The Theory of Common Morality of Bernard Gert

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Theory of Common Morality of Bernard Gert See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/335875979 The Theory of Common Morality of Bernard Gert Article · August 2019 DOI: 10.26512/rbb.v15i1.26866 CITATIONS READS 0 17 3 authors: Flávio Rocha Lima Paranhos Volnei Garrafa Pontifícia Universidade Católica de Goiás (PUC Goiás) University of Brasília 27 PUBLICATIONS 134 CITATIONS 217 PUBLICATIONS 1,059 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE Jan Helge Solbakk University of Oslo 79 PUBLICATIONS 633 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Persistents Situation in Bioethics View project Conceptual Basis of Bioethics View project All content following this page was uploaded by Flávio Rocha Lima Paranhos on 25 September 2019. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. Artigo Original Paranhos, Garrafa, Solbakk. Rev Bras Bioética 2019;15(e2):1-14 The Theory of Common Morality of Bernard Gert A Teoria da Moralidade Comum de Bernard Gert Resumo: Tom L. Beauchamp e James F. Childress têm lançado mão de forma crescente de uma teoria moral conhecida como “teoria da moralidade comum” como base filosófica para a sua abordagem de quatro princípios para a ética biomédica, atualmente conhecida como principialismo. Na última edição (2013) de seus Principles of Biomedical Ethics, os autores reconhecem a contribuição de alguns teóricos anteriores da moralidade comum. Bernard Gert, um crítico do principialismo, é um deles. O objetivo deste artigo é apresentar uma análise crítica da teoria da moralidade comum de Gert, desenvolvida em seu livro Common Morality. Deciding Flávio R. L. Paranhos What to Do (2004). de acordo com Gert, a moralidade comum é um sistema Escola de Ciências Médicas, moral que todos usam implicitamente ao tomar decisões e julgamentos. Farmacêuticas e Biomédicas da PUC Tal sistema consistiria, basicamente, de regras morais, ideais morais e um Goiás, Goiânia, Goiás, Brasil procedimento de duas etapas usado intuitivamente por cada pessoa para [email protected] decidir se uma determinada violação de uma regra ou ideal é legítimo. Há dez regras morais, que podem ser agrupadas em duas básicas, a saber, não causar danos (não matar; não cause dor; não desabilite; não privar Volnei Garrafa a liberdade; não privar de prazer), e não violar a confiança (não enganar; Centro Internacional de Bioética manter suas promessas; não trapaciar; obedecer à lei; fazer o seu dever). e Humanidades / Cátedra Unesco As regras morais se aplicam aos agentes morais, que são constituídos de Bioética / Programa de Pós- por todos os seres humanos capazes de compreender plenamente as regras morais, bem como prever as consequências de sua eventual Graduação em Bioética da UnB, violação. Apesar do apelo intuitivo da abordagem de Gert, bem como Brasília, DF, Brasil de Beauchamp e Childress, a teoria da moralidade comum tem algumas [email protected] falhas fundamentais que são discutidos no artigo. Keywords: bioética, fundamentação filosófica, teoria moral, moralidade comum, regras morais, principialismo, Bernard Gert. Jan Helge Solbakk Center for Medical Ethics, Institute of Abstract: Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress have been increasingly using a moral theory known as “Theory of Common Morality” Health and Society, University of Oslo, as a philosophical basis for their four principle approach to biomedical Oslo, Norway ethics, currently known as principlism. In the latest edition (2013) of their [email protected] Principles of Biomedical Ethics, they acknowledge the contribution of some previous theorists of common morality. Bernard Gert, a critic of principlism, is one of them. The aim of this paper is to provide a critical analysis of Gert’s Theory of Common Morality, as developed in his book Common Morality. Deciding What to Do (2004). According to Gert, common morality is a moral system that everyone uses implicitly when making decisions and judgments. This system consists, basically, of moral rules, moral ideals and a two-step procedure used intuitively by every person to decide whether a given violation of a rule or ideal is legitimate. There are ten moral rules, which can be collapsed into two basic ones, Do not cause harm (Do not kill; Do not cause pain; Do not disable; Do not deprive of freedom; Do not deprive of pleasure), and Do not violate the trust (Do not deceive; Keep your promises; Do not cheat; Obey the law; Do your duty). Moral rules apply to moral agents, which are constituted by all humans able to fully understand the moral rules, as well as predict the consequences of their eventual violation. It is our understanding that, despite the highly intuitive appeal of Gert’s approach, as well as of Beauchamp and Childress’s, the Theory of Common Morality has some fundamental flaws which are discussed in the article. Keywords: bioethics, philosophical grounding, moral theory, common