IS INTENTIONALITY DEPENDENT UPON CONSCIOUSNESS? the Mental Features Two Remarkable Aspects: Intentionality and Consciousness. In

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

IS INTENTIONALITY DEPENDENT UPON CONSCIOUSNESS? the Mental Features Two Remarkable Aspects: Intentionality and Consciousness. In URIAH KRIEGEL IS INTENTIONALITY DEPENDENT UPON CONSCIOUSNESS? (Received in revised version 5 February 2003) ABSTRACT. It is often assumed that consciousness and intentionality are two mutually independent aspects of mental life. When the assumption is denounced, it usually gives way to the claim that consciousness is somehow dependent upon intentionality. The possibility that intentionality may be dependent upon consciousness is rarely entertained. Recently, however, John Searle and Colin McGinn have argued for just such dependence. In this paper, I reconstruct and evaluate their argumentation. I am in sympathy both with their view and with the lines of argument they employ in its defense. Unlike Searle and McGinn, however, I am quite attached to a naturalist approach to intentionality. It will turn out to be somewhat difficult to reconcile naturalism with the notion that intentionality is dependent upon consciousness, although, perhaps surprisingly, I will argue that McGinn’s case for such dependence is compatible with naturalism. 1. INTRODUCTION: DEPENDENCE RELATIONS BETWEEN CONSCIOUSNESS AND INTENTIONALITY The mental features two remarkable aspects: intentionality and consciousness. Intentionality is the property in virtue of which a subject’s mental state is directed at, or is about, something other than itself. Consciousness is the property in virtue of which there issomething it is like for the subject to be in that mental state.1 In the short history of the philosophy of mind, intentionality and consciousness have often been treated as mutually independent. Call this the Independence Assumption. One way to formulate the Independence Assumption is in terms of the following pair of theses: (1) The fact that a mental state M is intentional does not entail any (non-disjunctive, non-necessary) facts regard- ing consciousness. Philosophical Studies 116: 271–307, 2003. © 2003 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 272 URIAH KRIEGEL (2) The fact that a mental state M is conscious does not entail any (non-disjunctive, non-necessary) facts regard- ing intentionality.2,3,4 The Independence Assumption can be construed as the conjunction of (1) and (2). Support for the Independence Assumption has been eroded in recent years. The erosion of (2) has been especially prominent: many philosophers have argued that a subject’s mental state is conscious when, and only when, the subject instantiates a certain intentional structure. Thus, according to the representational theory of consciousness (defended, e.g., by Dretske and Tye), if a mental state M is conscious, then M must have a certain specific kind of intentional content.5 The representational theory claims, then, that: (3) The fact that M is conscious entails the fact that M has intentional content of kind K. This is incompatible with (2), since the fact that M has inten- tional content of kind K is a (non-disjunctive, non-necessary) fact regarding intentionality. Similarly, according to the higher-order monitoring theory of consciousness (defended, e.g., by Armstrong and Rosenthal), if M is conscious, then M must be itself the intentional object of a higher-order intentional state.6 This theory claims, then, that: (4) The fact that subject x’s mental state M is conscious entails the fact that x has another mental state, M*, such that M* is intentionally directed at M. Which is, again, incompatible with (2), since the fact that x has a mental state M* that is intentionally directed at M is a (non- disjunctive, non-necessary) fact regarding intentionality. Both the representational and higher-order monitoring theories attempt a reductive account of consciousness in terms of intention- ality, and therefore imply the falsity of (2). But a reductive account of consciousness in terms of intentionality is not required in order to falsify (2). It is possible to hold, for instance, that even though M’s consciousness is not exhausted by M’s intentional content, it nonetheless necessarily involves an intentionality.7 Such a view is also incompatible with (2). IS INTENTIONALITY DEPENDENT UPON CONSCIOUSNESS? 