Before Loving: the Lost Origins of the Right to Marry

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Before Loving: the Lost Origins of the Right to Marry University at Buffalo School of Law Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1-1-2020 Before Loving: The Lost Origins of the Right to Marry Michael Boucai University at Buffalo School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/journal_articles Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Sexuality and the Law Commons Recommended Citation Michael Boucai, Before Loving: The Lost Origins of the Right to Marry, 2020 Utah L. Rev. 69 (2020). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/journal_articles/968 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEFORE LOVING: THE LOST ORIGINS OF THE RIGHT TO MARRY Michael Boucai* Abstract For almost two centuries of this nation’s history, the basic contours of the fundamental right to marry were fairly clear as a matter of natural, not constitutional, law. The right encompassed marriage’s essential characteristics: conjugality and contract, portability and permanence. This Article defines those four dimensions of the natural right to marry and describes their reflections and contradictions in positive law prior to Loving v. Virginia (1967). In that landmark case, the Supreme Court enforced a constitutional “freedom to marry” just when marriage’s definitive attributes were on the brink of legal collapse. Not only did wedlock proceed in Loving’s wake to lose its exclusive claims to licit sex and legitimate procreation, personal autonomy in those very domains gained independent constitutional protection. Drained of its conjugal essence, today’s constitutional right to marry is thus an anachronism, the vestige of a bygone consensus about what, if anything, “marriage” fundamentally is. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 70 I. NATURAL MARRIAGE ..................................................................................... 77 II. “A THING OF NATURAL RIGHT” .................................................................... 90 A. The Conjugal Right to Marry .................................................................... 91 1. Sex and Procreation .............................................................................. 94 2. Parenthood and Cohabitation? .............................................................. 99 3. The Conjugal Right in Positive Law ..................................................... 103 * © 2020 Michael Boucai. Associate Professor, University at Buffalo School of Law. I am grateful to the many interlocutors whose wisdom and encouragement enabled this study: Erez Aloni, Christine Bartholomew, Mark Bartholomew, Anya Bernstein, Guyora Binder, Luke Boso, Douglas Brown, Luis Chiesa, Jessica Clarke, Maxime Fleuriot, Lucinda Finley, Jim Gardner, Joe Gerken, Jill Hasday, Janet Halley, Amanda Hughett, Courtney Joslin, Isabel Marcus, Kevin Maillard, Jonathan Manes, Kaipo Matsumura, David McNamee, Martha McCluskey, Athena Mutua, Doug NeJaime, Tony O’Rourke, Frank Oveis, Nancy Polikoff, Dave Pozen, Orly Rachmilovitz, Karla Raimundi, Cliff Rosky, Jack Schlegel, Ed Stein, Matt Steilen, Rick Su, Tico Taussig-Rubbo, and Marsha Zubrow. I thank John Mondo and the staff of the Charles B. Sears Law Library for their heroic pursuit of sources. I thank Whitney McKiddy and the members of the Utah Law Review for their insights and professionalism. And I thank Katherine Bruno, Noreena Chaudari, Katie Gojevic, Stan Makowski, Melanie Prasad, and William Rossi for excellent research assistance. Errors of fact and judgment are mine alone. 69 70 UTAH LAW REVIEW [NO. 1 B. The Contractual Right to Marry .............................................................. 107 1. The Right Not to Marry ........................................................................ 111 2. The Right to Marry by Mutual Consent ................................................ 114 3. A Right to Marry the Person of One’s Choice?..................................... 129 C. The Right to Stay Married ....................................................................... 134 1. Portability ........................................................................................... 134 2. Permanence ......................................................................................... 139 III. THE CONSTITUTIONAL RISE OF THE NATURAL RIGHT TO MARRY ............... 150 A. Before Skinner ........................................................................................ 151 B. From Skinner to Loving .......................................................................... 158 IV. FROM LOVING TO LAWRENCE ...................................................................... 165 A. Loving’s Natural Right to Marry ............................................................. 165 B. Decline and Fall ..................................................................................... 170 CONCLUSION: AFTER OBERGEFELL ................................................................... 