How the Many Worlds Interpretation Brings Common Sense to Paradoxical Quantum Experiments

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

How the Many Worlds Interpretation Brings Common Sense to Paradoxical Quantum Experiments How the Many Worlds Interpretation brings Common Sense to Paradoxical Quantum Experiments Kelvin J. McQueen and Lev Vaidman The many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics (MWI) states that the world we live in is just one among many parallel worlds. It is widely believed that because of this commitment to parallel worlds, the MWI violates common sense. Some go so far as to reject the MWI on this basis. This is despite its myriad of advantages to physics (e.g. consistency with relativity theory, mathematical simplicity, realism, determinism, etc.). Here, we make the case that common sense in fact favors the MWI. We argue that causal explanations are commonsensical only when they are local causal explanations. We present several quantum mechanical experiments that seem to exhibit nonlocal “action at a distance”. Under the assumption that only one world exists, these experiments seem immune to local causal explanation. However, we show that the MWI, by taking all worlds together, can provide local causal explanations of the experiments. The MWI therefore restores common sense to physical explanation. 1. Introduction The purpose of explanation is to help us understand why things happen as they do. Typically, one explains an event by citing the causes of that event. For example, to explain why the window broke, one might cite the throwing of a stone. A particularly compelling and natural type of causal explanation is local causal explanation. In a local causal explanation there is spatiotemporal continuity between the cause and the explained effect. For example, the thrown stone explains the broken window in part because the stone traces out a continuous trajectory from the stone-thrower’s hand to the window. In opposition to local explanations are nonlocal explanations. Nonlocal explanations involve “action at a distance”. Nonlocal explanations are rare in everyday life. Familiar cases are purported cases of psychokinesis, e.g., when people claim to bend spoons with their minds. If one explains the bending of a spoon in terms of an individual’s mental effort, then one is offering a nonlocal explanation, since there is no spatiotemporally continuous series of causes and effects connecting the mental effort and the spoon bending. 1 Common sense rejects such nonlocal explanations and presumes a hidden local cause of the spoon bending. And there is a good reason for this. A nonlocal explanation of X in terms of Y only tells us that X happens given Y. But an explanation should enable us to understand why X happens given Y. This is what local causal explanations offer. We understand why the window broke given the stone-throw because we understand the spatiotemporal continuity between the cause and the effect. Thus, if any type of explanation deserves to be called “common sense explanation”, it is local causal explanation. The point is a general one and is not specific to macroscopic objects. Whether we scale up to planets and galaxies or scale down to elementary particles, a causal explanation that leaves behind “gaps” in spacetime will in turn leave behind gaps in our understanding. Presumably this is why Einstein (1935) famously referred to action at a distance as “spooky”. In philosophy, there is an approach known as the common sense tradition. This approach takes various common sense beliefs as data for philosophical reflection and rejects those philosophical views that conflict with them (Lemos, ch.10, this edition). Here, we employ a similar approach in the context of physics. In particular, we argue that locality is a necessary condition for causal explanations to be commonsensical. We then take it as a requirement on an adequate physical theory that it be able to offer local causal explanations of all experimental outcomes. In the next section, we discuss how the demand for local causal explanation shaped classical physics. In section 3, we introduce quantum physics in the context of a simple experiment, which, while strange, can be explained locally. We then specify three refined common sense principles of locality. These principles are satisfied by classical physics and by the simple quantum experiment. However, in sections 4 and 5, we present several quantum experiments that do seem to violate the principles and therefore defy common sense. Finally, in section 6, we show that common sense can be restored to quantum theory if we adopt the many worlds interpretation (MWI). We show how the MWI is capable of giving local causal explanations of all these experiments. We conclude by discussing the significance of our results to debates over the interpretation of quantum mechanics. In particular, many reject the MWI by an appeal to common sense. As one philosopher puts it, “The most obvious disadvantage is that its burgeoning world of duplicate histories seem repugnant to common sense.” (Papineau 1995, 239). We will argue that our results suggest the contrary, that the advantages to common sense that the MWI provides outweigh its disadvantages. 