THE INFINITE Thomas Jech

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

THE INFINITE Thomas Jech THE INFINITE Thomas Jech The Pennsylvania State University century the study of the innite was an exclusive domain of Until the th philosophers and theologians For mathematicians while the concept of innity was crucial in applications of calculus and innite series the innite itself was to paraphrase Gauss just the manner of sp eaking Indeed th century mathe matics even with its frequent use of innite sequences and innitesimals had no real need to study the concept of innity itself functions of real and complex variable and the The increasing use of abstract emerging theory of real numb ers in the work of Cauchy Weierstrass and Dedekind brought ab out the necessity to use innity not only as a manner of sp eaking but rather intro duce into mathematical usage the concept of innite set The earliest mathematician to study sets as ob jects of a mathematical theory Bolzano in the s He gave a convincing philosophical agrument was Bernhard for the existence of innite sets and was also rst to explicitly formulate the concept of onetoone corresp ondence b etween sets It seems that Bolzano was not aware of the p ossibility that there may exist innite sets of dieren t size and that as some historians b elieve he envisioned a mathematical universe where all innite sets are countable While some of his ideas were clearly ahead of his time he did Research for this article was supp orted in part by a grant from the International Research Exchange Board IREX with funds provided by the Andrew W Mellon Foundation the National Endowment for the Humanities and the US Department of State None of these organizations is resp onsible for the views expressed The author is grateful to the Kurt Godel So ciety in Vienna and to the Center for Theoretical Studies in Prague for the opp ortunity to discuss the topics of this to Professor Petr Vopenka for his interpretation of Bolzanos article I am particularly thankful work X Typ eset by A ST M E THOMAS JECH consider paradoxical the fact that the set of all p ositive integers can b e in a oneto one corresp ondence with a smaller subset a fact that had b een already p ointed out by Galileo centuries earlier who realized the signicance of onetoone It was Georg Cantor in the s corresp ondence and who embarked on a systematic study of abstract sets and of cardinal and ordinal numb ers His was also the rst application of set theoretical metho ds namely his nonconstructive pro of of the existence of transcendental numb ers The signicance of Cantors pro of lies in the fact that it employs in the idea that any arbitrary b ounded increasing its pro of of uncountability of R sequence of real numb ers has a least upp er b ound This assumption is related to the concept of real numb ers as Dedekind cuts in Q or as limits of Cauchy sequences of rationals or as innite decimal expansions These three p ossible approaches to the denition of real numb ers are all equivalent in a sense and all require the existence of arbitrary innite sets of integers ery few mathematicians ob ject to the idea of an arbitrary set of integers We V will argue later that the idea of existence of large cardinal numb ers that some mathematicians nd ob jectionable the nevernever land in the words of one detractor is conceptionally no dierent from Cantors idea that is inherent in his pro of A natural question arising from Cantors theory of cardinal numb ers is the fol Do there exist sets of real numb ers that are uncountable yet not equivalent lowing in cardinality to the set of all real numb ers The conjecture that no such sets exist Hypothesis Hilb ert attached such imp ortance has b ecome known as the Continuum to this question that it gured on the top of his famous list of problems in The continuum problem has eventually b een solved in a nontraditional way It was proved that the continuum hyp othesis is neither provable nor refutable thus endent b eing indep To show that a mathematical statement is indep endent one has to sp ecify a THE INFINITE system of p ostulates axioms of the theory which are then shown to b e insucient to prove or to refute the statement For instance the parallels p ostulate is indep en p ostulates The pro of of indep endence is accomplished dent of the rest of Euclids by exhibiting models such as