173 There are . in legal consciousness at any moment, concepts that legal thinkers find in . a preceding age, and perhaps themselves mouth ritualistically, without any confidence that they have a meaning.1 INTRODUCTION The fundamental right to marry is a paradox in contemporary American jurisprudence: repeatedly and reverently affirmed by the Supreme Court, but viewed with puzzlement, skepticism, even outright disbelief by legal scholars. On the judicial side of the ledger, we encounter a line of precedents stretching from Meyer v. Nebraska (1923), with its fleeting invocation of a “right . to . marry, establish a home and bring up children,” to Obergefell v. Hodges (2015), which extended the marriage right to same-sex couples.2 The case that definitively identified marriage as a constitutional right was decided about midway between those two rulings. In Loving v. Virginia (1967), the Court held that prohibitions of interracial marriage violate the Fourteenth Amendment, violating both the Equal Protection Clause and an independent “freedom to marry” anchored in the Due Process Clause.3 Since that landmark decision, the Court has consistently cast marriage as the most august, central, and specific among a family of freedoms—privacy, intimate association, sexual autonomy, the rights to procreate and not to procreate—traveling together under the banner of “substantive due process.”4 That doctrine is notoriously 1 DUNCAN KENNEDY, THE RISE AND FALL OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT 70 (1975). 2 Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 399 (1923); Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2584, 2600–01 (2015) (quoting Meyer, 262 U.S. at 399). 3 Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 12 (1967). 4 See, e.g., Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2599; Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 726 (1997); Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851– 2020] BEFORE LOVING 71 controversial, but Loving has gone to show that it cannot possibly be all wrong. Justices who quarrel vehemently over the bounds of due-process “liberty” evince shared faith that marriage, though “nowhere mentioned” in the Constitution, is a fundamental right thereunder.5 To legal scholars, Loving’s “freedom to marry” comes as a challenge, a riddle. Our quandary originates in the fact that every decision vindicating the right involves access to civil matrimony, a state-run institution. Is that really what “the freedom to marry” guarantees? If so, access to marital status would be one of few unenumerated, positive entitlements gleaned from a constitution reductively but not unaccountably styled a “charter of negative liberties.”6 Hypotheticals about marriage abolition are 52 (1992); Harris v. McRae, 448 U.S. 297, 312 n.18 (1980); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 152–54, 159 (1973). 5 Casey, 505 U.S. at 847–48 (referring to marriage and citing Loving); cf. id. at 951–53 (1992) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (distinguishing Loving’s right to marry from the right to abortion). For similarly competing uses of Loving’s right to marry, compare Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 499, 503 (1977) with Moore, 431 U.S. at 535–56 (Stewart, J., dissenting); compare Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 191, 204–05 (1986) with Bowers, 478 U.S. at 210 n. 5 (Blackmun, J., dissenting); and compare Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2598, 2602–03 (2015) with Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2614–15, 2619 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting). In 1978, Justices Lewis Powell and William Rehnquist expressed doubt as to whether the marriage right was properly called “fundamental,” but less than a decade later they joined an opinion holding a Missouri prison regulation to violate “the fundamental right to marry.” Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374, 396–403, 407–11 (1978) (Powell, J., concurring and Rehnquist, J., dissenting); Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 81, 94–99 (1987). Since Turner, Justice Clarence Thomas, joined by Justice Antonin Scalia, has come closer than any member of the Court to flatly repudiating the constitutional right to marry. His discussion of the right assumes only arguendo that “the ‘liberty’” protected by the Due Process Clause embraces anything beyond “freedom from physical restraint.” Obergefell, 135 S. Ct. at 2634 (Thomas, J.,
Recommended publications
  • Principles of U.S. Family Law Vivian E
    College of William & Mary Law School William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository Faculty Publications Faculty and Deans 2006 Principles of U.S. Family Law Vivian E. Hamilton William & Mary Law School, [email protected] Repository Citation Hamilton, Vivian E., "Principles of U.S. Family Law" (2006). Faculty Publications. 184. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs/184 Copyright c 2006 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs ARTICLE PRINCIPLES OF U.S. FAMILY LAW Vivian Hamilton* What explains US. family law? What are the orzgms of the current chaos and controversy in the field, the home of some of the most vituperative debates in public policy? To answer these questions, this Article identifies and examines family law's foundational principles. It undertakes a conceptual analysis ofthe legal practices that govern families. This analysis has yet to be done, and its absence hamstrings constructive thought on our family law. The Article develops a typology that conceptualizes US. family law and exposes its underlying principles. First, it identifies the significant elements, or rules, of family law. Second, it demonstrates that these rules reflect or embody four important concepts­ conjugality, privacy (familial as well as individual), contract, and parens patriae. Third, it shows that the concepts offamily law in turn embody two distinct underlying principles-Biblical traditionalism and liberal individualism. From these powerful principles, we can derive modern U.S. family law: They explain what our family law is. With this deepened understanding offamily law's structure, the Article next evaluates these principles, and family law as the expression ofthem.