2 2. Common sense explanation in classical physics The philosopher of science W.V.O. Quine (1957, 229) once said, “Science is not a substitute for common sense but an extension of it”. Accordingly, physicists seek local causal explanations of the motions of physical objects. This is clear in classical physics. For example, in Newtonian mechanics a body’s motion in a given region and time is explained by a force applied at that region and time. The exception is Newton’s law of gravitation. According to this law, a planet’s motion at a time is explained by a force applied by a distant planet at that time. However, Newton himself described this action at a distance as an “absurdity” and proclaimed the source of gravitational forces to be “hitherto unknown”. In fact, Newton went so far as to say: “Tis inconceivable that inanimate brute matter should (without the mediation of something else which is not material) operate upon and affect other matter without mutual contact. […] [T]hat one body may act upon another at a distance through a vacuum, without the mediation of anything else, by and through which their action and force may be conveyed from one to another, is to me so great an absurdity that I believe no man who has in philosophical matters a competent faculty of thinking can ever fall into it.” (Newton 2004, 102–3) Newton’s appeal to “a competent faculty of thinking” is an appeal to common sense. Newton is then proclaiming that his theory of gravity cannot offer any commonsensical explanation of gravitational motion, since it cannot offer a local causal explanation. (For recent debate over Newton’s views on action at a distance see Ducheyne (2014).) Later, Newton’s Law was understood in local terms by adding the concept of a gravitational field created by massive bodies. Classical (i.e. non-quantum) physics, then, describes point particles (“point-masses”) and fields spread out in spacetime. The point-masses create the fields which propagate with finite velocity. The motions of the point-masses are then affected locally by the fields of other point-masses. This physical ontology, together with Newton’s laws, Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory, and relativity theory, provides local explanations of many things we see around us. The common sense picture of classical physics ultimately consists in the motions of particles on continuous trajectories and the continuous propagation of waves with multiple trajectories, which includes the local phenomena of (constructive and destructive) interference. The motion of particles and the propagation of waves provide (common sense) causal connections. This includes continuous traces that moving particles and propagating waves leave behind in their local environments. The continuous propagation of waves and their local causal effects are illustrated by the Mach-Zehnder interferometer (MZI) (Zehnder 1891, and Mach 1892), see Fig.1. The electromagnetic wave (i.e. the photon) splits at the beamsplitter, passes through two arms of the interferometer and reunites at the second beamsplitter. The reuniting of the waves creates interference, which leads to observable effects. When the interferometer is properly 3 tuned, only detector D2 detects light. This is due to constructive interference towards D2 and destructive interference towards D1. If the distance of one path is lengthened by half of the wavelength of the electromagnetic wave, then only detector D1 receives light. Formally, classical physics places no constraints on interactions except that they be local. It is assumed that these local interactions never vanish completely and that the electromagnetic wave leaves some trace, e.g. heating of the air in the arms of the interferometer. Any such trace can in principle be detected, so the interferometer tuned as in Fig. 1a leaves an observable trace of the same form, see Fig. 1b. Figure 1: Mach-Zehnder interferometer (MZI). A beam of light is sent towards a beamsplitter, resulting in two beams of light. Each beam is then deflected towards a second beamsplitter, and then detected by one or both of the detectors. a) The interferometer is tuned so that the light comes only to detector D2. b) The trace left by the light in the interferometer tuned as in a). 3. Common sense explanation in quantum physics In 1986 Grangier et al. showed that the MZI exhibits interference when we send single photons through the interferometer. MZI interference is also routinely observed with neutrons (Rauch 1974). But even before that, the double slit experiment with attenuated light, where single photons would one-by-one build up an interference pattern on the detection screen, led to the radical picture of quantum theory: In some sense particles are waves! Let us first discuss a quantum particle and a single beamsplitter, Fig. 2. We observe that sometimes the particle passes undisturbed and sometimes it bounces from the beamsplitter 4 as if the beamsplitter was a mirror.