the BolyaiLobacevskij mo del of nonEuclidean ge ometry So clearly the assertion that the continuum hyp othesis is indep endent requires that we sp ecify the axiom system There is a more fundamental reason for axiomatizing set theory With very few insignicant exceptions all mathematical arguments and concepts can b e in principle reduced to concepts and statements formalized in the language of set theory Thus an axiom system for the theory of sets is in fact an axiom system for all of mathematics The axiomatization of set theory based on Cantors denition of sets turns out to b e inconsistent for rather trivial reasons The idea is to consider as sets all collections of ob jects that satisfy an arbitrary prop erty This approach is clearly untenable as exemplied by the set a a ag f whose existence leads to a logical contradiction the widely accepted system of axioms for set theory is the Since the s ZermeloFraenkel axiomatic set theory ZF It consists of several axioms and ax iom schemata that encompass all uses of sets in mathematics This axiomatic theory is almost universally accepted as the logical foundation of current mathe matics Most axioms of ZermeloFraenkel are construction principles that merely formal ize certain manipulations with sets The two notable exceptions are the axiom of innity and the axiom of choice The axiom of innity p ostulates the existence of an innite set or equivalently the existence of the set N of all natural numb ers This axiom is of course the essence of set theory If we replace the axiom of innity by its negation we get a THOMAS JECH theory equivalent to Pe ano arithmetic the axiomatic theory of elementary numb er theory Historically the most interesting axiom of ZF is the axiom of choice Unlike the other axioms it is highly nonconstructive as it p ostulates the existence of choice functions without giving a sp ecic description of such functions It was intro duced by Zermelo in his pro of of wellordering and is in fact equivalent to the principle set can b e well ordered As it seems imp ossible to dene a that states that every well ordering of the set R among others this principle was violently opp osed by some mathematicians of the rst half of this century Some of the ob jections are quite understandable in light of such consequences of the axiom of choice as the HausdorBanachTarski paradoxical decomp osition of the unit ball It should b e noted that the axiom of choice is indep endent of the rest of ZF by the work of G odel and Cohen which puts set theory in situation roughly similar to that of Euclidean v nonEuclidean geometry From the formalists p oint of view it do es not make any dierence whether the axiom of choice is accepted as an axiom or not In view of its usefulness in algebra and analysis the prevailing opinion favors the axiom I would like to p oint out that even such an inno cuous statement as the union of countably many countable sets of real numb ers is countable requires the axiom of choice It is of these ZermeloFraenkel axioms that the continuum hyp othesis was shown Kurt Godel constructed a mo del of set theory to b e indep endent First in the constructible universe in which the continuum hyp othesis holds Godels it is the least p ossible mo del which any other mo del mo del is a canonical mo del that contains all ordinal numb ers has to include In Paul Cohen discovered a metho d of constructing generic extensions of mo dels of set theory including mo dels in which the continuum hyp othesis fails Cohens metho d turned out to b e quite general and resulted in a numb er of indep endence pro ofs It so happ ens that a numb er of conjectures in dierent areas of mathematics cannot b e decided on the THE INFINITE basis of ZermeloFraenkel axioms and have b een proved indep endent by Cohens metho d In addition to the continuum hyp othesis we mention Suslins Problem Borels Conjecture Whiteheads Problem and Kaplanskys Conjecture In view of the apparent incompleteness of ZermeloFraenkel axioms a reasonable suggestion oers itself namely to nd a complete system of axioms in which every p ossible statement of mathematics would b e formally decidable This was the so Program A mortal blow to this program were the two Incomplete called Hilberts ness Theorems of Godel The First Incompleteness Theorem shows in eect that there is no hop e for a complete axiomatization of mathematics