation in Pigeons", R.J. Herrnstein, advisor. A.M. Psychology, 1984. Ph.D. Psychology, 1985. Department of Psychology & Social Relations. Major: Cognition. Minors: Cognitive development, Evolutionary biology. Adviser: Sheldon H. White. Stanford University Stanford, California Postdoctoral Scholar, Department of Psychology (1985-9). Focus: Evolution and cognition. Adviser: Roger N. Shepard. Honors 2005 Recipient, NIH Director’s Pioneer Award (top 13 out of ~840 biomedical nominees) 2004 Finalist, NIH Director’s Pioneer Award (top 21 out of 1300+ biomedical nominees) 1999-2000Fellow, John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • 493 the Evolutionary Foundation of Perceiving
    Behavior and Philosophy, 32, 493-502 (2004) © 2004 Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies THE EVOLUTIONARY FOUNDATION OF PERCEIVING ONE’S OWN EMOTIONS Sarah L. Strout Rosemarie I. Sokol James D. Laird Nicholas S. Thompson Program in Social, Evolutionary, and Cultural Psychology Clark University ABSTRACT: Much research in the field of emotions has shown that people differ in the cues that they use to perceive their own emotions. People who are more responsive to personal cues (personal cuers) make use of cues arising from their own bodies and behavior; people who are less responsive to personal cues (situational cuers) make use of cues arising from the world around them. An evolutionary explanation of this well- documented phenomenon is that it occurs because of the operation of a cognitive module designed to enable the organism to predict its own impending behavior. This theory suggests that situational cuers would be people for whom external factors are the best source of information about their own future behavior, whereas personal cuers are people for whom cues about themselves are the best source of information about their own future behavior. Such a view is founded in the New Realist philosophy of the early twentieth century, a philosophy that affected psychology through the work of E. C. Tolman and J. J. Gibson. Key words: emotion, self-perception, evolutionary psychology, new realism The object of this paper is to offer an evolutionary psychological explanation of individual differences in emotion self-perception. Because the idea that our emotions are something that we ourselves must perceive is already philosophically controversial, this project requires that we revive New Realism.
    [Show full text]
  • SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Michaelmas 2020 Dr Michael Biggs
    SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Michaelmas 2020 Dr Michael Biggs Theoretical Perspectives 2. Evolutionary psychology http://users.ox.ac.uk/~sfos0060/ SociologicalTheory.shtml Introduction Charles Darwin (1871): ‘the difference in mind between man and the higher animals, great as it is, is certainly one of degree and not of kind’ Observational primate studies, esp. chimpanzees, reveal complex—and familiar?—social life (e.g. de Waal 1982) Evolutionary psychology Sociologists are vehemently anti-Darwinian, but this complements rational choice— • individualistic • does not assume rational calculation • gives an account of desires, including social preferences, e.g. sexual jealousy even if wrong, cannot ignore! Principles • Ultimately human behaviour evolved to maximize reproduction—to maximize individual’s genes surviving to the next generation, including genes shared with relatives (inclusive fitness) • Proximately • desires • sexual desire—contraception enables this to be divorced from reproduction (Symons in Barkow et al. 1992) • beliefs processed by specialized mental modules, analogous to Chomsky’s language • unconscious perception: e.g. detecting cheating (Cosmides & Tooby in Barkow et al. 1992; Cosmides, Barrett, & Tooby 2010) Wason test (Cosmides & Tooby in Barkow et al. 1992) • Test hypothesis: If card shows an even number on one face, then its reverse will be red • Enforce rule: if person is drinking beer, then s/he must be over 20 years old • Desires are universal across all cultures— but crucial differences between male and female (Bateman’s principle) • females invest more in offspring, therefore more choosey about mates • males compete for females; inequality in number of mates and offspring • Desires/perceptions were adaptive in the ancestral environment: Pleistocene foragers (1.8m to 10k YA) • e.g.
    [Show full text]