A Defense of the Identity Theory by ©2013 Nicholas K. Simmons Submitted To

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Defense of the Identity Theory by ©2013 Nicholas K. Simmons Submitted To Why Sensations Must be Neurological Properties: A Defense of the Identity Theory by ©2013 Nicholas K. Simmons Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Chairperson, John Bricke John Symons Thomas Tuozzo Ben Eggleston Michael Vitevitch Date Defended: April 16, 2013 The Dissertation Committee for Nicholas K. Simmons certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: Why Sensations Must be Neurological Properties: A Defense of the Identity Theory Chairperson, John Bricke Date Approved: April 16, 2013 ii ABSTRACT In this dissertation, I defend the thesis that qualitative mental states known as qualia (e.g., tastes, feelings, pains) are identical to physical properties. In Chapter 1, I argue that qualia have a functional role in the world, and that is to facilitate non-automatic mental processes. In Chapter 2, I demonstrate how non-reductive accounts of the mind fail. In Chapter 3, I demonstrate how my reductive account fares better than similar accounts with respect to common and contemporary objections. In Chapter 4, I address arguments against any view like mine which seeks to understand qualia in a physicalistic framework. iii CONTENTS Introduction ........................................................................................................................ 1 A BRIEF CHART OF THE TERRAIN .......................................................................... 2 Chapter One ........................................................................................................................ 5 What are Qualia For? ........................................................................................................... 5 § 1: ELIMINATIVISM AND EPIPHENOMENALISM ................................................ 6 § 1.1: Dennett’s Eliminativism ....................................................................................... 6 § 1.2: Epiphenomenalism ............................................................................................. 10 § 2: THE FUNCTION OF QUALIA ........................................................................... 14 § 2.1: The Function of Qualia ...................................................................................... 15 § 2.2: Possible Objections ............................................................................................. 18 § 2.3: Implications ....................................................................................................... 25 CONCLUSION ............................................................................................................ 27 Chapter Two ..................................................................................................................... 29 Non-Reductive Physicalism and Qualia ............................................................................. 29 § 1: STRONG NON-REDUCTIVE PHYSICALISM .................................................. 31 § 1.1: Davidson’s Argument for Non-reductive Physicalism ............................................ 31 § 1.2: The Causal Exclusion Problem ............................................................................ 33 § 1.21: One Proposed Solution: Functional Reduction ................................................. 37 § 1.22: Another Proposed Solution: Compatibilism ..................................................... 48 § 1.3: The Explanatory Exclusion Problem .................................................................... 51 § 2: A WEAKER FORM OF NRP ................................................................................ 57 § 2.1: Two Senses of ‘Explain’ ....................................................................................... 58 § 2.2: Weak Non-Reductive Physicalism ........................................................................ 60 § 2.3: Where Qualia Fit Into Our Picture ..................................................................... 64 CONCLUSION ............................................................................................................ 68 Chapter Three ................................................................................................................... 70 The Identity Theory ........................................................................................................... 70 § 1: THE IDENTITY THEORY AND ITS HISTORY ................................................ 71 § 1.1: Smart’s Modern Predecessors ............................................................................... 71 § 1.2: Smart’s Positive Account ..................................................................................... 72 iv § 1.3: A Negative Account ............................................................................................ 76 § 1.31: Semantic/Epistemic Objections ....................................................................... 77 § 1.32: Metaphysical Objections ................................................................................. 78 § 1.321: Kripke’s Modal Objection ...................................................................... 80 § 1.3211: Smart’s Reply to Kripke .................................................................... 84 § 1.3212: Hill’s Reply to Kripke ....................................................................... 85 § 1.3213: Soames’ Reply to Kripke ................................................................... 