morality, moral rules, principlism, Bernard Gert. Artigo Original Paranhos, Garrafa, Solbakk. Rev Bras Bioética 2019;15(e2):1-14 Introduction Since the fourth edition of the Principles of Biomedical Ethics, Beauchamp and Childress have been using, increasingly, a moral theory known as “Theory of Common Morality” (TCM) as a basis for a defense and theoretical underpinning of principlism. In the 7th and latest edition of their book (2013), the authors devote several chapters to the justification of their four principle approach to biomedical ethics. The first and last chapters are particularly devoted to the presentation and development of TCM. In the first chapter of this latest edition the authors recognize that they are not the only ones to avail themselves of such a theory. In a note, they acknowledge that “although there is only one common universal morality, there is more than one theory of common morality” (Beauchamp and Childress 2013, p.25-26).Among the authors cited, one is particularly interesting - Bernard Gert, since he was critic of principlism. In the last chapter of the same edition, Beauchamp and Childress (2013, p.393- 397) try to elaborate their TCM, when, again, they cite (this time more thoroughly) the ideas of Gert. It is noteworthy, however, that the authors do not disagree fundamen- tally with the ideas proposed by Gert about TCM, but only with his criticism of their principlism (Beauchamp and Childress 2013, p.394): Like us, they understand the common morality as universal morality that is not on the cultures, individuals, religions or professional associ- ations. However, Gert and colleagues reject both the language and the substance of our account of principles, while putting forward their own impartial rules and moral ideals as a superior and alternative frame- work in biomedical ethics. Later on, the authors turn to the TCM of Gert again, this time to agree with him to the extent that they consider there is no reason why the standards of common morality cannot be justified by a general ethical theory, even though Gert himself has not been able to do this conclusively (Beauchamp and Childress 2013, p.419). Although Beauchamp & Childress demonstrate a growing interest in developing a moral theory that might provide an appropriate epistemological foundation for their approach, they fall short of the achievements of Gert. The aim of this paper is to pro- vide a critical analysis of Gert’s Theory of Common Morality (TCM), as developed in his book Common Morality. Deciding What to Do (2004). 2 Artigo Original Paranhos, Garrafa, Solbakk. Rev Bras Bioética 2019;15(e2):1-14 On the term “common morality” The expression “common morality” may appear with different meanings depend- ing on the chosen approach of different authors, as well as their original intention in using the term. In his book, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, whose first edition was published in 1780, Jeremy Bentham, one of the founding fa- thers of utilitarianism, presents his proposal of a “principle of utility”, which, according to the author, is nothing more than the principle which approves or disapproves of ev- ery action that seems to increase or decrease the happiness of those whose interest is in question (Bentham 2007, p.2). Bentham, then, discusses the principles contrary to the principle of utility. These are basically of two types: asceticism and sympathy/antipathy. While the principle of utility, which Bentham considers an objective one, since it uses a criterion external to the moral agent, the principle of sympathy/antipathy is subjective since it rests only in the disposition to approve or disapprove something (Bentham 2007, p.13-17). In a footnote to paragraph XIV, concerning the principle of sympathy/antipathy, Bentham refers to the “moral sense” and “common sense”. His description of what is “common sense” has some striking similarities with that of Gert’s, although the latter has solemnly ignored this line of Bentham’s thought (Gert cites Bentham four times, but none of them makes reference to his idea of the morality of common sense): He then tells you, that his common sense teaches him what is right and wrong (...), meaning, by common sense, a sense of some kind or other, which, he says, is possessed by all mankind. (...) But common sense is as old as the creation; and there is no man but would be ashamed to be thought not to have as much of it as his neighbors. (...) Another comes, and says, that (...) however he has an understanding, which will do quite as well. This understanding, he says, is the stan- dard of right and wrong. (...) If other men’s understandings differ in any point from his, so much the worse for them: it is a sure sign they are either defective or corrupt (Bentham 2007, p.17). In characterizing the principle of sympathy/antipathy (which he refutes), Bentham provides us with a characterization similar to that of Gert’s to common morality, but he does not use the expression “common morality”.