273 Although many philosophers accept today the dependence of consciousness on intentionality, few think that, conversely, or inversely, intentionality is dependent on consciousness. At the same time, arguments to this effect have been advanced by a handful of philosophers. In this paper, I reconstruct and evaluate two such arguments, due to John Searle (1992, ch. 7)8 and Colin McGinn (1988).9 These arguments are sometimes quite complex (as in the case of Searle) and sometimes turn on subtle phenomenological observations (as in the case of McGinn). The challenge will be twofold, then: to extricate clear lines of argument from the texts, and to clarify the basic observations and distinctions behind them. On the way, I also want to get clear on just what the dependence of intentionality upon consciousness is suggested to consist in. In §2, I discuss Searle’s line of argument. Since Searle’s argument is fairly complex, I will focus on trying to reconstruct it in a precise manner. In §3, I discuss McGinn’s argument. Since it relies crucially on a certain phenomenological observation, I will mainly try to bring out this observation in a decently vivid way. My conclusions will not be dramatic. My overall impression is that the thesis that intentionality depends upon consciousness merits a more serious consideration than it has been hitherto granted. More specifically, I will suggest that some versions of this thesis are compatible with a naturalistic approach to intentionality, and should therefore be unobjectionable to a naturalist. 2. SEARLE’S ARGUMENT FROM THE ASPECTUALITY OF INTENTIONALITY In The Rediscovery of the Mind, Searle (1992, p. 132) writes: I now want to make a very strong claim ...The claim is this: Only a being that could have conscious intentional states could have intentional states at all, and every unconscious intentional state is at least potentially conscious. This thesis ... has the consequence that a complete theory of intentionality requires an account of consciousness. This passage all but explicitly rejects (1). To reject (1) is to hold: (5) The fact that a mental state M is intentional entails some (non-disjunctive, non-necessary) facts regarding consciousness. 274 URIAH KRIEGEL (5) leaves open what the entailed facts regarding consciousness are. Different entailments of facts define different forms of dependence, and therefore, different dependence theses. The quoted passage contains, in fact, two dependence theses. The first is the thesis that “only a being that could have conscious intentional states could have intentional states at all.”10 We may formulate this thesis as follows: (6) The fact that a mental state M of a subject x is intentional entails that x can have a mental state M*, such that M* is a conscious state. On a liberal enough understanding of “facts,” (6) entails (5).11 Searle’s second thesis is that “every unconscious intentional state is at least potentially conscious,” which we may formulate as follows: (7) Thefact that a mentalstate M is intentionalentails that M is potentially conscious. But what is involved in a mental state being potentially conscious? Potential consciousness means, for Searle, that M is in principle accessible to consciousness, where being accessible to conscious- ness in principle means that it must be “the sort of thing that could be ... conscious” (1992, p. 153; italics mine).12 This elucidation leaves something to be desired, but it appears to imply that M’s being intentional entails that it is possibly conscious. The question is what modal strength should this “possibly” be construed to carry.13 Metaphysical possibility is too weak. Arguably, it is metaphys- ically possible for an ameba to be conscious. So given that what is metaphysically possible is necessarily metaphysically possible (at 14 least in S4 and S5) and that necessary facts are entailed by all other facts, any random fact entails the metaphysical possibility of the ameba being conscious. Thus, the fact that a certain ameba is 7 microns long entails that it is metaphysically possible for this ameba to be conscious. But surely this does not define a genuine dependence of 7 micron length on consciousness.15 More to the point, M’s being metaphysically-possibly conscious appears to be a purely logical property (or perhaps a “metaphysical” property) of it,16 rather than a genuinely psychological property. But what Searle hopes to capture in saying that M must be poten- IS INTENTIONALITY DEPENDENT UPON CONSCIOUSNESS? 275 tially conscious is a psychological property of M. My suggestion is that we construe potential consciousness in terms of possible consciousness consistent with the laws of psychology. To say that M is potentially conscious is to say that M’s not being conscious is not a matter of the laws of psychology, but just happens to be the case. That is, M is potentially conscious iff there is a possible world W, such that the laws of psychology in W are the same as in the actual world, and M is conscious in W. If this condition holds, we may say that it is a psychological possibility that M be conscious. (7) then unpacks into: (8) The fact that M is intentional entails that M is psycho- logically-possibly conscious. That is, the fact that M is intentional entails that it is psychologically possible for M to be conscious.17 Note now two things about the logical strength of (7) and (8). First, they entail (5), since M’s being potentially conscious, or psychologically-possibly conscious, is a (non-disjunctive, non- necessary) fact regarding consciousness.18 But second, they also entail (6): if M’s being intentional entails that M is potentially conscious, or psychologically-possibly conscious, then a fortiori it entails that x can have a conscious state – for then x can have M consciously.