86 § 1.3214: A Thoroughly Externalist Approach .................................................. 89 § 1.322: After-Images .......................................................................................... 94 § 1.33: The Multiple Realzability Objection .................................................................. 97 § 2: CONTEMPORARY OBJECTIONS TO THE IDENTITY THEORY .............. 103 CONCLUSION .......................................................................................................... 109 Chapter Four ................................................................................................................... 111 Objections to Physicalist Accounts of Qualia ................................................................... 111 § 1: THE CONCEIVABILITY ARGUMENT ............................................................ 112 § 1.1: Two-dimensionalism and Conceivability ........................................................... 112 § 1.2: Responding to the Two-dimensional Argument ................................................... 117 § 1.21: Rejecting Two-dimensionalism ..................................................................... 117 § 1.22: From Semantics to Ontology? ........................................................................ 122 § 2: THE KNOWLEDGE ARGUMENT ................................................................... 123 § 2.1: The Argument in Detail ................................................................................... 124 § 2.2: The Phenomenal Concept Strategy ..................................................................... 126 § 2.21: Problems with PCS ...................................................................................... 127 § 2.22: Problems With Arguments Against PCS ........................................................ 128 § 2.23: Another Try With The Phenomenal Concept Strategy .................................... 131 § 3: IMPLICATIONS FOR THE EXPLANATORY GAP .......................................... 132 CONCLUSION .......................................................................................................... 134 Works Cited .................................................................................................................... 136 v INTRODUCTION We have a paradoxical relationship with the qualitative mental properties known as qualia. On the one hand, properties such as the sensation of the color red, the taste of ice cream, or the painful prick of a pin are intimately familiar. It seems obvious, for instance, how the taste of vanilla ice cream differs from the taste of chocolate ice cream. On the other hand, qualia are obstinately elusive, as we have yet to find a place for them in our understanding of the physical world. The natural place to look is the brain but, borrowing from Colin McGinn, we might despairingly wonder how “technicolor phenomenology” could possibly “arise from soggy gray matter” (1989, pg. 349). This problem has rightly come to be known as the hard problem of consciousness (Chalmers, 1996). Despite the admitted difficulty in solving this problem, I aim to make some headway towards reconciling our understanding of qualia with our understanding of the physical world. In particular, I shall defend an account known as the identity theory, the idea that qualia are nothing “over and above” certain (yet to be determined) kinds of brain states. The theory, itself, is not new, as it dates back at least to the 1950s (Place, 1956; Smart, 1959). But, since the 1960s, it has been nearly unanimously rejected by the philosophical and cognitive science communities in favor of an understanding of the mind as (ontologically autonomous) software “realized” by the (non-essential) hardware of the brain (Putnam, 1967). As I shall argue, this was a mistake. Indeed, as it is becoming increasingly apparent that the dominant “mind as software” account has no place for qualia (Kim, 2005),
Recommended publications
  • Putnam's Theory of Natural Kinds and Their Names Is Not The
    PUTNAM’S THEORY OF NATURAL KINDS AND THEIR NAMES IS NOT THE SAME AS KRIPKE’S IAN HACKING Collège de France Abstract Philosophers have been referring to the “Kripke–Putnam” theory of natural- kind terms for over 30 years. Although there is one common starting point, the two philosophers began with different motivations and presuppositions, and developed in different ways. Putnam’s publications on the topic evolved over the decades, certainly clarifying and probably modifying his analysis, while Kripke published nothing after 1980. The result is two very different theories about natural kinds and their names. Both accept that the meaning of a natural- kind term is not given by a description or defining properties, but is specified by its referents. From then on, Putnam rejected even the label, causal theory of reference, preferring to say historical, or collective. He called his own approach indexical. His account of substance identity stops short a number of objections that were later raised, such as what is called the qua problem. He came to reject the thought that water is necessarily H2O, and to denounce the idea of metaphysical necessity that goes beyond physical necessity. Essences never had a role in his analysis; there is no sense in which he was an essentialist. He thought of hidden structures as the usual determinant of natural kinds, but always insisted that what counts as a natural kind is relative to interests. “Natural kind” itself is itself an importantly theoretical concept, he argued. The paper also notes that Putnam says a great deal about what natural kinds are, while Kripke did not.