Recommended publications
  • Lev VAIDMAN Date & Place of Birth
    Name: Lev VAIDMAN Date & Place of Birth: 4 Sept 1955, Leningrad, Russia Date of arrival to Israel: 24 Sept 1973 Israeli Military Service: 10.12.77 { 10.03.80, officer of the IDF Marital Status: Married, 2 children A. Education 1972-1973 Leningrad University Physics 1973-1974 Ben-Gurion University Physics 1974-1976 Hebrew University Physics & Mathematics B.Sc. 1976 1980-1982 Weizmann Institute Physics M.Sc. 1982 1982-1987 Tel-Aviv University Physics Ph.D. 1987 Title of Master's thesis: Nonperturbative Sum Rules in Quantum Chromo-Dynamics Name of Supervisor: Prof. Hector Rubinstein Title of Doctoral Dissertation: The Problem of Measurement in Relativistic Quantum Theory Name of Supervisor: Prof. Yakir Aharonov B. Academic and professional experience 2005 - present U. of Tel-Aviv Full Professor 1998-2005 U. of Tel-Aviv Associate Professor 2000-2001 Centre for Quantum Comp., Oxford U-ty Visiting Professor 1995 - 1998 U. of Tel-Aviv Senior Lecturer 1998 April -June Institute of Advanced Studies, Jerusalem Visiting Professor 1996 July -August ITP, U. of California, Santa-Barbara Visiting Professor 1996 February-March Inst. of Exp. Physics, U. of Innsbruck Visiting Professor 1990 - 1995 U. of Tel-Aviv Senior Research Associate 1987 - 1990 U. of South Carolina Assistant Visiting Professor 1986 - 1987 U. of Tel-Aviv Senior Teaching Assistant 1 C. Active participation in scientific meetings. 1985 Microphysical Reality and Quantum Formalism, Urbino, Italy. 1986 New Techniques and Ideas in Quantum Measurements Theory, New-York. 1987 Frontiers of the Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics, Philadelphia. 1988 Bell's Theorem, Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe, Fairfax, MD.
    [Show full text]
  • Bacciagaluppi CV
    Guido Bacciagaluppi: Curriculum Vitae and List of Publications 1 December 2020 Born Milan (Italy), 24 August 1965. Italian citizen. Freudenthal Instituut Postbus 85.170 3508 AD Utrecht The Netherlands Email: [email protected] Tel.: +31 (0)30 253 5621 Fax: +31 (0)30 253 7494 Web: https://www.uu.nl/staff/GBacciagaluppi/Profile https://www.uu.nl/staff/GBacciagaluppi/Research https://www.uu.nl/staff/GBacciagaluppi/Teaching Research interests My main field of research is the philosophy of physics, in particular the philosophy of quantum theory, where I have worked on a variety of approaches, including modal interpretations (for my PhD), stochastic mechanics, Everett theory, de Broglie-Bohm pilot-wave theory and spontaneous collapse theories, with a special interest in the theory of decoherence. Other special interests include time (a)symmetry, the philosophy of probability, issues in the philosophy of logic, and the topics of emergence, causation, and empiricism. I also work on the history of quantum theory and have co-authored three books on the topic, including a widely admired monograph on the 1927 Solvay conference, and I am a contributor to the recent revival of interest in the figure and work of Grete Hermann. Present positions Academic: • Utrecht University: Associate Professor (UHD1, scale 14), Freudenthal Institute, Departement of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, and Descartes Centre for the History and Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, since September 2015. • SPHERE (CNRS, Paris 7, Paris 1), Paris: Associate Member since April 2015. • Foundational Questions Institute (http://fqxi.org/): Member since February 2015. • Institut d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques (CNRS, Paris 1, ENS), Paris: Associate Member since January 2007.
