Colimits and Profunctors

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Colimits and Profunctors Colimits and Profunctors Robert Par´e Dalhousie University [email protected] June 14, 2012 The Problem For two diagrams I JJ Γ Φ A what is the most general kind of morphism Γ / Φ which will produce a morphism lim Γ lim Φ? −! / −! Answer: A morphism lim Γ lim Φ. −! / −! Want something more syntactic? E.g. F IIJ/ J Γ Φ A The Problem For two diagrams I JJ Γ Φ A what is the most general kind of morphism Γ / Φ which will produce a morphism lim Γ lim Φ? −! / −! Answer: A morphism lim Γ lim Φ. −! / −! Want something more syntactic? E.g. F IIJφ / J +3 Γ Φ A Example A0 B0 g0 g1 f f 0 1 A / B B 1 p1 1 2 f h k A B p1f0 = g0p2 p1f1 = g0p3 g1p2 = g1p3 Thus we get hp1f0 = hg0p2 = kg1p2 = kg1p3 = hg0p3 = hp1f1 So there is a unique p such that pf = hp1. Problems I Different schemes (number of arrows, placement, equations) may give the same p I It might be difficult to compose such schemes On the positive side I It is equational so for any functor F : A / B for which the coequalizer and pushout below exist we get an induced morphism q The Problem (Refined) For two diagrams I JJ Γ Φ A what is the most general kind of morphism Γ / Φ which will produce a morphism lim F Γ lim F Φ −! / −! for every F : A B for which the lim's exist? / −! I Should be natural in F (in a way to be specified) op Take F to be the Yoneda embedding Y : A / SetA . Then we have the bijections lim Y Γ lim Y Φ −! / −! lim A(−; ΓI ) / lim A(−; ΦJ) −!I −!J hA(−; ΓI ) / lim A(−; ΦJ)i −!J I hx 2 lim A(ΓI ; ΦJ)i I −!J I An element of lim A(ΓI ; ΦJ) is an equivalence class of morphisms −!J a [ΓI / ΦJ]J where a ∼ a0 iff there is a path of diagrams ak ΓI / ΦJk Φjk ΓI / ΦJk+1 ak+1 Thus, to give a compatible family hx 2 lim A(ΓI ; ΦJ)i I −!J I we must give: aI I For each I , a JI and a morphism ΓI / ΦJI 0 i I For each I / I a path of J's and a's joining 0 Γi aI ΓI / ΓI / ΦJI with 0 ΓI / ΦJI 0 aI 0 0 0 Two such choices haI :ΓI / ΦJI i are haI :ΓI / ΦJI i are aI equivalent, if for each J there is a path joining ΓI / ΦJI with a0 I 0 ΓI / ΦJI . Theorem The above data induces for every F a morphism lim F Γ lim F Φ. Two such sets of data induce the same −! / −! morphism for all F iff they are equivalent as described above. p2 A0 / B0 g0 g1 f f 0 1 A / B B 1 p1 1 2 f1 p1 A0 / A1 / B1 O g0 f0 p1 p3 A0 / A1 / B1 A0 / B0 O g0 g1 A0 / B0 A0 / B2 p2 O g1 A / B 0 p2 0 Canonization Recalling our idea of F IIJ/ J φ +3 Γ Φ A we get for every I , a JI = FI , and a morphism aI = φI :ΓI / ΦFI . Naturality of φ gives a one-step path Γi φI ΓI 0 / ΓI / ΦFI ΦFi ΓI 0 / ΦFI 0 φI 0 In the general case I JI is not a functor. There can be several 0 JI , and for i : I / I we don't get a morphism JI / JI 0 but only a path. This is a kind f \relation between categories". They are called profunctors (distributors, bimodules, modules, relators). Profunctors op I A profunctor P : A • / B is a functor P : A × B / Set I Every functor F : A / B gives two profunctors op F∗ : A • / B; F∗ = B(F −; −): A × B / Set F ∗ : B • / A; F ∗ = B(−; F −): Bop × A / Set ∗ F∗ a F P Q I Composition A • / B • / C Z B Q ⊗ P(A; C) = Q(B; C) × P(A; B) x y = f[A • / B • / C]B g = fy ⊗B xg P Q 0 x y x0 0 y I A • / B • / C ∼ A • / B • / C if there is x y AAB• / BBC• / C y ⊗ x = y 0b ⊗ x b = y 0 ⊗ bx AAB• / B0 • / C = y 0 ⊗ x0 x0 y 0 Given functors Γ Φ I / A o J ∗ we get a profunctor Φ ⊗ Γ∗ : I • / J ∗ Φ ⊗ Γ∗(I ; J) = A(ΓI ; ΦJ): Proposition A compatible family hx 2 lim A(ΓI ; ΦJ)i determines a I J J ∗ −! profunctor P ⊆ Φ ⊗ Γ∗ with the property that for every F and every a 2 P(I ; J) we have Fa F ΓIIF/ F ΦJ injI injJ lim F Γ lim F Φ −! / −! for the morphism induced by hxi i. Proof. P(I ; J) = fa :ΓI / ΦJj[a] = [xI ]g. Total Profunctors Definition P : A • / B is total if for every A, lim P(A; B) =∼ 1: −!B Let T : A / 1 be the unique functor. Then P is total iff =∼ T∗ ⊗ P / T∗. Proposition (1) Total profunctors are closed under composition. (2) For any functor F : A / B,F∗ is total. (In particular IdA is total.) (3) If P and P ⊗ Q are total then Q is total. (4) Total profunctors are closed under connected colimits and quotients. (5) F ∗ is total iff F is final. Σ Θ ∗ (6) For I o K / J, Θ∗ ⊗ Σ is total iff Σ is final. Profunctors over A Definition For Γ : I / A and Φ : J / A, a profunctor from Γ to Φ (or a profunctor from I to J over A) is P IIJ• / J π Γ Φ A where P is a profunctor I • / J and ∗ π : P / A(Γ−; Φ−) = Φ ⊗ Γ∗ is a natural transformation. Profunctors over A compose in the \obvious" way: (Q; ) ⊗ (P; π) = (Q ⊗ P; ⊗ π) ⊗ π(y ⊗ x) = ( y)(πx): Theorem Let P IIJ• / J π Γ Φ A be a profunctor over A with P total. Then for every F : A / B for which lim F Γ and lim F Φ exist, there is a unique morphism −! −! lim F π : lim F Γ lim F Φ such that for every x 2 P(I ; J) we have −! −! / −! F π(x) F ΓIIF/ F ΓJ injI injJ lim F Γ/ lim F Φ −! lim F φ −! −! If (Q; ):Φ / Ψ is another total profunctor over A, we have lim F ( ⊗ π) = (lim F )(lim F π): −! −! −! Saturation Definition P / / Q : I • / J is saturated if x 2 Q(I ; J) and for some j j : J / J0, jx 2 P(I ; J0) implies x 2 P(I ; J). I P is saturated in Q iff for every I , P(I ; −) / / Q(I ; −) is complemented in SetJ. I Every P / / Q has a saturation P¯ / / Q. Theorem Let (P; π) and (P0; π0) be two total profunctors Γ • / Φ. Then they induce the same family lim F Γ / lim F Φ iff the images of ∗ 0 0 −! ∗ −! π : P / Φ ⊗ Γ∗ and π : P / Φ ⊗ Γ∗ have the same saturation. Naturality Definition A family of morphisms b : lim F Γ lim F Φ is natural if for F −! / −! every G we have b lim GF Γ GF lim GF Φ −! / −! G lim F Γ / G lim F Φ −! GbF −! Theorem A total profunctor over A induces a natural family as above. Every ∗ natural family comes from a total saturated profunctor ⊆ Φ ⊗ Γ∗. In fact there is a bijection between natural families and saturated ∗ total ⊆ Φ ⊗ Γ∗. Cohesive Families As remarked by B´enabou already in the 70's, a category over I K Λ I corresponds to a lax normal functor I / Prof where an object I is 0 sent to KI , the fibre over I and a morphism i : I / I to the profunctor Pi : KI • / KI 0 given by formula 0 k 0 Pi (K; K ) = fK / K jΛk = ig Definition Λ: K / I is a cohesive family of categories if each Pi is total. In elementary terms, for every K in K and every morphism k i :ΛK / I 0, there exists a morphism k : K / K 0 such that i = Λk and any two such liftings are connected by a path over i. k KKK/ K 0 ΛKIK / I 0 i Proposition (1) Opfibrations are cohesive families (2) Cohesive families are stable under pullback (3) Cohesive families are closed under composition Definition A cohesive family of diagrams in A is a span Γ KKA/ A Λ I with Λ cohesive. Let ΓI = ΓjKI . Theorem lim Γ extends to a unique functor lim Γ : I A such that for all −! I −! () / k : K / K 0 over i : I / I 0 Γk ΓK / ΓK 0 injK injK0 lim ΓI / lim Γ 0 −! lim Γ −! I −! i Kan Extensions lim Γ : I A is the left Kan extension and cohesiveness says it −! () / is fibrewise. So perhaps a more functorial version of the theorem is: Theorem Λ: K / I is cohesive iff for every pullback diagram F LLK/ K Σ Λ JIJ / I F and every cocomplete A, the canonical morphism F ∗ AL o AK Lan Lan Σ λ Λ AJ o AI F ∗ is an isomorphism. If we take = 1, F I 2 I, we get (Lan Γ)I ∼ lim Γ . J Λ = −! I The Comprehensive Factorization Set Cat Relations $ Profunctors Everywhere Defined $ Total Single Valued $ ? Functions $ Functors Recall the comprehensive factorization on Cat (Street & Walters '79).