Recommended publications
  • Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin
    Journal of Undergraduate Research at Minnesota State University, Mankato Volume 6 Article 5 2006 Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin Ryan Feldbrugge Minnesota State University, Mankato Follow this and additional works at: https://cornerstone.lib.mnsu.edu/jur Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Feldbrugge, Ryan (2006) "Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin," Journal of Undergraduate Research at Minnesota State University, Mankato: Vol. 6 , Article 5. Available at: https://cornerstone.lib.mnsu.edu/jur/vol6/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate Research Center at Cornerstone: A Collection of Scholarly and Creative Works for Minnesota State University, Mankato. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Undergraduate Research at Minnesota State University, Mankato by an authorized editor of Cornerstone: A Collection of Scholarly and Creative Works for Minnesota State University, Mankato. Feldbrugge: Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin INTENTIONALITY IN KANT AND WITTGENSTEIN Ryan Feldbrugge (Philosophy) Dr. Richard Liebendorfer, Faculty Mentor, Philosophy How is thought about and experience of a world possible? This has been the framing question of the present work and it is generally understood as the problem of intentionality. The more specific problem dealt with has been whether or not intentionality has an internal structure that can be made explicit through science, particularly cognitive science. In his Critique of Pure Reason, Immanuel Kant outlines an internal, mental structure that, when imposed on our sensory data, makes thought about and experience of a world possible, which can be viewed as highly anticipatory of modern cognitive science. On the other hand, there are a number of philosophers who have it that the structure of intentionality cannot be made explicit nor can it be understood within science, notably Ludwig Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • Intentionality and the Mental Volume IV, Number 4 (Winter 1957)
    Paul E. Meehl we have a formula, and a case comes along in which it disagrees with ------APPENDIX------ our heads? Shall we then use our heads? I would say, yes-provided the psychological situation is as clear as a broken leg; otherwise, very, very seldom. EDITORS' NOTE. This article first appeared in the Tournal of Counseling Psychology, Intentionality and the Mental Volume IV, Number 4 (Winter 1957). For the assignment of copyright, we are grateful to the editor, C. Gilbert Wrenn. REFERENCES I. Cronbach, L. J., and P. E. Meehl. "Construct yalidity in Psy.chological Tests," Psychological Bulletin, 52:281-302 (1955). Reprmted m H. Fe1gl and M. Scnv~n Introduction by Wilfrid Sellars (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. I, pp. 174-204. Mm­ The traditional mind-body problem is, as Herbert Feig] has amply demonstrated in neapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1956. his contribution to this volume, a veritable tangle of tangles. At first sight but one of 2. Humphreys, L. G., C. C. McArthur, P. E. Meehl, N. Sanford, ~nd _ J. Zubin. the 'problems of philosophy,' it soon turns out, as one picks at it, to be nothin& more "Clinical versus Actuarial Prediction," Proceedings of the 1955 Invitational Con- nor less than the philosophical enterprise as a whole. Yet if, to the close-up view. of ference on Testing Problems, pp. 91-141. the philosopher at work, it soon becomes a bewildering crisscross of th.r~ds l.eadmg 3. McArthur, C. C. "Analyzing the Clinical Process," Tournal of Counselmg Psy­ in all directions, it is possible to discern, on standing off, a number of d1stmgmshable chology, 1:203-207 (1954).
    [Show full text]
  • So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research?