It states that every axiomatic theory that includes elementary arithmetic is incomplete if it is consistent In particular b oth Peano arithmetic and ZermeloFraenkel set theory are incomplete and will remain incomplete even if we add further axioms Godels pro of of the Incompleteness Theorem yields an undecidable sentence but unlike the Continuum Hyp othesis in set theory Godels sentence is not particularly meaningful It do es provide a starting p oint in the search for easily understandable statements expressible in the language of arithmetic that are indep endent of Peano arithmetic Such statements have indeed b een found by Harrington and Paris Their examples are combinatorial principles expressible in the language of arith metic and true ie provable in set theory but unprovable in Peano arithmetic It remains to b e seen whether some of the unproved conjectures in elementary numb er theory may p erhaps
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, Xii + 621 Pp., '$53.00
    BOOK REVIEWS 775 BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 3, Number 1, July 1980 © 1980 American Mathematical Society 0002-9904/80/0000-0 319/$01.75 Set theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, xii + 621 pp., '$53.00. "General set theory is pretty trivial stuff really" (Halmos; see [H, p. vi]). At least, with the hindsight afforded by Cantor, Zermelo, and others, it is pretty trivial to do the following. First, write down a list of axioms about sets and membership, enunciating some "obviously true" set-theoretic principles; the most popular Hst today is called ZFC (the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of Choice). Next, explain how, from ZFC, one may derive all of conventional mathematics, including the general theory of transfinite cardi­ nals and ordinals. This "trivial" part of set theory is well covered in standard texts, such as [E] or [H]. Jech's book is an introduction to the "nontrivial" part. Now, nontrivial set theory may be roughly divided into two general areas. The first area, classical set theory, is a direct outgrowth of Cantor's work. Cantor set down the basic properties of cardinal numbers. In particular, he showed that if K is a cardinal number, then 2", or exp(/c), is a cardinal strictly larger than K (if A is a set of size K, 2* is the cardinality of the family of all subsets of A). Now starting with a cardinal K, we may form larger cardinals exp(ic), exp2(ic) = exp(exp(fc)), exp3(ic) = exp(exp2(ic)), and in fact this may be continued through the transfinite to form expa(»c) for every ordinal number a.
    [Show full text]
  • Convergence and Submeasures in Boolean Algebras
    Converence and submeasures in Boolean algebras Thomas Jech e-mail: [email protected] October 8, 2018 In memory of Bohuslav Balcar Abstract A Boolean algebra carries a strictly positive exhaustive submeasure if and only if it has a sequential topology that is uniformly Fr´echet. 1 Introduction. In 1937, John von Neumann proposed the problem of characterizing the complete Boolean algebras that carry a strictly positive σ−additive measure (The Scottish Book [17], Problem 163.) Such algebras satisfy the countable chain condition (ccc): every subset of mutually disjoint elements is countable. In addition, von Neumann isolated a weak dis- tributive law and asked whether these two properties are sufficient for the existence of measure. arXiv:1705.01019v1 [math.LO] 2 May 2017 The first major contribution to von Neumann’s problem was given by Dorothy Maharam [16] who identified a part of the problem as a topological problem. She showed that a complete Boolean algebra carries a strictly positive continuous submeasure if and only if the sequential topology given by the algebraic convergence is metrizable. This gives a natural decomposition of the von Neumann problem into two parts: I. Does every complete weakly distributive ccc Boolean algebra carry a strictly positive continuous submeasure? 1 II. Does the existence of a strictly positive continuous submeasure imply the existence of a strictly positive σ−additive measure? Part II has become the well known and well-studied Control Mea- sure Problem [12] in Functional Analysis and remained open until Talagrand’s solution [22] in 2008. As for Part I, Maharam showed that a negative answer would follow from the existence of a Suslin algebra.