    [Show full text]
  • Time and Spacetime: the Crystallizing Block Universe
    Time and Spacetime: The Crystallizing Block Universe George F. R. Ellis∗ and Tony Rothman∗† ∗ †University of Cape Town, Rondebosch 7701, Cape, South Africa † Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 08544 A LTEX-ed October 26, 2018 Abstract The nature of the future is completely different from the nature of the past. When quantum effects are significant, the future shows all the signs of quantum weirdness, including duality, uncertainty, and entanglement. With the passage of time, after the time-irreversible process of state-vector reduction has taken place, the past emerges, with the previous quantum uncertainty replaced by the classical certainty of definite particle identities and states. The present time is where this transition largely takes place, but the process does not take place uniformly: Evidence from delayed choice and related experiments shows that isolated patches of quantum indeterminacy remain, and that their transition from probability to certainty only takes place later. Thus, when quantum effects are significant, the picture of a classical Evolving Block Universe (‘EBU’) cedes place to one of a Crystallizing Block Universe (‘CBU’), which reflects this quantum transition from indeterminacy to certainty, while nevertheless resembling the EBU on large enough scales. Keywords: Space-time, quantum uncertainty, arrow of time, block universe. 1 The Nature of Space Time: Emergent universes arXiv:0912.0808v1 [quant-ph] 4 Dec 2009 According to the spacetime view associated with both special and general relativity, time, in a real sense, is little more than an illusion. Given data at an arbitrary instant, we assume that everything occurring at a later or earlier time is determined, evolved according to time-reversible local physics.
    [Show full text]
  • Weak Measurements and the Two State Vector Formalism
    Weak measurements and the two state vector formalism Aharon Brodutch The aim of these four lectures is to make you familiar with the two state vec- tor formalism and weak measurements. I will try to keep the physical motivation alive throughout the lectures. The first three lectures will include the mathematical formalism used, with examples mixed in. I will explicitly derive a strong and weak measurement procedure using a qubit meter. This is unlike the majority of literature where the meter is a continuous variable system. I feel that the qubit derivation is simpler and the formalisms are very similar. I will however describe experimental implantations that are usually done with continuous degrees of freedom. I will also avoid discussion of mixed states and generalized two-state vectors. The lectures are planned as follows: In the first lecture I will discuss the two state vector formalism. In the second lecture I will go through the von Neumann measurement and the weak measurement schemes for projection operators. In the third lecture I will derive the weak measurement procedure in a more general way and discuss some of the properties of weak measurements. The final lecture will be used for discussing theoretical and experimental work done in the last decade (and a bit). I will cite the relevant literature as I go, at this point I will mention a few reviews. The first is my personal choice for an introduction to weak measurements of the two state vector formalism written by two of the originators of these ideas, Yakir Aharonov and Lev Vaidman [1].
    [Show full text]
  • Nonlinearities in the Quantum Measurement Process of Superconducting Qubits
    Nonlinearities in the quantum measurement process of superconducting qubits Ioana S¸erban M¨unchen, 2008 Nonlinearities in the quantum measurement process of superconducting qubits Ioana S¸erban Dissertation an der Fakult¨atf¨urPhysik der Ludwig–Maximilians–Universit¨at M¨unchen vorgelegt von Ioana S¸erban aus Bukarest, Rum¨anien M¨unchen, Mai 2008 Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Jan von Delft Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Frank K. Wilhelm Tag der m¨undlichen Pr¨ufung:09.07.2008 Contents Abstract 1 I Introduction 3 1 Quantum measurement 5 1.1 Quantum decoherence . 7 1.1.1 Open quantum systems . 8 1.2 Quantum optical methods for the solid state . 9 2 Quantum computing with superconducting devices 11 2.1 The Josephson effect . 13 2.2 Superconducting qubits . 16 2.2.1 Flux qubit readout . 19 II Flux qubit readout and control in the presence of decoher- ence 21 3 Dispersive readout protocols 23 3.1 Introduction . 24 3.2 From circuit to Hamiltonian . 26 3.3 Method . 30 3.4 Results . 33 3.4.1 Measurement . 33 3.4.2 Back-action on the qubit . 40 3.4.3 Comparison of dephasing and measurement times . 43 3.5 Conclusion . 45 3.6 Additional information . 46 3.6.1 Parameter conversion . 46 3.6.2 Parameters for the generalized Fokker-Planck equation . 47 vi CONTENTS 4 Qubit dephasing for dispersive readout 49 4.1 Introduction . 50 4.2 Method . 51 4.3 Weak qubit-oscillator coupling . 53 4.4 Strong qubit-oscillator coupling . 54 4.5 Conclusion . 56 4.6 Additional information . 56 5 QND-like, fast qubit measurement 59 5.1 Introduction .
