<<

CHAPTER EIGHT

UNDERSTANDING AND TEACHING RUDOLPH OTTO'S

"These words were chosen that that which could not be comprehended might yet in some measure be understood." -Hugh of St. Victor (Cited by Otto in the The Idea of the Holy)

Rudolph Otto's book on the holy is both simple and complex: simple in pre­ senting a single, compelling definition of 's meaning; complex in for­ mulating concepts that explain religion's origins and development. 1 Students who do not appreciate Otto's complexity run the risk of oversimplify the idea of the holy, rendering it a discrete religious object which can be experienced directly in the way the sun's light is experienced on hot summer days. This essay is devoted to a clarification of what is simple and what complex in Otto's account of the holy. Otto's descriptive account of the unique experience of religious feeling as mysterium tremendum etfascinans, is the simpler, more vivid, and perhaps more convincing part of his book. The complexity begins when Otto moves from a description of religious feeling to an analysis of the idea of the holy, the origins and of religion, and finally of religion's historical devel­ opment and fulfillment. This account which mixes phenomenology, episte­ mology, and in bewieldering amounts, seems at times to confuse rather than to clarify the nature of religious feeling. Yet it is a necessary part of Otto' account of religion, as we shall see. However complex Otto's argument is about religion his genius as a writer was to give his readers the confidence that has a unique content and a distinct meaning. He wrote that " if there be any single domain of human experience that presents us with something unmistakably specific and unique, peculiar to itself, assuredly it is that of the religious life." [4] In this respect Otto continued the task begun earlier by in 1799 with the publication of his Speeches on Religion To Its Culture Despisers, which was to defend the uniqueness of religion against the naturalists who would equate religion with ethics or reduce it to psycho­ logical and social reactions to life's situations. The dominant theological influence on Otto's idea of the holy was Luther's doctrine of justifification by alone. The main philosophical in-

1 All page numbers from Otto's book, The Idea of the Holy, are given in the text of this article, and the quotations are made from the Galaxy Book edition, New York, 1958, John W. Harvey, translator. 140 CHAPTER EIGHT fluence was 's notion of the a priori. Otto was also influenced by the interpretation given to Kant's by Jakob Fries and by the argument of that religion was a unique and valid category of meaning.2 Kant spoke of the a priori as a predisposition of the human mind to knowledge of the sensory world. Utilizing the a priori Otto argued there is a religious a priori or predisposition of mind to religious knowledge. That a priori, he named the holy (Das Heilige), and identified it as "a category of in­ terpretation and valuation peculiar to the sphere of religion." [5] We should understand Otto here to mean that the holy, which is part and parcel of our mind's working, makes it possible for us to recognize and appropriately re­ spond to religious experience as religious. This recognition occurs in the ex­ perience of certain feelings such as creatureliness, dread, awe, and wonder. Otto quotes with warm approval Kant's famous opening words of the Cri- tique of Pure Reason: That all our knowledge begins with experience there can be no doubt. For how is it possible that the faculty of cognition should be awakened into exercise oth­ erwise than by means of objects which affect our senses? . . . But, though all our knowledge begins with experience, it by no means follows that all arises out of experience." (112-113 J Adapting Kant's proposition about knowledge to religion, Otto wanted to ar­ gue that religion comes into being as the result of numinous feeling that is the experience of both an objective numinous reality (which seems to occasion religion) and an inner numinous, a priori mind (which causes religion). The connections here between exprience, mind, and object as affecting religion, so far as I can judge, is not made clear in Otto's major book on the holy or any of the other books which deal with the holy. In supposing that there is a con­ nection between the experience of numinous feeling to the religiously cogni­ tive and a priori capacity of mind, without actually explaining that connec­ tion, much of the confusion in Otto's account of religion occurs. The confusion becomes acute when one asks about the numinous object which Otto acknowledges [IO-II] as necessary to religious knowledge but never ex­ plains in its relation to the a priori working of the religious mind. Confusion might have been avoided had Otto made a clear distinction between what in religion is a matter of a priori knowledge and what is apprehended a poste­ riori, through experience. That he did not do. Repeatedly what we find in Otto's book is a hazing over of the difference subject and object, exerience

2 For useful discussion of the infuence of Luther, Schleiermacher, Kant, Fries, and Troeltsch on Otto, see Robert Davidson, s Interpretation ofReligion (Princeton: Princeton Uni­ versity Press, 1947) and Philip C. Almond, Rudolph Otto: An Introduction to His Philosophical Theology (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1984).