    The Qualitative Report Volume 24 Number 4 How To Article 15 4-22-2019 So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research? Katherine E. Soule University of California, Agriculture and Natural Resources Division, [email protected] Melissa Freeman University of Georgia, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://nsuworks.nova.edu/tqr Part of the Educational Assessment, Evaluation, and Research Commons, Quantitative, Qualitative, Comparative, and Historical Methodologies Commons, and the Social Statistics Commons Recommended APA Citation Soule, K. E., & Freeman, M. (2019). So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research?. The Qualitative Report, 24(4), 857-872. https://doi.org/10.46743/2160-3715/2019.3305 This How To Article is brought to you for free and open access by the The Qualitative Report at NSUWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Qualitative Report by an authorized administrator of NSUWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research? Abstract In this article, phenomenology, both in its philosophical and methodological variants, is introduced in the form of a fictional dialogue between a student justifying her interest in using a post-intentional phenomenological approach in her dissertation to her major professor. The dialogue tackles founding philosophers, notably Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty; contemporary researchers, including A. Giorgi, B. Giorgi, van Manen, and Vagle; several phenomenological concepts, such as intentionality, bracketing, and bridling; and provides examples of three distinct approaches to phenomenological research. Keywords Phenomenology, Post-Intentional Phenomenology, Bridling, Bracketing, Intentionality Creative Commons License This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 4.0 International License.
    [Show full text]
  • Transparency of Mind: the Contributions of Descartes, Leibniz, and Berkeley to the Genesis of the Modern Subject
    Transparency of Mind: The Contributions of Descartes, Leibniz, and Berkeley to the Genesis of the Modern Subject Gary Hat! eld Philosophers often use classical positions as paradigms for de! ning their own views, usually in contrast. In the philosophy of mind, the notion of the Cartesian subject is one such paradigm. This notion is often used to represent tendencies in the conception of the subject that today’s philosophers wish to avoid. John McDowell and Hilary Putnam 1, among others, portray the Cartesian subject – and speci! cally the Cartesian mind – as a step backward from an earlier, preferable Aristotelianism, whose concept of mind might be made serviceable today if adjusted to ! t modern science. Such paradigms, whose use is unavoidable, are typically caricatures, whether slight or gross. The Cartesian mind as standardly portrayed by McDowell, Putnam, and oth- ers 2 is a gross caricature. This would be important enough for its potential to mislead us about the actual historical development of philosophy. But even more crucially for the philosophy of mind, the use of a caricatured picture as a counterparadigm against which one de! nes one’s own, comparatively better position, can lead to a pyrrhic vic- tory that avoids or misrepresents the real problems. If the opponent has been tailored to one’s desired virtues as conquering hero, one may give the impression that one’s own position solves great problems, deeply embedded in the tradition, when in fact one has simply rejected a fairly recent problematic position, which one has perhaps also misun- derstood and misidenti! ed. 3 The Cartesian mental paradigm is frequently de! ned in terms of four factors: con- sciousness as essence, intentionality as exclusively mental, the veil of perception, and the transparency of mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Intentionality *
    Ronald McIntyre and David Woodruff Smith, “Theory of Intentionality,” in J. N. Mohanty and William R. McKenna, eds., Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook (Washington, D. C.: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology and University Press of America, 1989), pp. 147-79. Original page numbers are in <>. THEORY OF INTENTIONALITY * by Ronald McIntyre and David Woodruff Smith 1. INTENTIONALITY Intentionality is a central concept in philosophy of mind and in Husserl’s phenom­ enology. Indeed, Husserl calls intentionality the “fundamental property of consciousness” and the “principle theme of phenomenology”. Although ‘intentionality’ is a technical term in philosophy, it stands for something familiar to us all: a characteristic feature of our mental states and experiences, especially evident in what we commonly call being “conscious” or “aware”. As conscious beings, or persons, we are not merely affected by the things in our environment; we are also conscious of these things – of physical objects and events, of our own selves and other persons, of abstract objects such as numbers and propositions, and of anything else we bring before our minds. Many, perhaps most, of the events that make up our mental life – our perceptions, thoughts, beliefs, hopes, fears, and so on – have this characteristic feature of being “of” or “about” something and so giving us a sense of something in our world. When I see a tree, for example, my perception is a perception of a tree; when I think that 3 + 2 = 5, I am thinking of or about certain numbers and a relation among them; when I hope that nuclear war will never take place, my hope is about a possible future state of the world; and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • A Naturalistic Perspective on Intentionality. Interview with Daniel Dennett