    [Show full text]
  • Ineffability Within the Limits of Abstraction Alone
    Ineffability within the Limits of Abstraction Alone Stewart Shapiro and Gabriel Uzquiano 1 Abstraction and iteration The purpose of this article is to assess the prospects for a Scottish neo-logicist foundation for a set theory. The gold standard would be a theory as rich and useful as the dominant one, ZFC, Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with choice, perhaps aug- mented with large cardinal principles. Although the present paper is self-contained, we draw upon recent work in [32] in which we explore the power of a reasonably pure principle of reflection. To establish terminology, the Scottish neo-logicist program is to develop branches of mathematics using abstraction principles in the form: xα = xβ $ α ∼ β where the variables α and β range over items of a certain sort, x is an operator taking items of this sort to objects, and ∼ is an equivalence relation on this sort of item. The standard exemplar, of course, is Hume’s principle: #F = #G ≡ F ≈ G where, as usual, F ≈ G is an abbreviation of the second-order statement that there is a one-one correspondence from F onto G. Hume’s principle, is the main support for what is regarded as a success-story for the Scottish neo-logicist program, at least by its advocates. The search is on to develop more powerful mathematical theories on a similar basis. As witnessed by this volume and a significant portion of the contemporary liter- ature in the philosophy of mathematics, Scottish neo-logicism remains controver- sial, even for arithmetic. There are, for example, issues of Caesar and Bad Com- pany to deal with.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Forcing? Thomas Jech
    WHAT IS... ? Forcing? Thomas Jech What is forcing? Forcing is a remarkably powerful case that there exists no proof of the conjecture technique for the construction of models of set and no proof of its negation. theory. It was invented in 1963 by Paul Cohen1, To make this vague discussion more precise we who used it to prove the independence of the will first elaborate on the concepts of theorem and Continuum Hypothesis. He constructed a model proof. of set theory in which the Continuum Hypothesis What are theorems and proofs? It is a use- (CH) fails, thus showing that CH is not provable ful fact that every mathematical statement can from the axioms of set theory. be expressed in the language of set theory. All What is the Continuum Hypothesis? In 1873 mathematical objects can be regarded as sets, and Georg Cantor proved that the continuum is un- relations between them can be reduced to expres- countable: that there exists no mapping of the set sions that use only the relation ∈. It is not essential N of all integers onto the set R of all real numbers. how it is done, but it can be done: For instance, Since R contains N, we have 2ℵ0 > ℵ , where 2ℵ0 0 integers are certain finite sets, rational numbers and ℵ are the cardinalities of R and N, respec- 0 are pairs of integers, real numbers are identified tively. A question arises whether 2ℵ0 is equal to with Dedekind cuts in the rationals, functions the cardinal ℵ1, the immediate successor of ℵ0.
    [Show full text]
  • Multiple Forcing, by Thomas Jech. Cambridge Tracts in Mathematics, Vol. 88, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1986, Vii + 136 Pp., $34.50
    BOOK REVIEWS 103 REFERENCES 1. B. Blackadar, K-theory for operator algebras, MSRI Publications, no. 5, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1986. 2. L. Brown, R. Douglas and P. Fillmore, Extensions of C*-algebras and K-homology, Ann. of Math. (2) 105 (1977), 265-324. 3. A. Connes, A survey of foliations and operator algebras, Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., vol. 38, Amer. Math. Soc, Providence, R.I., 1982, pp. 521-628. 4. , Noncommutative differential geometry, Inst Hautes Études Sci. Publ. Math. 62 (1986), 257-360. 5. J. Cuntz, K-theory for certain C*-algebras, Ann. of Math. (2) 113 (1981), 181-197. 6. G. Elliott, On the classification of inductive limits of sequences of semi-simple finite dimensional algebras, J. Algebra 38 (1976), 29-44. 7. M. Karoubi, K-theory: An introduction, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1978. 8. G. Kasparov, The operator K-functor and extensions of C* -algebras, Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser. Mat. 44 (1980), 571-636. 9. , Equivariant KK-theory and the Novikov conjecture, Invent. Math. 91 (1988), 147- 201 (preliminary version was circulated already in 1981). 10. M. Pimsner and D. Voiculescu, Exact sequences for K-groups andExt-groups of certain cross-product C*-algebras, J. Operator Theory 4 (1980), 93-118. JOACHIM CUNTZ FACULTÉ DES SCIENCES DE LUMINY BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 20, Number 1, January 1989 ©1989 American Mathematical Society 0273-0979/89 $1.00 + $.25 per page Multiple forcing, by Thomas Jech. Cambridge Tracts in Mathematics, vol. 88, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1986, vii + 136 pp., $34.50.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory and Logic, Spring 2019
    MATH 71200 - Set Theory and Logic, Spring 2019 Dr. Gunter Fuchs Wednesday & Friday from 12:15 to 1:45pm, Room 9116 This course is going to develop the concept of a formal proof, or a deduction for first order predicate calculus. This purely syntactic concept will be shown to be equivalent to the semantic notion of logical consequence, which is defi- ned using model theory. This equivalence is known as G¨odel'sCompleteness Theorem, and it will be one of the main results this course is aiming at, the other one being G¨odel'sIncompleteness Theorem, which says that it cannot be decided by a finitistic algorithm whether a sentence is provable or not. In order to be able to state that theorem precisely, we shall briefly develop the basics of computability theory. All the proofs will take place in the framework of a weak set theory which will be used as the metatheory. This way, this course is intended to show how intricately model theory, computability theory, proof theory and set theory are intertwined. I will regularly pose homework problems. While I encourage students to discuss the problems together, everybody has to submit their own solutions. Students are asked to use LATEX to layout their solutions and submit printouts of their work, or to send them by email. There will be a final exam at the end of the semester, offered as part of the logic qualifier. The grade for the course will be the average of the homework grade and the final exam. To succeed in the course, it will be crucial to review the concepts, proofs and ideas presented in class.