Recommended publications
  • "On the Moral Relevance of Ignorance to Morality's Demands"
    3 On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality1 Geoffrey Sayre-McCord “It is impossible to overestimate the amount of stupidity in the world.” Bernard Gert2 Introduction In Morality, Bernard Gert argues that the fundamental demands of morality are well articulated by ten distinct, and relatively simple, rules. These rules, he holds, are such that any person, no matter what her circumstances or interests, would be rational in accepting, and guiding her choices by, them. The rules themselves are comfortably familiar (e.g. “Do not kill,” “Do not deceive,” “Keep your promises”) and sit well as intuitively plausible. Yet the rules are not, Gert argues, to be accepted merely because they are intuitively attractive, nor because they are already widely recognized, but because they stand as the only set of rules that can qualify as appropriately acceptable to all rational beings. Two questions naturally arise when confronted with a proposed account of morality’s standards. The first question is: Why believe the account is true? The second question is: Supposing it is true, what reason do people have to accept those standards as guides either for themselves or others? Before turning directly to the details of Gert’s defense of the rules and the accompanying answers he offers to these two questions, it is worth highlighting the different attitudes people have taken toward these questions and the relation answers to them might bear to one another. A fair number of people think that the two questions are completely inde- pendent. One question focuses on what morality demands while the other fo- cuses on the apparently distinct issue of whether, and why, one might rationally accept morality’s demands either as a standard for oneself or for others.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories
    A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Gavin G. Enck June 2009 © 2009 Gavin G. Enck. All Rights Reserved. 2 This thesis titled A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories by GAVIN G. ENCK has been approved for the Department of Philosophy and the College of Arts and Sciences by Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy Benjamin M. Ogles Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 ABSTRACT ENCK, GAVIN G., M.A., June 2009, Philosophy A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories (81 pp.) Director of Thesis: Arthur Zucker This thesis compares two bioethical theories in order to determine which theory is better for use by medical professionals. The two theories are Tom L. Beauchamp and James Childress’s “Principlism” and Bernard Gert, K. Danner Clouser, and Charles M. Culver’s “Moral Rules.” The structure of the paper is as follows: an explication of both theories, an examination of the similarities and differences between the theories, an evaluation of criticisms of both theories, and identification of the three advantages the Moral Rules theory has over Principlism. In the conclusion, I claim the Moral Rules is the better bioethical theory for the medical profession. Approved: _____________________________________________________________ Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy 4 TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Abstract ..............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Challenges
    Ethical Challenges: Building an Ethics Toolkit by Deni Elliott AuthorHouse™ 1663 Liberty Drive, Suite 200 Bloomington, IN 47403 www.authorhouse.com Phone: 1-800-839-8640 © 2009 Deni Elliott. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted by any means without the written permission of the author. First published by AuthorHouse 1/16/2009 ISBN: 978-1-4343-8802-5 (sc) Library of Congress Control Number: 2008904456 Printed in the United States of America Bloomington, Indiana This book is printed on acid-free paper. Dedicated to my real-life sister, Debbie, and to my spiritual sisters Allison, Rose, and Pam, all of whom keep me nourished with their love. v An Introduction to Ethical Challenges Right and wrong. Good and bad. What may I do? What must I do? Which is the best thing to do? Every thinking person grapples with these issues. But most people make their choices haphazardly and hope that things will turn out okay. There is a better way. When people think about the different components involved in ethical decision making, they tend to become better at making tough choices. Their decision making improves in three ways: clarity, consistency, and completeness. Clarity means that people can describe what they are choosing in specific situations and why. It is good to be able to explain one’s choices. Saying, “I did what I felt like doing,” is not an adequate explanation if someone else is suffering because of your choice. If you can explain your reasoning to yourself, you are in a better position to examine the adequacy of your choice and determine how you might want to do things differently in the future.
    [Show full text]
  • Consistency, Common Morality, and Reflective Equilibrium
    BRAND-BALLARD • CONSISTENCY, COMMON MORALITY, REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM Jeffrey Brand-Ballard Consistency, Common Morality, and Reflective Equilibrium ABSTRACT. Biomedical ethicists often assume that common morality consti- tutes a largely consistent normative system. This premise is not taken for granted in general normative ethics. This paper entertains the possibility of inconsistency within common morality and explores methodological implications. Assuming common morality to be inconsistent casts new light on the debate between principlists and descriptivists. One can view the two approaches as complemen- tary attempts to evade or transcend that inconsistency. If common morality proves to be inconsistent, then principlists might have reason to prefer a less pluralistic theory, thereby moving closer to descriptivism. Descriptivists, by contrast, might want to qualify their claim to accommodate all of people’s basic moral convic- tions. Finally, both camps might wish to adopt a more revisionist posture, ac- cepting that an adequate ethical theory occasionally will contradict some of people’s deepest moral convictions. Proper application of the method of reflec- tive equilibrium, to which both descriptivists and principlists claim allegiance, may entail greater openness to revisionism than either camp admits. ne of the liveliest theoretical debates in biomedical ethics re- mains the controversy between “principlists” and O “descriptivists.” In recent years, representatives of the two fac- tions have found some common ground (Beauchamp 1995, pp. 188–90; Gert, Culver, and Clouser 1997, pp. 89–90). Yet each faction continues to insist that the competing approach is flawed, and inferior to its own (Beauchamp and Childress 2001; Gert, Culver, and Clouser 1997). I offer what I expect to be a controversial perspective on this debate.