Recommended publications
  • Compositional Game Theory, Compositionally
    Compositional Game Theory, Compositionally Robert Atkey Bruno Gavranovic´ Neil Ghani Clemens Kupke Jérémy Ledent Fredrik Nordvall Forsberg The MSP Group, University of Strathclyde Glasgow, Écosse Libre We present a new compositional approach to compositional game theory (CGT) based upon Arrows, a concept originally from functional programming, closely related to Tambara modules, and operators to build new Arrows from old. We model equilibria as a module over an Arrow and define an operator to build a new Arrow from such a module over an existing Arrow. We also model strategies as graded Arrows and define an operator which builds a new Arrow by taking the colimit of a graded Arrow. A final operator builds a graded Arrow from a graded bimodule. We use this compositional approach to CGT to show how known and previously unknown variants of open games can be proven to form symmetric monoidal categories. 1 Introduction A new strain of game theory — Compositional Game Theory (CGT) — was introduced recently [9]. At its core, CGT involves a completely new representation of games — open games — with operators for constructing larger and more complex games from smaller, simpler (and hence easier to reason about) ones. Despite recent substantial interest and further development [13, 10, 7, 6, 4, 11, 14], open games remain complex structures, e.g. the simplest form of an open game is an 8-tuple consisting of 4 ports, a set of strategies, play and coplay functions and an equilibrium predicate. More advanced versions [4] require sophisticated structures such as coends. This causes problems: (i) complex definitions lead to complex and even error prone proofs; (ii) proofs are programs and overly complex proofs turn into overly complex programs; (iii) even worse, this complexity deters experimentation and innovation, for instance the authors of [10] were deterred from trying alternative definitions as the work became prohibitive; and (iv) worse still, this complexity suggests we do not fully understand the mathematical structure of open games.
    [Show full text]
  • Monads and Interpolads in Bicategories
    Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 3, No. 8, 1997, pp. 182{212. MONADS AND INTERPOLADS IN BICATEGORIES JURGEN¨ KOSLOWSKI Transmitted by R. J. Wood ABSTRACT. Given a bicategory, Y , with stable local coequalizers, we construct a bicategory of monads Y -mnd by using lax functors from the generic 0-cell, 1-cell and 2-cell, respectively, into Y . Any lax functor into Y factors through Y -mnd and the 1-cells turn out to be the familiar bimodules. The locally ordered bicategory rel and its bicategory of monads both fail to be Cauchy-complete, but have a well-known Cauchy- completion in common. This prompts us to formulate a concept of Cauchy-completeness for bicategories that are not locally ordered and suggests a weakening of the notion of monad. For this purpose, we develop a calculus of general modules between unstruc- tured endo-1-cells. These behave well with respect to composition, but in general fail to have identities. To overcome this problem, we do not need to impose the full struc- ture of a monad on endo-1-cells. We show that associative coequalizing multiplications suffice and call the resulting structures interpolads. Together with structure-preserving i-modules these form a bicategory Y -int that is indeed Cauchy-complete, in our sense, and contains the bicategory of monads as a not necessarily full sub-bicategory. Inter- polads over rel are idempotent relations, over the suspension of set they correspond to interpolative semi-groups, and over spn they lead to a notion of \category without identities" also known as \taxonomy".