    [Show full text]
  • Measure Algebras
    Measure Algebras Thomas Jech Warsaw, October 2013 Thomas Jech Measure Algebras Boolean σ-algebras Boolean algebra: a set B, operations a ∨ b, a ∧ b and −a; a partial ordering a ≤ b and the smallest and the greatest element, 0 and 1. If every countable subset A of B has a least upper bound W A (and the greatest lower bound V A) then B is a Boolean σ-algebra. Thomas Jech Measure Algebras Boolean σ-algebras Boolean algebra: a set B, operations a ∨ b, a ∧ b and −a; a partial ordering a ≤ b and the smallest and the greatest element, 0 and 1. If every countable subset A of B has a least upper bound W A (and the greatest lower bound V A) then B is a Boolean σ-algebra. B+ is the set of all nonzero elements of B. An antichain in B is a set A ⊂ B+ whose any two elements a, b are disjoint, i.e. a ∧ b = 0. A is maximal if W A = 1. Thomas Jech Measure Algebras Boolean σ-algebras Boolean algebra: a set B, operations a ∨ b, a ∧ b and −a; a partial ordering a ≤ b and the smallest and the greatest element, 0 and 1. If every countable subset A of B has a least upper bound W A (and the greatest lower bound V A) then B is a Boolean σ-algebra. B+ is the set of all nonzero elements of B. An antichain in B is a set A ⊂ B+ whose any two elements a, b are disjoint, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY for CATEGORY THEORY 3 the Category Is Well-Powered, Meaning That Each Object Has Only a Set of Iso- Morphism Classes of Subobjects
    SET THEORY FOR CATEGORY THEORY MICHAEL A. SHULMAN Abstract. Questions of set-theoretic size play an essential role in category theory, especially the distinction between sets and proper classes (or small sets and large sets). There are many different ways to formalize this, and which choice is made can have noticeable effects on what categorical constructions are permissible. In this expository paper we summarize and compare a num- ber of such “set-theoretic foundations for category theory,” and describe their implications for the everyday use of category theory. We assume the reader has some basic knowledge of category theory, but little or no prior experience with formal logic or set theory. 1. Introduction Since its earliest days, category theory has had to deal with set-theoretic ques- tions. This is because unlike in most fields of mathematics outside of set theory, questions of size play an essential role in category theory. A good example is Freyd’s Special Adjoint Functor Theorem: a functor from a complete, locally small, and well-powered category with a cogenerating set to a locally small category has a left adjoint if and only if it preserves small limits. This is always one of the first results I quote when people ask me “are there any real theorems in category theory?” So it is all the more striking that it involves in an essential way notions like ‘locally small’, ‘small limits’, and ‘cogenerating set’ which refer explicitly to the difference between sets and proper classes (or between small sets and large sets). Despite this, in my experience there is a certain amount of confusion among users and students of category theory about its foundations, and in particular about what constructions on large categories are or are not possible.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate
    SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2011 Committee: Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor Juan Bes Rieuwert Blok i Abstract Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor This manuscript was to show the equivalency of the Axiom of Choice, Zorn's Lemma and Zermelo's Well-Ordering Principle. Starting with a brief history of the development of set history, this work introduced the Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel, common applications of the axioms, and set theoretic descriptions of sets of numbers. The book, Introduction to Set Theory, by Karel Hrbacek and Thomas Jech was the primary resource with other sources providing additional background information. ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Warren Wm. McGovern for his assistance and guidance while working and writing this thesis. I also want to thank Reiuwert Blok and Juan Bes for being on my committee. Thank you to Dan Shifflet and Nate Iverson for help with the typesetting program LATEX. A personal thank you to my husband, Don, for his love and support. iii Contents Contents . iii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Naive Set Theory . 2 1.2 The Axiom of Choice . 4 1.3 Russell's Paradox . 5 2 Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel 7 2.1 First Order Logic . 7 2.2 The Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel . 8 2.3 The Recursive Theorem . 13 3 Development of Numbers 16 3.1 Natural Numbers and Integers . 16 3.2 Rational Numbers . 20 3.3 Real Numbers .