    [Show full text]
  • Just Consequentialism and Computing
    Ethics and Information Technology 1: 65–69, 1999. © 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Just consequentialism and computing James H. Moor Department of Philosophy, Dartmouth College, NH, USA. E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. Computer and information ethics, as well as other fields of applied ethics, need ethical theories which coherently unify deontological and consequentialist aspects of ethical analysis. The proposed theory of just consequentialism emphasizes consequences of policies within the constraints of justice. This makes just consequentialism a practical and theoretically sound approach to ethical problems of computer and information ethics. Introduction instance of a policy – in this kind of situation such and such action is allowed or required or forbidden. The malleability of computers allows them to be Understanding actions as exemplars of more general used in novel and unexpected ways, ways for which normative prescriptions promotes responsibility and we frequently do not have formulated policies for more careful reflection on conduct. The word “policy” controlling their use.1 Advancing computer techno- is intended to suggest both that there can be justified logy produces policy vacuums in its wake. And exemptions (policies are not absolute rules) and a level even when relevant policies do exist, they are often of obligation (policies are not mere suggestions). ambiguous or inadequate as they were designed for We want our policies for computing to be ethical, times with a less versatile technology than computing. but what should we look for when constructing ethical A basic job of computer ethics is to identify these computing policies? When we turn to traditional policy needs, clarify related conceptual confusions, ethical theories for help we discover a strong rivalry formulate appropriate new policies, and ethically exists between the leading contenders – consequen- justify them.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Deontology?, Part One: Orthodox Views Gerald F. Gaus
    What is Deontology?, Part One: Orthodox Viewsa Gerald F. Gaus 1. Introduction Current moral philosophy is often seen as essentially a debate between the two great traditions of consequentialism and deontology. Although there has been considerable work clarifying consequentialism, deontology is more often attacked or defended than analyzed. Just how we are to understand the very idea of a deontological ethic? We shall see that competing conceptions of deontology have been advanced in recent ethical thinking, leading to differences in classifying ethical theories. If we do not focus on implausible versions, the idea of a deontological ethic is far more attractive than most philosophers have thought. Indeed, I shall argue that in an important sense, only a deontological ethic can be plausible. 2. Deontology as the Non-teleological Most commentators follow William Frankena in characterizing deontology as the class of non- teleological theories. “Deontological theories deny what teleological theories affirm.”1 It is widely agreed that a theory is teleological if it justifies the right, moral duty, or obligation, on the a Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 35 (2001): 27-42. grounds that it promotes what is good. This, though, is vague. If we are to understand this characterization of deontology, we need to be clearer about the idea of teleology. Because philosophers disagree about precisely what teleology affirms, we confront different accounts of deontology. One interpretation of this orthodox formulation is suggested by Jeffrey Reiman: Teleological
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded from Brill.Com09/30/2021 04:09:34AM Via Free Access
    Part Two HOW TO DO BIOETHICS? Veikko Launis - 9789042027404 Downloaded from Brill.com09/30/2021 04:09:34AM via free access Veikko Launis - 9789042027404 Downloaded from Brill.com09/30/2021 04:09:34AM via free access Four THE UNBEARABLE LIGHTNESS OF BIOETHICAL PRINCIPLES Veikko Launis If there is such a thing as the truth about the subject matter of ethics—the truth, we might say, about the ethical—why is there any expectation that it should be simple? In particular, why should it be conceptually simple, using only one or two ethical concepts, such as duty or good state of af- fairs, rather than many? Perhaps we need as many concepts to describe it as we find we need, and no fewer.1 1. Introduction: Metaphysical and Normative Lightness In the past two decades or so, a mode of theorizing commonly known as “prin- ciplism” or a “principle-based approach” has been the dominant approach in bioethics. As Donald C. Ainslie points out, the label “principlism” was origi- nally meant to be derogatory, but became embraced by its defenders.2 In the form it has come to be known, principlism is usually characterized by adopting a limited number of prima facie binding bioethical principles which are then individually specified and balanced against each other when a specific moral problem is discussed. The derivation of the principles, the number of princi- ples, and the specification and balancing methods differ depending on the in- terpretation.3 Though there are different principlist theories, principlism is most com- monly characterized by citing four so-called “midlevel” principles—respect for autonomy (the obligation to respect and promote the decision-making ca- pacities of autonomous individuals), nonmaleficence (the obligation to avoid the causation of harm), beneficence (the obligation to provide benefits and bal- ance benefits against risks), and justice (obligations of fairness and non- discrimination in the distribution of benefits and risks).