    [Show full text]
  • Bachelors, Energy, Cats and Water: Putnam on Kinds and Kind Terms by ÅSA WIKFORSS Stockholm University
    bs_bs_banner THEORIA, 2013, 79, 242–261 doi:10.1111/theo.12015 Bachelors, Energy, Cats and Water: Putnam on Kinds and Kind Terms by ÅSA WIKFORSS Stockholm University Abstract: Since Hilary Putnam and Saul Kripke’s first attacks on traditional, descriptivist theories of natural kind terms, it has become customary to speak of the ‘Putnam-Kripke’ view of meaning and reference. This article argues that this is a mistake, and that Putnam’s account of natural kind terms is importantly different from that of Kripke. In particular, Putnam has from the very start been sceptical of Kripke’s modal claims, and in later papers he explicitly rejects the proposal that theoretical identity statements are metaphysically necessary (if true). I suggest that this is wholly in line with Putnam’s earlier, Quine-inspired writings on general terms, and his preoccupation with the philosophy of science. Moreover, I argue that the picture of general terms that emerges from Putnam’s writings is more plausible than that suggested by Kripke. However, contrary to Putnam, I also suggest that Putnam’s later views on natural kinds and natural kind terms do not support standard Twin Earth externalism. Keywords: general terms, natural kinds, cluster theory, metaphysical necessity, externalism DURING THE LAST FEW decades the semantics of general terms has been dominated by the so-called ‘Putnam-Kripke view’ of meaning and reference. There is a reason Putnam and Kripke have come to be joined this way: about the same time, in the 1970s, they both developed views that sharply departed from the well-established, descriptivist views of the semantics of general terms and they both defended a radically new way of thinking about meaning and reference determination.1 In particular, they both rejected the idea that the meaning of general terms can be understood as a purely internal business, in complete independence of the causal interaction between the speaker and her environment.
    [Show full text]
  • FROM CONCEIVABILITY to POSSIBILITY an Essay in Modal Epistemology
    FROM CONCEIVABILITY TO POSSIBILITY An Essay in Modal Epistemology Anders Berglund UMEÅ STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY 8 FROM CONCEIVABILITY TO POSSIBILITY An Essay in Modal Epistemology Anders Berglund Umeå 2005 © Anders Berglund 2005 Series editors: Gunnar Andersson, Ingvar Johansson, and Sten Lindström Department of Philosophy and Linguistics Umeå University SE-901 87 Umeå, Sweden ISBN 91-7305-861-0 ISSN 1650-1748 Printed in Sweden by NRA Repro AB, Umeå 2005 Distributor: Department of Philosophy and Linguistics, Umeå University, SE-901 87 Umeå, Sweden. Persistence ABSTRACT This study deals with the thesis that conceivability implies possibility. Confronted with alleged counterexamples to this thesis, some philosophers have turned to what may be called “idealized” or “more demanding” notions of conceivability. I argue that in turning to such notions, they have made the thesis useless to limited beings like us for attaining modal knowledge. However, in refusing to identify conceivability with demanding or idealized notions, we cannot maintain that conceivability always implies possibility. Essentially, there are two ways to proceed: to view conceivability as a mere guide to possibility, or to argue that the conceivability thesis is a local truth, i.e., a truth with respect to a certain class of statements. I defend the latter alternative. This class of statements employs concepts with respect to which doubt concerning the conceivability thesis is to be regarded as general skepticism, not as skepticism relating to the conceivability thesis itself. I proceed by outlining an interpretation of strict possibility—i.e., the kind of possibility that I take the conceivability thesis to be about—according to which modal truths depend essentially on conceptual relations, as opposed to obtaining purely in virtue of properties of things themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • A Kantian Perspective
    Kripke’s metaphysical necessity: a Kantian perspective Ediovani Antônio Gaboardi [email protected] (Universidade Federal da Fronteira Sul, Santa Catarina, Brasil) Abstract: This article studies the concept of necessity in Kripke’s Naming and Necessity. Kripke distinguishes metaphysical from epistemological necessity. So, neoclassical and neo- empiricist positions are both wrong, because they remain in the epistemological realm. In Kripke, the epistemology becomes a psychological investigation about individual knowledge. It cannot deal with the problem of justification, and therefore cannot explain why there are necessarily true propositions. When he tries to do this, he falls into the trap of dialectics, as Kant warned. Finally, the article defends that the metaphysical domain is just an abstraction based on an objective epistemology. Keywords: Kripke; Kant; metaphysics; epistemology; necessity. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.11606/issn.2318-9800.v26i1p33-48 Introduction Kripke’s Naming and Necessity (1980), based on his lectures at Princeton University in 1970, challenges the Kant’s doctrine of a priori, a posteriori, necessity, and contingency. Its theses problematize the Kantian point of view and reintroduce the possibility of metaphysics inquiries in the philosophical field. This article tries to show that the distinction between metaphysics and epistemology is Kripke’s main strategy for sustaining the existence of necessary a posteriori judgments and contingent a priori judgments. However, this distinction is based on a misunderstanding of Kant’s objective epistemology and overlooks Kant’s criticisms of the metaphysics’ claim to know the world itself. Besides, this text defends that the distinction between metaphysics and epistemology has serious consequences that can restrict or even deny some epistemological or metaphysical claims.