    [Show full text]
  • Minicourse on the Axioms of Zermelo and Fraenkel
    Minicourse on The Axioms of Zermelo and Fraenkel Heike Mildenberger January 15, 2021 Abstract These are the notes for a minicourse of four hours in the DAAD-summerschool in mathematical logic 2020. To be held virtually in G¨ottingen,October 10-16, 2020. 1 The Zermelo Fraenkel Axioms Axiom: a plausible postulate, seen as evident truth that needs not be proved. Logical axioms, e.g. A∧B → A for any statements A, B. We assume the Hilbert axioms, see below. Now we focus on the non-logical axioms, the ones about the underlying set the- oretic structure. Most of nowadays mathematics can be justified as built within the set theoretic universe or one of its extensions by classes or even a hierarchy of classes. In my lecture I will report on the Zermelo Fraenkel Axioms. If no axioms are mentioned, usually the proof is based on these axioms. However, be careful, for example nowaday’s known and accepted proof of Fermat’s last theorem by Wiles uses “ZFC and there are infinitely many strongly inaccessible cardinals”. It is conjectured that ZFC or even the Peano Arithmetic will do. The language of the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms is the first order logic L (τ) with signature τ = {∈}. The symbol ∈ stands for a binary relation. However, we will work in English and thus expand the language by many defined notions. If you are worried about how this is compatible with the statement “the language of set theory is L({∈})” you can study the theory of language expansions by defined symbols. E.g., you may read page 85ff in [15].
    [Show full text]
  • [Math.LO] 27 Oct 2000 N11 Htteeeit Atto Fteshr Nofu P Four Into Sphere the of Partition a Exists There That 1914 in a M;Pb.N.699 No
    RELATIONS BETWEEN SOME CARDINALS IN THE ABSENCE OF THE AXIOM OF CHOICE DEDICATED TO THE MEMORY OF PROF. HANS LAUCHLI¨ LORENZ HALBEISEN1 AND SAHARON SHELAH2 Abstract. If we assume the axiom of choice, then every two cardinal numbers are comparable. In the absence of the axiom of choice, this is no longer so. For a few cardinalities related to an arbitrary infinite set, we will give all the possible relationships between them, where possible means that the relationship is consistent with the axioms of set theory. Further we investigate the relationships between some other cardinal numbers in specific permutation models and give some results provable without using the axiom of choice. §1. Introduction. Using the axiom of choice, Felix Hausdorff proved in 1914 that there exists a partition of the sphere into four parts, S = A ∪˙ B ∪˙ C ∪˙ E, such that E has Lebesgue measure 0, the sets A, B, C are pairwise congruent and A is congruent to B ∪˙ C (cf. [9] or [10]). This theorem later became known as Hausdorff’s paradox. If we want to avoid this paradox, we only have to reject the axiom of choice. But if we do so, we will run into other paradoxical situations. For example, without the aid of any form of infinite choice we cannot prove that a partition of a given set m has at most as many parts as m has elements. Moreover, it is consistent with set theory that the real line can be partitioned into a family of cardinality strictly bigger than the cardinality of the real numbers (see Fact 8.6).
    [Show full text]