    [Show full text]
  • Supererogation and Duty in Immanuel Kant's Ethical Framework
    UNIVERSITY OF NEW HAMPSHIRE COLLEGE OF LIBERAL ARTS UNDERGRADUATE RESEARCH CONFERENCE FINAL PAPER Can Kant Accommodate Supererogation? * Supererogation and Duty in Immanuel Kant’s Ethical Framework Submitted by: Mark Andrew Joseph Senior: English and Philosophy University of New Hampshire 7828 Granite Square Station Durham, NH 03824 (603) 295-1108 Faculty Mentor: Paul McNamara Associate Professor in Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of New Hampshire 14 Hamilton-Smith Hall Durham, NH 03824 (603) 862-4215 Date: May 13, 2006 I. “Supererogation is the technical term for the class of actions that go ‘beyond the call of Comment [REE1]: It’s a good rule of 1 thumb to only use quotes for things you duty’” (Heyd 2002, 1). Intuitively, common sense recognizes supererogation: oftentimes peoplecan’t say just as easily yourself. This first line smacks of laziness: you gotta express your introduction in your own words! “engage in praiseworthy behavior where they do more than they have to do, morally speaking” This line from Heyd is simply a canned definition of supererogation: give your own canned def! 2 (McNamara 2004, 1). These supererogatory actions, “good, but not obligatory, to do” (Chisholm Comment [REE2]: Same comment as above: surely you can express this in your 1963, 5), customarily exemplify human beings at their very best.3 J.O. Urmson, in his seminal articleown words. Comment [REE3]: Here I think you can keep the quotation marks and simply “Saints and Heroes,” characterized these laudable actions with his example of a doctor “who, nodrop the citation altogether – it’s unnecessary. differently situated from countless other doctors in other places, volunteers to join the depleted Comment [REE4]: I won’t mention this again, but even here the use of the medical forces” (Urmson 1958, 62) of a plague-ridden city.
    [Show full text]
  • Being Aristotelian: Using Virtue Ethics in an Applied Media Ethics Course Wendy N
    University of St. Thomas, Minnesota UST Research Online Communication and Journalism Faculty Communication and Journalism Publications 2008 Being Aristotelian: Using Virtue Ethics in an Applied Media Ethics Course Wendy N. Wyatt University of St. Thomas, Minnesota, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://ir.stthomas.edu/cas_cojo_pub Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Journalism Studies Commons, and the Mass Communication Commons Recommended Citation Wyatt, Wendy N., "Being Aristotelian: Using Virtue Ethics in an Applied Media Ethics Course" (2008). Communication and Journalism Faculty Publications. 1. http://ir.stthomas.edu/cas_cojo_pub/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Communication and Journalism at UST Research Online. It has been accepted for inclusion in Communication and Journalism Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UST Research Online. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Page 1 Being Aristotelian: Using virtue ethics in an applied media ethics course This essay explores the tendency of undergraduate media ethics students to do what Bernard Gert calls “morality by slogans” and their tendency to misuse Aristotle’s golden mean slogan. While not solving the dilemma of morality by slogans, the essay suggests some ways of rectifying the misuse of the golden mean and encouraging its more authentic application. Any professor of media ethics knows the dangers of teaching ethical theory to undergraduates. In 15 weeks or fewer, students work not only to develop skills in ethical analysis—in which theory is only one part—but they also explore recurring moral issues, they reflect on what they can do to make their profession better, and they think about their roles and responsibilities as media consumers.