    [Show full text]
  • Age and Sexual Consent
    Per Se or Power? Age and Sexual Consent Joseph J. Fischel* ABSTRACT: Legal theorists, liberal philosophers, and feminist scholars have written extensively on questions surrounding consent and sexual consent, with particular attention paid to the sorts of conditions that validate or vitiate consent, and to whether or not consent is an adequate metric to determine ethical and legal conduct. So too, many have written on the historical construction of childhood, and how this concept has influenced contemporary legal culture and more broadly informed civil society and its social divisions. Far less has been written, however, on a potent point of contact between these two fields: age of consent laws governing sexual activity. Partially on account of this under-theorization, such statutes are often taken for granted as reflecting rather than creating distinctions between adults and youth, between consensual competency and incapacity, and between the time for innocence and the time for sex. In this Article, I argue for relatively modest reforms to contemporary age of consent statutes but propose a theoretic reconstruction of the principles that inform them. After briefly historicizing age of consent statutes in the United States (Part I), I assert that the concept of sexual autonomy ought to govern legal regulations concerning age, age difference, and sexual activity (Part II). A commitment to sexual autonomy portends a lowered age of sexual consent, decriminalization of sex between minors, heightened legal supervision focusing on age difference and relations of dependence, more robust standards of consent for sex between minors and between minors and adults, and greater attention to the ways concerns about age, age difference, and sex both reflect and displace more normatively apt questions around gender, gendered power and submission, and queer sexuality (Part III).
    [Show full text]
  • Sex and the Law
    1 SEX AND THE LAW This factsheet summarises the legal position in relation to the age of sexual consent in Northern Ireland, and outlines the new sexual offences legislation in light of the revision of sexual offences legislation in Northern Ireland. Key facts • The age of sexual consent has been reduced from 17 to 16 years of age. • There is no longer a statutory duty to report to the police cases of sexual activity involving a young person aged 13 to 16 years old, where the other person is under 18 years of age. • There is now a new set of offences to protect persons with a mental disorder from sexual abuse. The Sexual Offences (Northern Ireland) Order 2008 The Sexual Offences (Northern Ireland) Order 2008, which was approved by Parliament in June 2008 came into force on 2nd February 2009. It incorporated significant changes to the law in relation to sexual offences in Northern Ireland, better protection for young people from sexual abuse and exploitation and seeks to clarify issues surrounding consent in sexual assault cases and rape. Key elements included: • lowering the age of sexual consent from 17 years of age to 16 years of age • a set of offences to protect persons with a mental disorder • new offences of kerb crawling and soliciting for prostitution • tighter penalties for keeping a brothel • more clarity on the abuse of positions of trust offences • gender neutrality. All sexual activity with a young person of either gender under the age of 16 is now illegal, even if both parties are under 16 – this is the same as the rest of the UK.
    [Show full text]
  • Thesis Polygamy on the Web: an Online Community for An
    THESIS POLYGAMY ON THE WEB: AN ONLINE COMMUNITY FOR AN UNCONVENTIONAL PRACTICE Submitted by Kristen Sweet-McFarling Department of Anthropology In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University Fort Collins, Colorado Summer 2014 Master’s Committee: Advisor: Lynn Kwiatkowski Cindy Griffin Barbara Hawthorne Copyright by Kristen Sweet-McFarling 2014 All Rights Reserved ABSTRACT POLYGAMY ON THE WEB: AN ONLINE COMMUNITY FOR AN UNCONVENTIONAL PRACTICE This thesis is a virtual ethnographic study of a polygamy website consisting of one chat room, several discussion boards, and polygamy related information and links. The findings of this research are based on the interactions and activities of women and men on the polygamy website. The research addressed the following questions: 1) what are individuals using the website for? 2) What are website members communicating about? 3) How are individuals using the website to search for polygamous relationships? 4) Are website members forming connections and meeting people offline through the use of the website? 5) Do members of the website perceive the Internet to be affecting the contemporary practice of polygamy in the U.S.? This research focused more on the desire to create a polygamous relationship rather than established polygamous marriages and kinship networks. This study found that since the naturalization of monogamous heterosexual marriage and the nuclear family has occurred in the U.S., due to a number of historical, social, cultural, political, and economic factors, the Internet can provide a means to denaturalize these concepts and provide a space for the expression and support of counter discourses of marriage, like polygamy.