    [Show full text]
  • Naming Without Necessity
    NAMING WITHOUT NECESSITY By NIGEL SABBARTON-LEARY A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Philosophy School of Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies College of Arts and Law The University of Birmingham March 2010 1 ABSTRACT In this thesis I argue that we should break with the dominant Kripkean tradition concerning natural kind terms and theoretical identity. I claim that there is just no interesting connection between the metaphysics and semantics of natural kind terms, and demonstrate this by constructing a version of descriptivism that is combined with the same metaphysics – that is, a nontrivial version of essentialism – found in Kripke, but which effectively avoids all of the standard criticisms. With my version of descriptivism in place, I present what I take to be the most reasonable version of metaphysical essentialism, positing only what I call ‗thin‘ essences. I claim that thin essences are perfectly adequate to underpin scientific realism, and moreover that they are sufficient to support the version of descriptivism developed here. In effect, what I offer here is an error theory of the Kripkean tradition: Kripke is right to think that there are interesting things to say about meaning and essence, but just wrong about what those things are. Thus whilst Kripke thinks that it is possible to make discoveries about the meanings of natural kind terms, I think, rather, that we make empirical discoveries that lead to revisions in meaning. Furthermore, whilst Kripke thinks there is a dichotomy between de re and de dicto necessity, and that theoretical identities are necessary de re, I think this distinction is both misleading and inaccurate, and that the necessity of theoretical identities is neither entirely de re nor entirely de dicto.
    [Show full text]
  • 158 I Critique of Pure Reason Was Historic in Many Important Respects. It Has Made Seminal Contributions in the Post-Kantian
    158 A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE NABANITA BHOWAL I Critique of Pure Reason was historic in many important respects. It has made seminal contributions in the post-Kantian era. The critical philosophy that he espoused there, has been influencing philosophical discourse since 1781 onwards. In the Introduction of that book Kant asserts that we are in possession of certain modes of a priori knowledge. Actually there he talks about four sorts of judgements or knowledge: a priori, a posterior, analytic and synthetic. In order to clarify the nature of these judgements he contrasted a priori with a posterior knowledge and analytic judgement with synthetic one. The necessity of explanations of these judgements was caused by his indomitable desire to show the possibility of a particular combination of judgements which his predecessors mostly considered impossible. The combination was between synthetic judgements and a priori judgements. In brief Kant wanted to demonstrate how synthetic a priori judgements are possible. The detailed explanation of various sorts of judgements in the Introduction paved the way for his demonstration. However, we should not presume that Kant was the first philosopher to talk about a priori knowledge in philosophy. The concept of a priori was, of before Kant the notions of a priori and a posteriori was used, though of course without mentioning these terms. Like many issues in philosophy we can trace the mention of these sorts of knowledge in ancient Greek philosophy. For example, in the dialogue Meno (380 B. C.) where Plato talks about theory of recollection we find the hint of a knowledge which is akin to a priori knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural-Kind Term Reference and the Discovery of Essence
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1998 Natural-kind term reference and the discovery of essence. Joseph F. LaPorte University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation LaPorte, Joseph F., "Natural-kind term reference and the discovery of essence." (1998). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2317. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2317 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UMASS/AMHERST 3120bb015ai5[D55 NATURAL-KIND TERM REFERENCE AND THE DISCOVERY OF ESSENCE A Dissertation Presented by JOSEPH F. LAPORTE Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY May 1998 Department of Philosophy © Copyright by Joseph F. LaPorte 1998 All Rights Reserved NATURAL-KIND TERM REFERENCE AND THE DISCOVERY OF ESSENCE A Dissertation Presented by JOSEPH F. LAPORTE Approved as to style and content by iruce Aune, Chair #yv LdLi LJcu Lynne Rudder Baker, Member Fred Feldman, Member i(J James Walker, Member John Robison, Department Head ^Department of Philosophy For my wife, Carmelita and for our children, Francis Lawrence and Emily Carmen. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I thank the journal for Nous permission to incorporate portions of my article “Chemical Kind Term Reference and the Discovery of Essence” (LaPorte 1996a) into Chapter 4 of the present work.