    [Show full text]
  • Law, Humanities and Equipoise in the Ethics Education of Physician Assistants
    A Peer Reviewed Publication of the College of Allied Health & Nursing at Nova Southeastern University Dedicated to allied health professional practice and education http://ijahsp.nova.edu Vol. 4 No. 2 ISSN 1540-580X Law, Humanities and Equipoise in the Ethics Education of Physician Assistants Frederick Adolf Paola, M.D., J.D. Affiliate Associate Professor of Medicine Division of Medical Ethics & Humanities University of South Florida College of Medicine Citation: Paoloa, F. Law, Humanities and Equipoise in the Ethics Education of Physician Assistants. The Internet Journal of Allied Health Sciences and Practice. Apr 2006, Volume 4 Number 2. Abstract The humanities have been defined as a group of academic subjects united by a commitment to studying aspects of the human condition and a qualitative approach that generally prevents a single paradigm from coming to define any discipline. In the medical humanities context, the most quickly growing area is the field of literature and medicine. The use of literature in bioethics education plays a number of well-recognized educational roles. Herein, we argue that the law is relatively overemphasized in bioethics education and that one heretofore ignored yet important role of the humanities is to serve as a counterbalance to the pernicious influence of legal hegemony in the field of bioethics. In the process, we consider the special circumstances surrounding the fields of philosophy and jurisprudence; we discuss the 1998 American Society for Bioethics and Humanities “Core Competencies” report; and we use examples (drawn from teaching materials employed at the University of South Florida College of Medicine and Nova Southeastern University’s Naples-based Physician Assistant Program) to contrast the law’s narrowness with the richness and ambiguity of the humanities.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 3G03E: Ethics September-December 2009 Instructor: Dr
    Philosophy 3G03E: Ethics September-December 2009 Instructor: Dr. D. L. Hitchcock Lectures: Tuesdays 19:00 to 20:50, Arthur Bourns Building (ABB) 163 Optional tutorials: Tuesdays 21:00 to 21:50, ABB 163 Instructor’s office hours: Wed 14:00 to 15:00, or by appointment, in University Hall (UH) 304 Instructor’s e-mail address: [email protected] Course Web site: ELM Teaching assistant: Ben Hamby TA’s e-mail address: [email protected] TA’s office hours: Tues 18:00 to 18:50, or by appointment, in UH B106A This course is "an introduction to the major types of ethical theory and the problem of their justification" (Undergraduate Calendar description). We will consider the two currently most influential ethical theories, as well as a contemporary ethical theory that includes a critique of them: 1) Immanuel Kant's apparently deontological theory, articulated in the various formulations of his "categorical imperative" and justified by an appeal to the autonomy of a rational agent 2) John Stuart Mill's consequentialist theory of utilitarianism, expressed by his "principle of utility" and justified by the claim that all human beings ultimately desire only happiness 3) Bernard Gert's mixed theory of "common morality", consisting of 10 defeasible moral rules, a set of moral ideals, and a two-step procedure for justifying violations of the moral rules; and justified as a system that, given certain conditions, it is rationally required for all moral agents to endorse Objectives: On completion of the course, you should be able to: 1) describe, apply and discuss critically the ethical theories of Kant, Mill and Gert.
    [Show full text]
  • Bernard Gert Moral Disagreement Concerning Abortion
    Bernard Gert Moral disagreement concerning abortion Diametros nr 26, 23-43 2010 Diametros № 26 (December 2010): 23-43 MORAL DISAGREEMENT CONCERNING ABORTION 1 - Bernard Gert - Introduction Even though it is seldom explicitly stated, it seems to be a common phi- losophical view that either every moral question has a unique correct answer or that none of them do. Since it is obvious that some moral questions, e.g., “Is it morally acceptable to torture a person for the enjoyment of sadists?” have unique correct answers, some philosophers seem to hold that even the most controversial moral questions have unique correct answers. This may explain why some phi- losophers think that they can resolve the question about the moral acceptability of abortion. Many philosophers do not even consider the view that although most moral questions have unique correct answers some do not. Our common morality does not resolve every moral problem, for not every moral problem can be re- solved. A moral theory should describe our common morality and try to justify it by showing that all equally informed rational persons would support it. The proper tasks for a moral theory are to explain both why there is moral agreement about the answers to the overwhelming majority of moral questions, and why there is moral disagreement concerning the answers to a small but important number of moral questions. The overwhelming agreement on most moral matters is obscured by the fact that there is very little discussion of these uncontrover- sial matters and a great deal of discussion about the small number of controversial issues.
    [Show full text]