    [Show full text]
  • Higher Correspondences, Simplicial Maps and Inner Fibrations
    Higher correspondences, simplicial maps and inner fibrations Redi Haderi [email protected] May 2020 Abstract In this essay we propose a realization of Lurie’s claim that inner fi- brations p : X → C are classified by C-indexed diangrams in a ”higher category” whose objects are ∞-categories, morphisms are correspondences between them and higher morphisms are higher correspondences. We will obtain this as a corollary of a more general result which classifies all sim- plicial maps. Correspondences between ∞-categories, and simplicial sets in general, are a generalization of the concept of profunctor (or bimodule) for cat- egories. While categories, functors and profunctors are organized in a double category, we will exibit simplicial sets, simplicial maps, and corre- spondences as part of a simpliclal category. This allows us to make precise statements and proofs. Our main tool is the theory of double colimits. arXiv:2005.11597v1 [math.AT] 23 May 2020 1 Notation and terminology We will mostly observe standard notation and terminology. Generic categories are denoted by calligraphic capital letters C, D etc., while particular categories are denoted by the name of their objects in bold characters. For example Set, Cat, sSet are the categories of sets, categories and simplicial sets. ∆ denotes the category of finite ordinals and order preserving maps as usual, n while ∆ denotes the standard n-simplex. For a simplicial set X, Xn refers to its set of n-simplices. Given the nature of our discussion the term ”simplicial category” means simplicial object in the category of categories. We refer to simplicially enriched categories as sSet-categories.
    [Show full text]
  • Profunctors, Open Maps and Bisimulation
    BRICS RS-04-22 Cattani & Winskel: Profunctors, Open Maps and Bisimulation BRICS Basic Research in Computer Science Profunctors, Open Maps and Bisimulation Gian Luca Cattani Glynn Winskel BRICS Report Series RS-04-22 ISSN 0909-0878 October 2004 Copyright c 2004, Gian Luca Cattani & Glynn Winskel. BRICS, Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus. All rights reserved. Reproduction of all or part of this work is permitted for educational or research use on condition that this copyright notice is included in any copy. See back inner page for a list of recent BRICS Report Series publications. Copies may be obtained by contacting: BRICS Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus Ny Munkegade, building 540 DK–8000 Aarhus C Denmark Telephone: +45 8942 3360 Telefax: +45 8942 3255 Internet: [email protected] BRICS publications are in general accessible through the World Wide Web and anonymous FTP through these URLs: http://www.brics.dk ftp://ftp.brics.dk This document in subdirectory RS/04/22/ Profunctors, Open Maps and Bisimulation∗ Gian Luca Cattani DS Data Systems S.p.A., Via Ugozzolo 121/A, I-43100 Parma, Italy. Email: [email protected]. Glynn Winskel University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory, Cambridge CB3 0FD, England. Email: [email protected]. October 2004 Abstract This paper studies fundamental connections between profunctors (i.e., dis- tributors, or bimodules), open maps and bisimulation. In particular, it proves that a colimit preserving functor between presheaf categories (corresponding to a profunctor) preserves open maps and open map bisimulation. Consequently, the composition of profunctors preserves open maps as 2-cells.
    [Show full text]
  • Locally Cartesian Closed Categories, Coalgebras, and Containers
    U.U.D.M. Project Report 2013:5 Locally cartesian closed categories, coalgebras, and containers Tilo Wiklund Examensarbete i matematik, 15 hp Handledare: Erik Palmgren, Stockholms universitet Examinator: Vera Koponen Mars 2013 Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Contents 1 Algebras and Coalgebras 1 1.1 Morphisms .................................... 2 1.2 Initial and terminal structures ........................... 4 1.3 Functoriality .................................... 6 1.4 (Co)recursion ................................... 7 1.5 Building final coalgebras ............................. 9 2 Bundles 13 2.1 Sums and products ................................ 14 2.2 Exponentials, fibre-wise ............................. 18 2.3 Bundles, fibre-wise ................................ 19 2.4 Lifting functors .................................. 21 2.5 A choice theorem ................................. 22 3 Enriching bundles 25 3.1 Enriched categories ................................ 26 3.2 Underlying categories ............................... 29 3.3 Enriched functors ................................. 31 3.4 Convenient strengths ............................... 33 3.5 Natural transformations .............................. 41 4 Containers 45 4.1 Container functors ................................ 45 4.2 Natural transformations .............................. 47 4.3 Strengths, revisited ................................ 50 4.4 Using shapes ................................... 53 4.5 Final remarks ................................... 56 i Introduction
    [Show full text]
  • Ends and Coends
    THIS IS THE (CO)END, MY ONLY (CO)FRIEND FOSCO LOREGIAN† Abstract. The present note is a recollection of the most striking and use- ful applications of co/end calculus. We put a considerable effort in making arguments and constructions rather explicit: after having given a series of preliminary definitions, we characterize co/ends as particular co/limits; then we derive a number of results directly from this characterization. The last sections discuss the most interesting examples where co/end calculus serves as a powerful abstract way to do explicit computations in diverse fields like Algebra, Algebraic Topology and Category Theory. The appendices serve to sketch a number of results in theories heavily relying on co/end calculus; the reader who dares to arrive at this point, being completely introduced to the mysteries of co/end fu, can regard basically every statement as a guided exercise. Contents Introduction. 1 1. Dinaturality, extranaturality, co/wedges. 3 2. Yoneda reduction, Kan extensions. 13 3. The nerve and realization paradigm. 16 4. Weighted limits 21 5. Profunctors. 27 6. Operads. 33 Appendix A. Promonoidal categories 39 Appendix B. Fourier transforms via coends. 40 References 41 Introduction. The purpose of this survey is to familiarize the reader with the so-called co/end calculus, gathering a series of examples of its application; the author would like to stress clearly, from the very beginning, that the material presented here makes arXiv:1501.02503v2 [math.CT] 9 Feb 2015 no claim of originality: indeed, we put a special care in acknowledging carefully, where possible, each of the many authors whose work was an indispensable source in compiling this note.