    [Show full text]
  • Essentialism, Reference and the Necessary a Posteriori
    Filosofia Unisinos 12(3):197-218, sep/dec 2011 © 2011 by Unisinos – doi: 10.4013/fsu.2011.123.01 Essentialism, reference and the necessary A posteriori Essencialismo, referência e o A posteriori necessário Mihai Rusu1 Babes-Bolyai University Abstract This paper elaborates on the epistemological incongruencies and shortcomings identifi ed in Kripke’s view on reference. I question the consistency of Kripke’s notion of a posteriori necessity and show that all purported examples of necessary a posteriori truth are in principle amenable to a priori knowledge. The relevance of the notion of epistemic modality is also put in doubt, at least in a realist framework. This conforms not only to Kantian usage, but also to the actual way we use names and natural kind terms. Conclusions about a more permissive view of reference that conciliates causal and descriptivist theories, but also essentialism and the skepticism engendered by any valid assessment of the limits of human knowledge, are supplemented by examples and arguments showing that our overall conception about the nature of reality and knowledge refl ects strongly upon our view of language and reference. Key words: essentialism, theory of reference, epistemic possibility, a priori, a posteriori, Saul Kripke, Scott Soames. Resumo Este artigo discorre sobre as incongruências e lacunas epistemológicas identifi cadas no ponto de vista de Kripke acerca das referências. Questiono a consistência da noção de Kripke sobre uma necessidade a posteriori e demonstro que todos os exemplos propostos de uma verdade necessária a posteriori são em princípio vinculadas a um conhecimento a priori. A relevância da noção de modalidade epistêmica é igualmente posta em dúvida no mínimo numa estrutura realista.
    [Show full text]
  • AN EVALUATION of SAUL KRIPKE's ARGUMENT for PROPERTY DUALISM THESIS Presented to the Graduate Council of Texas State Universit
    AN EVALUATION OF SAUL KRIPKE’S ARGUMENT FOR PROPERTY DUALISM THESIS Presented to the Graduate Council of Texas State University-San Marcos in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of ARTS by Thomas Hunter Chambers, B.A. San Marcos, Texas August 2013 AN EVALUATION OF SAUL KRIPKE’S ARGUMENT FOR PROPERTY DUALISM Committee Members Approved: ______________________________ Audrey McKinney, Chair ______________________________ Robert Fischer ______________________________ JoAnn Carson Approved: ______________________________ J. Michael Willoughby Dean of the Graduate College COPYRIGHT by Thomas Hunter Chambers 2013 FAIR USE AND AUTHOR’S PERMISSION STATEMENT Fair Use This work is protected by the Copyright Laws of the United States (Public Law 94-553, section 107). Consistent with fair use as defined in the Copyright Laws, brief quotations from this material are allowed with proper acknowledgment. Use of this material for financial gain without the author’s express written permission is not allowed. Duplication Permission As the copyright holder of this work I, Thomas Hunter Chambers, authorize duplication of this work, in whole or in part, for educational or scholarly purposes only. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to thank my thesis committee, Dr. Audrey McKinney, Dr. Robert Fischer, and Dr. JoAnn Carson, for their help in writing my thesis. Their comments, suggestions, and questions were insightful and helpful in the development of my thesis. This manuscript was submitted on June 20, 2013. v TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
    [Show full text]
  • The Necessity of Metaphysics