    Mind & Society, 6, 2002, Vol. 3, pp. 1-12 2002, Rosenberg & Sellier, Fondazione Rosselli A naturalistic perspective on intentionality. Interview with Daniel Dennett by Marco Mirolli Marco Mirolli You describe yourself as a philosopher of mind and you reject the exhortations to get more involved in the abstract problems of ontology and of philosophy of science in general, even if the problems of the philosophy of mind and those of philosophy of science are deeply mutually dependent. I think this is an important issue because, while you say that your philosophy presupposes only the standard scientific ontology and epistemology 1, it seems to me that what you really presuppose is rather a Quinean view of ontology and epistemology, which is not so standard, even if it may well be the one we should accept. Daniel Dennett Well, maybe so, let's see. Certainly I have seen almost no reason to adopt any other ontology than Quine's; and when I look at the work in the phi- losophy of science and more particularly at the work in science, I do not find any ground yet for abandoning a Quinean view of ontology for something fancier. It could happen, but I haven't seen any reason for doing this; so if you want to say that I am vulnerable on this, that's really true. I have stated that I don't see any of the complexities of science or philosophy of mind raising ontological issues that are more sophisticated than those a Quinean ontology could handle; but I may be wrong.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Problem of Intentionality: a Cardinal Difficulty for Physicalism Or What Happens to the World When a Mind Shows Up? Joel S
    The Problem of Intentionality: A Cardinal Difficulty for Physicalism Or What Happens to the World When a Mind Shows Up? Joel Steinmetz I. What is the Socratic Club? • Content: Issues related to the truth or falsity of the Christian faith • Method: In the Socratic spirit to follow the argument wherever it leads • Motivation: “In any fairly large and talkative community such as a university there is always the danger that those who think alike should gravitate together into coteries where they will henceforth encounter opposition only in the emasculated form of rumour that the outsiders say thus and thus. The absent are easily refuted, complacent dogmatism thrives, and differences of opinion are embittered by group hostility. Each group hears not the best, but the worst, that the other group can say. In the Socratic all this was changed. Here a man could get the case for Christianity without all the paraphernalia of pietism and the case against it without the irrelevant sansculottisme of our common anti-God weeklies. At the very least we helped civilize one another…. Everyone found how little he had known about everyone else.”1 II. What is the problem of intentionality (a brief historical intro)? • The way in which intentionality is understood, or the aspect of intentionality that is emphasized, focuses the way in which intentionality is problematic. Analytic vs. Continental divide: • Phenomenology: explain the essential structures of intentionality; how does objectivity arise from subjectivity? • Analytic: intentionality is mark of mental; how can we explain, or incorporate, intentional mental states into a physicalist account of the world? • Why a physicalist account of the world? “These days we’re all materialists for much the reason that Churchill gave for being a democrat: the alternatives seem even worse.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between Consciousness and Intentionality
    University of Central Florida STARS HIM 1990-2015 2013 The relationship between consciousness and intentionality Jordan Bell University of Central Florida Part of the Philosophy Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015 University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in HIM 1990-2015 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Bell, Jordan, "The relationship between consciousness and intentionality" (2013). HIM 1990-2015. 1384. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015/1384 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN CONSCIOUSNESS AND INTENTIONALITY by JORDAN BELL A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Arts & Humanities and in The Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term 2013 Thesis Chair: Dr. Mason Cash ABSTRACT Within the Philosophy of Mind two features of our mental life have been acknowledged as the most perplexing—consciousness, the phenomenal “what it is likeness” of our mental states, and intentionality, the aboutness or directedness of our mental states. As such, it has become commonplace to develop theories about these phenomena which seek to explain them naturalistically, that is, without resort to magic or miracles. Traditionally this has been done by analyzing consciousness and intentionality apart from one another. However, in more recent years the tide has turned. In contemporary theories these phenomena are typically analyzed in terms of the other.