    [Show full text]
  • Identity and Counterparthood in a Many Worlds Universe
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 2-2020 Identity and Counterparthood in a Many Worlds Universe Sophia A.M. Bishop The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/3575 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] Identity and Counterparthood in a Many Worlds Universe by Sophia A.M. Bishop A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2020 c 2020 Sophia A.M. Bishop All Rights Reserved ii Identity and Counterparthood in a Many Worlds Universe by Sophia A.M. Bishop This manuscript has been read and accepted by the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Date Michael Devitt Chair of Examining Committee Date Nickolas Pappas Executive Officer Supervisory Committee Graham Priest Michael Devitt Barry Loewer David Papineau The City University of New York iii ABSTRACT Identity and Counterparthood in a Many Worlds Universe by Sophia A.M. Bishop Advisor: Graham Priest The Many Worlds Interpretation of quantum mechanics - arguably our most powerfully predictive scientific theory to date - describes a branching Universe composed of an infinite number of quasi-classical macroscopic physical worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Nonlocality
    entropy Editorial Quantum Nonlocality Lev Vaidman Raymond and Beverly Sackler School of Physics and Astronomy, Tel-Aviv University, Tel-Aviv 69978, Israel; [email protected]; Tel.: +972545908806 Received: 23 April 2019; Accepted: 24 April 2019; Published: 29 April 2019 Keywords: nonlocality; entanglement; quantum The role of physics is to explain observed phenomena. Explanation in physics began as a causal chain of local actions. The first nonlocal action was Newton’s law of gravity, but Newton himself considered the nonlocal action to be something completely absurd which could not be true—and indeed, gravity today is explained through local action of the gravitational field. It is the quantum theory which made physicists believe that there was nonlocality in Nature. It also led to the acceptance of randomness in Nature, the existence of which is considered as another weakness of science today. In fact, I hope that it is possible to remove randomness and nonlocality from our description of Nature [1]. Accepting the existence of parallel worlds [2] eliminates randomness and avoids action at a distance, but it still does not remove nonlocality. This special issue of Entropy is an attempt to more deeply understand the nonlocality of the quantum theory. I am interested to explore the chances of removing nonlocality from the quantum theory, and such an attempt is the most desirable contribution to this special issue; however, other works presented here which characterize the quantum nonlocality and investigate the role of nonlocality as an explanation of observed phenomena also shed light on this question. It is important to understand what the meaning of nonlocality is in quantum theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Lev VAIDMAN Homepage: Education Period of Study Name of University Subject Degree Date of Award 1974
    Lev VAIDMAN Homepage: www.tau.ac.il/∼vaidman Education Period of Study Name of University Subject Degree Date of Award 1974 - 1976 Hebrew University Physics & Mathematics B.Sc 1976 1980 - 1982 Weizmann Institute Physics M.Sc. 1982 1982 - 1987 Tel-Aviv University Physics Ph.D. 1987 Academic and professional experience 2005 - present U. of Tel-Aviv Full Professor 1998 - 2005 U. of Tel-Aviv Associate Professor 2000 - 2001 Centre for Quantum Comp., Oxford U-ty Visiting Professor 1995 - 1998 U. of Tel-Aviv Senior Lecturer 1998 April -June Institute of Advanced Studies, Jerusalem Visiting Professor 1996 July -August ITP, U. of California, Santa-Barbara Visiting Professor 1996 February-March Inst. of Exp. Physics, U. of Innsbruck Visiting Professor 1990 - 1995 U. of Tel-Aviv Senior Research Associate 1987 - 1990 U. of South Carolina Assistant Visiting Professor 1986 - 1987 U. of Tel-Aviv Senior Teaching Assistant 1 C. Active participation in scientific meetings. 