    [Show full text]
  • ENRICHED CATEGORIES and COHOMOLOGY to Margery, Who Typed the Original Preprint in Milan
    Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories, No. 14, 2005, pp. 1–18. ENRICHED CATEGORIES AND COHOMOLOGY To Margery, who typed the original preprint in Milan ROSS STREET Author Commentary From the outset, the theories of ordinary categories and of additive categories were de- veloped in parallel. Indeed additive category theory was dominant in the early days. By additivity for a category I mean that each set of morphisms between two objects (each “hom”) is equipped with the structure of abelian group and composition on either side, with any morphism, distributes over addition: that is to say, the category is enriched in the monoidal category of abelian groups. “Enrichment” in this context is happening to the homs of the category. This enrichment in abelian groups is rather atypical since, for a category with finite products or finite coproducts, it is a property of the category rather than a structure. Linton, in [14], began developing the theory of categories enriched in monoidal cate- gories of sets with structure. Independently of each other, Eilenberg and Kelly recognized the need for studying categories enriched in the monoidal category of chain complexes of abelian groups: differential graded categories (or DG-categories). This led to the collab- oration [6] which began the theory of categories enriched in a general monoidal category, called the base. Soon after, in [1], Bénabou defined bicategories and morphisms between them. He observed that a bicategory with one object is the same as a monoidal category. He noted that a morphism of bicategories from the category 1 to Cat is what had been called (after [7]) a category together with a triple thereon; Bénabou called this a monad.
    [Show full text]
  • Profunctor Optics and Traversals
    Profunctor optics and traversals Mario Rom´an Hertford College University of Oxford arXiv:2001.08045v1 [cs.PL] 22 Jan 2020 A thesis submitted for the degree of MSc in Mathematics and Foundations of Computer Science Trinity 2019 Contents 1 Introduction6 1.1 Background and scope . .6 1.1.1 Lenses . .6 1.1.2 Prisms . .7 1.1.3 Traversals . .8 1.1.4 The problem of modularity . .8 1.1.5 Solving modularity . .9 1.2 Outline . .9 1.3 Contributions . 10 2 Preliminaries 12 2.1 (co)End calculus . 12 2.1.1 (co)Ends . 12 2.1.2 Fubini rule . 14 2.1.3 Yoneda lemma . 16 2.1.4 Kan extensions . 17 2.2 Monoids . 19 2.2.1 The category of monoids . 19 2.2.2 Applicative functors . 21 2.2.3 Morphisms of monads . 24 2.2.4 Monoidal actions . 26 2.3 The bicategory of profunctors . 27 2.3.1 Promonads . 27 2.3.2 Promonad modules . 28 2.4 Pseudomonic functors and replete subcategories . 28 3 Existential optics 30 3.1 Existential optics . 30 3.2 Lenses and prisms . 32 3.3 Traversals . 33 3.4 More examples of optics . 35 3.4.1 Grates . 35 2 3.4.2 Achromatic lenses . 35 3.4.3 Kaleidoscopes . 36 3.4.4 Algebraic lenses . 37 3.4.5 Setters and adapters . 38 3.4.6 Generalized lens . 38 3.4.7 Optics for (co)free . 39 4 Traversals 41 4.1 Traversables as coalgebras . 41 4.1.1 Traversable functors . 41 4.1.2 The shape-contents comonad .