    [Show full text]
  • Age of Consent and the Law
    Age Of Consent And The Law Tiebold is nary and deoxidised rompishly while isodimorphic Austin aphorises and experimentalize. Conjugated now.Wylie Julio still expertising: rambling mannishly. ablated and glinting Alexander classifying quite precipitously but monograph her scofflaws At the same time, raising the age below which girls would need to obtain consent from a parent or guardian or other third party would make teenaged women and their bodies involuntary vessels for gestating babies. The table includes the age requirements for both the actor and the child, and notes if the offense is a felony or a misdemeanor. Are there certain exceptions to the law in Colorado? Marriage is a defense to certain sex crimes. It does not address state laws that empower minors to consent for substance abuse treatment, mental health care, treatment for contagious diseases or reproductive health. Someone Who Must Register as a Sex Offender? Policy debates around the age of sexual consent have focused on three main issues: child protection; the age of expected sexual activity; and the age of maturity. The information in our publications is not a substitute for legal advice. Task Force provides to the Legislature. Commissioner of Developmental Services in any public or private facility or program and the actor has supervisory or disciplinary authority over such other person. Such as it is anchored by reason for the consent and the age of consent? At the sexual activity anyway, and the law indicates the age of the authority figures declared themselves. People with learning disabilities: Sex, the law and consent. This mainly refers to a minor engaging in intercourse with adult.
    [Show full text]
  • SEX and the LAW, by Morris Ploscowe, with an Introduction by Roscoe Pound, Prentice-Hall, Inc., New York, 1951, Pp
    194 UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS CITY LAW REVIEW SEX AND THE LAW, by Morris Ploscowe, with an introduction by Roscoe Pound, Prentice-Hall, Inc., New York, 1951, pp. ix, 310, $3.95. Reviewed by Quintin Johnstone, Associate Professor of Law, University of Kansas. One way of judging the value of a book is to determine who will read it and what service it will be to its readers. By this standard Sex and the Law has very limited value. It considers best seller, Sunday supplement topics, sex and crime; but is an objective, non-sensational treatment of these subjects. This means that it will not be widely read by the popular reading public. Nor will it be read by many lawyers because, as a dissertation on formal law, its coverage is sketchy with meager citations of cases and statutes. The treatment of sex crimes is a good, brief introduction to the subject, and merits attention by law students and novitiate prosecutors. Sex and the Law also is good background reading for the non-lawyers who work with problems of family discord and sex crime. These include clergymen, physicians, social workers, marriage coun­ selors, sociologists, and criminologists. Morris Proscowe, the author of Sex and the Law, is a New York judge with some years of judicial experience in the fields about which he writes. Unfortunately he gives little attention to that which he is most qualified to discuss, namely, a first hand account of how family and sex crime laws are administered. His comments about how such laws work are summaries of observations made previously by respectable authorities.
    [Show full text]
  • Pastorale Nureyev Park Appeal Dixie Union Dixieland Band
    Consigned by Woodfort Stud 401 401 Gone West Zafonic Iffraaj (GB) Zaizafon BAY FILLY (IRE) Nureyev April 8th, 2011 Pastorale Park Appeal (Third Produce) Dixieland Band Dixie Union Hams (USA) She's Tops (2003) Desert Wine Desert Victress Elegant Victress E.B.F. Nominated. B.C. Nominated. 1st dam HAMS (USA): placed twice at 3; dam of 2 previous foals; 2 runners; 2 winners: Super Market (IRE) (08 f. by Refuse To Bend (IRE)): 4 wins at 2 in Italy. Dixie's Dream (IRE) (09 c. by Hawk Wing (USA)): 2 wins at 2 and 3, 2012 and placed 5 times. 2nd dam DESERT VICTRESS (USA): placed twice at 2 and 3; also winner at 3 in U.S.A. and placed 3 times; dam of 10 foals; 9 runners; 3 winners inc.: DESERT DIGGER (USA) (f. by Mining (USA)): winner at 2 in U.S.A. and £99,649 viz. Sorrento S., Gr.2, placed 5 times inc. 2nd Del Mar Debutante S., Gr.2 and 3rd Princess S., Gr.2; dam of winners inc.: SIRMIONE (USA): won HBPA H. and 2nd Ellis Park Turf S., L. Back Packer (USA): winner in U.S.A., 2nd Transylvania S., L. 3rd dam ELEGANT VICTRESS (CAN) (by Sir Ivor (USA)): 3 wins at 3 in U.S.A. and placed 5 times; dam of 12 foals; 10 runners; 7 winners inc.: EXPLICIT (USA): 6 wins in U.S.A. and £404,504 inc. True North Breeders' Cup H., Gr.2, Count Fleet Sprint H., Gr.3, Pelleteri Breeders' Cup H., L.