1985 Microphysical Reality and Quantum Formalism, Urbino, Italy. 1986 New Techniques and Ideas in Quantum Measurements Theory, New-York. 1987 Frontiers of the Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics, Philadelphia. 1988 Bell’s Theorem, Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe, Fairfax, MD. 1989 62 Years of Uncertainty: Inquiries into the Found. of Quantum Mechanics, Erice. 1989 Fundamental Aspects of Quantum Theory, Columbia, SC. 1989 Annual Meeting of South Carolina Philosophy Society. 1990 Workshop on Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Santa Fe, NM. 1991 Annual Meeting of Israel Psychology Society. 1992 Fundamental Aspects of Quantum Theory, Columbia, SC. 1992 Annual Meeting of Israel Physical Society, Rehovot. 1992 Quantum Physics and the Universe, Tokyo.
    [Show full text]
  • The Two-State Vector Formalism of Qauntum Mechanics: an Updated Review
    The Two-State Vector Formalism: an Updated Review Yakir Aharonov1,2 and Lev Vaidman1 1 School of Physics and Astronomy Raymond and Beverly Sackler Faculty of Exact Sciences Tel Aviv University, Tel-Aviv 69978, Israel 2 Department of Physics and Department of Computational and Data Sciences College of Science, George Mason University, Fairfax, VA 22030 Abstract. In this paper we present the two-state vector formalism of quantum me- chanics. It is a time-symmetrized approach to standard quantum theory particularly helpful for the analysis of experiments performed on pre- and post-selected ensembles. Several peculiar effects which naturally arise in this approach are considered. In partic- ular, the concept of “weak measurements” (standard measurements with weakening of the interaction) is discussed in depth revealing a very unusual but consistent picture. Also, a design of a gedanken experiment which implements a kind of quantum “time machine” is described. The issue of time-symmetry in the context of the two-state vector formalism is clarified. 1 Descriptions of quantum systems 1.1 The quantum state In the standard quantum mechanics, a system at a given time t is described completely by a quantum state Ψ , (1) | i defined by the results of measurements performed on the system in the past relative to the time t. (It might be that the system at time t is not described by a pure quantum state, but by a mixed state (density matrix). However, we can always assume that there is a composite system including this system which arXiv:quant-ph/0105101v2 10 Jun 2007 is in a pure state.) The status of a quantum state is controversial: there are many papers on reality of a quantum state and numerous interpretations of this “reality”.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comparison of Quantum Hoare Logic and Quantum Propositional Dynamic Logic
    A comparison of Quantum Hoare Logic and Quantum Propositional Dynamic Logic Pelle Nelissen June 26, 2020 Bachelor thesis Mathematics and Physics & Astronomy Supervisors: prof. dr. C.J.M. Schoutens, prof. dr. S.J.L. Smets Institute of Physics Institute for Logic, Language and Computation Faculty of Science University of Amsterdam Abstract Propositional Dynamic Logic (PDL) and Hoare Logic (HL) are two logical languages capable of verifying the correctness of classical computer programs. In order to verify the correctness of quantum computer programs, LQP [3] and QHL [31] were developed as quantum versions of PDL and HL respectively. In this thesis, we compare the two languages by applying them to two typically `quantum' algorithms { the Mermin paradox [20] and the Elitzur-Vaidman bomb tester [10]. We conclude that LQP is more equipped for formal logical purposes such as proving decidability and QHL is more applicable in quantum physics as a means of easily calculating the output of a given quantum program. Finally, we informally show that the expressivity of LQP and QHL are not comparable in the sense that both languages can express statements that the other language cannot express. Title: A comparison of Quantum Hoare Logic and Quantum Propositional Dynamic Logic Author: Pelle Nelissen, [email protected], 11184205 Supervisors: prof. dr. C.J.M. Schoutens, prof. dr. S.J.L. Smets Second graders: dr. M. Walter, dr. M. Ozols End date: June 26, 2020 Institute of Physics University of Amsterdam Science Park 904, 1098 XH Amsterdam https://iop.uva.nl Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Science Park 107, 1098 XG Amsterdam https://illc.uva.nl 2 Contents 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Locating Uncertainty, Subjective Probability and the Everett Interpretation