    The Necessity of Metaphysics Tuomas E. Tahko Department of Philosophy Durham University Ph.D. Thesis January 2008 ABSTRACT The purpose of this thesis is to demonstrate that metaphysics is a necessary discipline – necessary in the sense that all areas of philosophy, all areas of science, and in fact any type of rational activity at all would be impossible without a metaphysical background or metaphysical presuppositions. Because of the extremely strong nature of this claim, it is not possible to put forward a very simple argument, although I will attempt to construct one. A crucial issue here is what metaphysics in fact is – the nature of metaphysics. The conception of metaphysics which I support could be called Aristotelian, as opposed to Kantian: metaphysics is the first philosophy and the basis of all other philosophical and scientific inquiry. I will argue that this is indeed the most plausible conception of metaphysics. The thesis consists of a brief historical introduction of certain important views concerning the nature of metaphysics, namely Aristotle's, Kant's, Carnap's and Quine's, and of a longer survey of the status of metaphysics in the context of contemporary analytic metaphysics. I make some critical observations of recent accounts by people like Hilary Putnam, Michael Dummett, Frank Jackson and Eli Hirsch before launching into a thorough analysis of the relationship between metaphysics and other philosophical and scientific disciplines. The central argument of the thesis is that our a priori capabilities, which I claim to be grounded in metaphysical modality and ultimately in essences, are necessary for rational inquiry.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origins of Modal Error
    02_Bealer 13.09.2004 7:09 Uhr Seite 11 The Origins of Modal Error George BEALER† ABSTRACT Modal intuitions are the primary source of modal knowledge but also of modal error. According to the theory of modal error in this paper, modal intuitions retain their evidential force in spite of their fallibility, and erroneous modal intuitions are in principle identifiable and eliminable by subjecting our intuitions to a priori dialectic. After an inventory of standard sources of modal error, two further sources are examined in detail. The first source – namely, the failure to dis- tinguish between metaphysical possibility and various kinds of epistemic possibility – turns out to be comparatively easy to untangle and poses little threat to intuition-driven philosophical investigation. The second source is the local (i.e., temporary) misunderstanding of one’s con- cepts (as opposed to outright Burgean misunderstanding). This pathology may be understood on analogy with a patient who is given a clean bill of health at his annual check-up, despite his having a cold at the time of the check-up: although the patient’s health is locally (temporarily) disrupted, his overall health is sufficiently good to enable him to overcome the cold without external intervention. Even when our understanding of certain pivotal concepts has lapsed locally, our larger body of intuitions is sufficiently reliable to allow us, without intervention, to ferret out the modal errors resulting from this lapse in understanding by means of dialectic and/or a process of a priori reflection. This source of modal error, and our capacity to overcome it, has wide-ranging implications for philosophical method – including, in particular, its prom- ise for disarming skepticism about the classical method of intuition-driven philosophical inves- tigation itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Posteriority Entails Contingency and Conceivability Entails Possibility; That Is, the Relationship Between, and the Nature Of, Rationality and Modality
    Durham E-Theses Conceivability, Apriority and Modality WINSTANLEY, PAUL How to cite: WINSTANLEY, PAUL (2011) Conceivability, Apriority and Modality, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/860/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk Conceivability, Apriority and Modality Paul Winstanley Submitted for the degree of PhD Department of Philosophy University of Durham 2011 Abstract I aim to understand whether apriority entails necessity, aposteriority entails contingency and conceivability entails possibility; that is, the relationship between, and the nature of, rationality and modality. The thesis is split into two parts: one on apriority and modality (chs. 2-4), and another on conceivability, apriority/aposteriority and modality (chs. 5 to 7). In Chapter 1, I discuss ‘two-dimensional modal semantics’, arguing that it is ill-equipped to provide a substantive account of rationality and modality, before setting out the basis of such an understanding.
    [Show full text]