    [Show full text]
  • NP 2013.Docx
    LISTE INTERNATIONALE DES NOMS PROTÉGÉS (également disponible sur notre Site Internet : www.IFHAonline.org) INTERNATIONAL LIST OF PROTECTED NAMES (also available on our Web site : www.IFHAonline.org) Fédération Internationale des Autorités Hippiques de Courses au Galop International Federation of Horseracing Authorities 15/04/13 46 place Abel Gance, 92100 Boulogne, France Tel : + 33 1 49 10 20 15 ; Fax : + 33 1 47 61 93 32 E-mail : [email protected] Internet : www.IFHAonline.org La liste des Noms Protégés comprend les noms : The list of Protected Names includes the names of : F Avant 1996, des chevaux qui ont une renommée F Prior 1996, the horses who are internationally internationale, soit comme principaux renowned, either as main stallions and reproducteurs ou comme champions en courses broodmares or as champions in racing (flat or (en plat et en obstacles), jump) F de 1996 à 2004, des gagnants des neuf grandes F from 1996 to 2004, the winners of the nine épreuves internationales suivantes : following international races : Gran Premio Carlos Pellegrini, Grande Premio Brazil (Amérique du Sud/South America) Japan Cup, Melbourne Cup (Asie/Asia) Prix de l’Arc de Triomphe, King George VI and Queen Elizabeth Stakes, Queen Elizabeth II Stakes (Europe/Europa) Breeders’ Cup Classic, Breeders’ Cup Turf (Amérique du Nord/North America) F à partir de 2005, des gagnants des onze grandes F since 2005, the winners of the eleven famous épreuves internationales suivantes : following international races : Gran Premio Carlos Pellegrini, Grande Premio Brazil (Amérique du Sud/South America) Cox Plate (2005), Melbourne Cup (à partir de 2006 / from 2006 onwards), Dubai World Cup, Hong Kong Cup, Japan Cup (Asie/Asia) Prix de l’Arc de Triomphe, King George VI and Queen Elizabeth Stakes, Irish Champion (Europe/Europa) Breeders’ Cup Classic, Breeders’ Cup Turf (Amérique du Nord/North America) F des principaux reproducteurs, inscrits à la F the main stallions and broodmares, registered demande du Comité International des Stud on request of the International Stud Book Books.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law of Embezzled Lives Lawrence M
    Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship Fall 2014 Double Take: The Law of Embezzled Lives Lawrence M. Friedman Joanna L. Grossman Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/faculty_scholarship Recommended Citation Lawrence M. Friedman and Joanna L. Grossman, Double Take: The Law of Embezzled Lives, 83 U. Cin. L. Rev. 117 (2014) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/faculty_scholarship/713 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DOUBLE TAKE: THE LAW OF EMBEZZLED LIvEs Lawrence M Friedman* JoannaL. Grossman** I. INTRODUCTION There was tremendous public sympathy for Notre Dame football player Manti Te'o, whose girlfriend, Lennay Kekua, had tragically died of leukemia. The sympathy, it turns out, was misplaced. Kekua never died because she never lived.' She was an internet hoax-a woman Te'o thought he loved, and with whom he had communicated over a long period of time, but who in fact had been created by jokesters. 2 Te'o appears to have been "catfished"-a modern term which means duped by a fake internet identity. A 2010 documentary, Catfish, depicted a man who meets a woman online and falls for her, only to learn later her identity was a far cry from the one portrayed on the Internet.3 In a television series of the same name, we see more unsuspecting people "catfished"-victims of an online dating hoax whose excitement and then humiliation are chronicled for viewer entertainment.4 "Catfishing" claimed Manti Te'o as one of its early victims.5 At the heart of "catfishing" is a basic problem-how do we ever know whether people are who they say they are? The title of this article * Marion Rice Kirkwood Professor of Law, Stanford Law School.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Law and Society May Legitimately Prefer Heterosexuality
    Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons Faculty Publications 2011 Straight Is Better: Why Law and Society May Legitimately Prefer Heterosexuality George W. Dent Jr. Case Western University School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/faculty_publications Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons Repository Citation Dent, George W. Jr., "Straight Is Better: Why Law and Society May Legitimately Prefer Heterosexuality" (2011). Faculty Publications. 506. https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/faculty_publications/506 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. TEXASFINAL STRAIGHT IS BETTER DENT FINAL AUG. UPDATE8/23/2011 3:15 PM STRAIGHT IS BETTER: WHY LAW AND SOCIETY MAY JUSTLY PREFER HETEROSEXUALITY GEORGE W. DENT, JR. * I. INTRODUCTION........................................................... 361 II. THE CONFLICT OVER HOMOSEXUALITY .................... 361 III. THE LEGITIMACY OF VALUE JUDGMENTS IN THE LAW ............................................................................ 363 IV. THE CATHOLIC NATURAL LAW PHILOSOPHY OF SEXUALITY ................................................................. 369 V. SOCIETY MAY LEGITIMATELY PREFER HETEROSEXUALITY AND TRADITIONAL MARRIAGE ... 371 A. The Intrinsic
    [Show full text]
  • The Federal Response to Mormon Polygamy, 1854 - 1887
    Mr. Peay's Horses: The Federal Response to Mormon Polygamy, 1854 - 1887 Mary K. Campbellt I. INTRODUCTION Mr. Peay was a family man. From a legal standpoint, he was also a man with a problem. The 1872 Edmunds Act had recently criminalized bigamy, polygamy, and unlawful cohabitation,1 leaving Mr. Peay in a bind. Peay had married his first wife in 1860, his second wife in 1862, and his third wife in 1867.2 He had sired numerous children by each of these women, all of whom bore his last name.3 Although Mr. Peay provided a home for each wife and her children, the Peays worked the family farm communally, often taking their meals together on the compound.4 How could Mr. Peay abide by the Act without abandoning the women and children whom he had promised to support? Hedging his bets, Mr. Peay moved in exclusively with his first wife. 5 Under the assumption that "cohabitation" required living together, he ceased to spend the night with his other families, although he continued to care for them. 6 After a jury convicted him of unlawful cohabitation in 1887,7 he argued his assumption to the Utah Supreme Court. As defense counsel asserted, "the gist of the offense is to 'ostensibly' live with [more than one woman.]' ' 8 In Mr. Peay's view, he no longer lived with his plural wives. The court emphatically rejected this interpretation of "cohabitation," declaring that "[a]ny more preposterous idea could not well be conceived."9 The use of the word "ostensibly" appeared to irritate the court.
    [Show full text]
  • Spousal Exemption to Rape Michael J
    Marquette Law Review Volume 65 Article 4 Issue 1 Fall 1981 Spousal Exemption to Rape Michael J. Gonring III Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr Part of the Law Commons Repository Citation Michael J. Gonring III, Spousal Exemption to Rape, 65 Marq. L. Rev. 120 (1981). Available at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr/vol65/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Marquette Law Review by an authorized administrator of Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SPOUSAL EXEMPTION TO RAPE Universally, rape1 is seen as a truly reprehensible crime, a crime of violence that not only damages the body, but which also leaves great scars on the mind. Legislatures have acted forcefully against such invasions of a woman's person,3 giving courts the means to punish the crime.' Yet, for reasons that will be explored in this comment, legislatures and courts throughout England and the United States have covered their eyes, closed their ears and sealed their mouths to one of the great inconsistencies in law, the common law sanction of a husband's rape of his wife. 5 A husband not only may demand that his wife consent to sexual intercourse, but should she re- fuse, he can threaten her with any weapon at his disposal; in- deed, he can use physical force to secure his wishes.6 He is, for the most part, above the law.
    [Show full text]