    [Show full text]
  • Concrete Possible Worlds (Final)
    CONCRETE POSSIBLE WORLDS Phillip Bricker 1. INTRODUCTION. Open a book or article of contemporary analytic philosophy, and you are likely to find talk of possible worlds therein. This applies not only to analytic metaphysics, but to areas as diverse as philosophy of language, philosophy of science, epistemology, and ethics. Philosophers agree, for the most part, that possible worlds talk is extremely useful for explicating concepts and formulating theories. They disagree, however, over its proper interpretation. In this chapter, I discuss the view, championed by David Lewis, that philosophers’ talk of possible worlds is the literal truth.1 There exists a plurality of worlds. One of these is our world, the actual world, the physical universe that contains us and all our surroundings. The others are merely possible worlds containing merely possible beings, such as flying pigs and talking donkeys. But the other worlds are no less real or concrete for being merely possible. Fantastic? Yes! What could motivate a philosopher to believe such a tale? I start, as is customary, with modality.2 Truths about the world divide into two sorts: categorical and modal. Categorical truths describe how things are, what is actually the case. Modal truths describe how things could or must be, what is possibly or 1 The fullest statement of Lewis’s theory of possible worlds is contained in his magnum opus, Lewis (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Lewis’s view is sometimes called “modal realism.” 2 Historically, it was the attempt to provide semantics for modal logic that catapulted possible worlds to the forefront of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
    INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON
    [Show full text]
  • Monism P16ff
    1 Intentionality in Mullā Ṣadrā Submitted by Sümeyye Parıldar to the University of Exeter as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Arab and Islamic Studies In June 2014 This thesis is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this thesis which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. Signature: ………………………………………………………….. 2 ABSTRACT The present study reconstructs psychological, linguistic and ontological aspects of Mullā Ṣadrā’s philosophy in the light of Brentano’s theory of intentionality. Brentano used intentionality as a psychological term to denote the ‘mental’ as opposed to the ‘natural’. Later, with Meinong, intentionality took an ontological commitment to assenting that ‘there are things that do not exist’. The chapters that discuss Ṣadrā’s philosophy reflect the two aspects with an investigation for the production process of intentional objects and an investigation of the status of these objects in ontology. The main aim of the research is to give an internalist and monist account for the nature of intentionality demonstrating an alternative approach to the concepts of existence and the soul. Ontologically, there is only one reality (existence) and nothing is left outside it. Accordingly, intentional objects are mental beings that are at a lower level of existence (wujūd ẓillī). The principles behind the monist ontology are: first, the gradational ontology (tashkīk) that all things are determined beings (mutamayyiz) and they are manifestations of a single reality at different levels of intensity (mutashakkik), and, second, the simplicity principle (basīṭ al-ḥaqīqa) in which existence is a simple reality that comprehends all beings whilst being the principle of multiplicity at the same time.
    [Show full text]
  • Materialism and the Logical Structure of Intentionality
    5 Materialism and the Logical Structure of Intentionality George Bealer This paper begins with a brief history of the thesis of intention­ ality and a review of some contemporary views. Following that, we present a problem for materialism that arises in connection with the possibility of a general materialist analysis (or reduction) of intentionality: if no such analysis (reduction) is possible, inten­ tional phenomena would have at least one non-physical property, namely, their intentionality-this materialistically unanalysable general property. With this problem in mind, we will then suggest a general analysis of intentionality. We close by arguing that any satisfactory general analysis of intentionality must share a certain central feature with the proposed analysis and that this feature entails the existence of an objective level of organization that is non­ physical. This is enough to show that the traditional materialist world view is mistaken. One way in which this argument against materialism is novel is that it would go through even if, per impos­ sibile, every particular type of mental phenomenon (pain, belief, etc.) had a materialist analysis (reduction).1 i. A Brief History Contemporary philosophical discussions of intentionality may be traced to the following famous passage by Franz Brentano (1838- 1917) in a chapter of Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt (1874) entitled 'The Distinction Between Mental and Physical Phenomena': 'Our intention is to use "materialism" in conformity with its traditional mean­ ing. Some contemporary philosophers use the term in a diluted way. In conse­ quence, some of the philosophers who now call themselves 'materialists' might accept the views defended in this paper.
    [Show full text]