    Columbia University Master's Thesis Self-Locating Uncertainty, Subjective Probability and the Everett Interpretation Author: Supervisor: Keith Fraser Prof. David Albert A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Philosophical Foundations of Physics Graduate School of Arts and Sciences October 2014 COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY Abstract Philosophy Department Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Master of Arts Self-Locating Uncertainty, Subjective Probability and the Everett Interpretation by Keith Fraser This paper analyses an attempt to reintroduce the probabilistic predictions of quantum mechanics into the Everett interpretation. An overview of the measurement problem and the Everett interpretation are first given, with particular attention paid to the issue of probability within a deterministic theory. An argument is put forth that observers in an Everettian multiverse generically experience a period of post-measurement un- certainty in regards to their location. It is further argued that this uncertainty allows pre-measurement to observers to act as if they are uncertain about future outcomes. This is then the justification for attaching probabilities to the squared moduli of the wave function. It is also noted that there is an assumption of typicality present in dis- cussions of probability within Everett and some arguments to justify this assumption are considered. Contents ii Contents Abstract i 1 Introduction1 2 Quantum Mechanics and the Everett Interpretation3 2.1 Quantum Mechanics..............................3 2.1.1 Alternative Interpretations......................5 2.2 The Everett Interpretation...........................7 2.2.1 Everett in practice...........................7 2.2.2 Living in a Multiverse.........................9 2.3 A Primer on Probability...........................
    [Show full text]
  • Book of Abstracts Ii Contents
    6th International Conference on New Frontiers in Physics (ICNFP2017) Thursday, 17 August 2017 - Tuesday, 29 August 2017 Book of Abstracts ii Contents Azimutal angular correlations in high energy processes in QCD 1208 ........... 1 The Quark Parton Model of the Nucleon - Missing Links1265 ................ 1 Chiral fluids: a few theoretical issues 1435 ........................... 1 What Physics Beyond the Standard Model? 1452 ....................... 2 ATLAS overview highlight talk 977 .............................. 2 Jet and photon production and extraction of αs at HERA. 1189 ............... 2 LHCb overview 1447 ....................................... 3 CMS Overview 1453 ....................................... 3 Physics perspectives of PANDA at FAIR 1329 ......................... 4 Exotica searches at CMS 1111 .................................. 4 Hunting New Physics with ATLAS [ATLAS] 982 ....................... 4 Scale hierarchies in particle physics and cosmology 1482 .................. 5 New Searches in High Energy Particle Physics 1478 ..................... 5 Gauge Theories and non-Commutative Geometry. A review 1449 .............. 5 Prediction and discovery of doubly-heavy baryon 1490 ................... 6 Search for magnetic monopoles with the MoEDAL forward trapping detector in 13 TeV proton-proton collisions at the LHC 1200 ......................... 6 : Possible origin(s) of RD(*) flavor anomalies 1269 ...................... 7 Precision RENORM / MBR Diffraction Predictions Tested by Recent LHC Results 1450 . 7 Latest results on
    [Show full text]