    [Show full text]
  • Categorical Notions of Fibration
    CATEGORICAL NOTIONS OF FIBRATION FOSCO LOREGIAN AND EMILY RIEHL Abstract. Fibrations over a category B, introduced to category the- ory by Grothendieck, encode pseudo-functors Bop Cat, while the special case of discrete fibrations encode presheaves Bop → Set. A two- sided discrete variation encodes functors Bop × A → Set, which are also known as profunctors from A to B. By work of Street, all of these fi- bration notions can be defined internally to an arbitrary 2-category or bicategory. While the two-sided discrete fibrations model profunctors internally to Cat, unexpectedly, the dual two-sided codiscrete cofibra- tions are necessary to model V-profunctors internally to V-Cat. These notes were initially written by the second-named author to accompany a talk given in the Algebraic Topology and Category Theory Proseminar in the fall of 2010 at the University of Chicago. A few years later, the first-named author joined to expand and improve the internal exposition and external references. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Fibrations in 1-category theory 3 3. Fibrations in 2-categories 8 4. Fibrations in bicategories 12 References 17 1. Introduction Fibrations were introduced to category theory in [Gro61, Gro95] and de- veloped in [Gra66]. Ross Street gave definitions of fibrations internal to an arbitrary 2-category [Str74] and later bicategory [Str80]. Interpreted in the 2-category of categories, the 2-categorical definitions agree with the classical arXiv:1806.06129v2 [math.CT] 16 Feb 2019 ones, while the bicategorical definitions are more general. In this expository article, we tour the various categorical notions of fibra- tion in order of increasing complexity.
    [Show full text]
  • Profunctor Optics, a Categorical Update (Extended Abstract)
    Profunctor optics, a categorical update (Extended abstract) Mario Román, Bryce Clarke, Fosco Loregian, Emily Pillmore, Derek Elkins, Bartosz Milewski and Jeremy Gibbons September 5, 2019 NWPT’19, Taltech Motivation Part 1: Motivation Optics Optics are composable data accessors. They allow us to access and modify nested data structures. • Each family of optics encodes a data accessing pattern. • Lenses access subfields. • Prisms pattern match. • Traversals transform lists. • Two optics (of any two families!) can be directly composed. Lenses Definition (Oles, 1982) Lens (A; S) := (S ! A) × (S × A ! S): Lenses Definition (Oles, 1982) ! !! A S Lens ; := (S ! A) × (S × B ! T ): B T Lenses Prisms Definition ! !! A S Prism ; = (S ! T + A) × (B ! T ): B T Prisms Adapted from Penner’s @opticsbyexample Traversals Definition ! !! A S X Traversal ; = S ! An × (Bn ! T ) : B T n The problem of modularity • How to compose any two optics? • Even from dierent families of optics (lens+prism+traversal). • Simple but tedious code. • Every pair of families needs special attention. Profunctor optics Profunctor optics A Tambara module is a profunctor endowed with a natural transformation p(A; B) ! p(C ⊗ A; C ⊗ B) subject to some conditions. Every optic can be written as a function polymorphic on these Tambara modules. Why is this? Outline • Existential optics: a definition of optic. • Profunctor optics: on optics as parametric functions. • Composing optics: on how composition works. • Case study: on how to invent an optic. • Further work: and implementations. Preliminaries Part 2: Existential optics Parametricity as ends • We write 8 to denote polymorphism( actually, ends). • We write 9 to denote existential types( coends).
    [Show full text]
  • Profunctor Semantics for Linear Logic
    Profunctor Semantics for Linear Logic Lawrence H. Dunn III University of Oxford A thesis submitted for the degree of M.Sc Mathematics and the Foundations of Computer Science Trinity Term 2015 Abstract Linear logic is a sort of \resource-aware" logic underlying intuitionistic logic. Investigations into the proof theory of this logic typically revolve around proof nets, certain two-dimensional graphical representations of proofs. Where sequent calculus deductions enforce arbitrary distinctions between proofs and complicate these investigations, proof nets represent sequent calculus deductions up to a notion of equivalence suggested by the semantics provided by ∗-autonomous categories, at least for restricted fragments of the logic. Indeed, proof nets may be considered the string di- agrams of these categories. However, for fragments of the logic containing units for the multiplicative connectives, the coherence of ∗-autonomous categories implies an equivalence of proofs which prevents a canonical ex- tension of proof nets to the full system. This obstruction is what is meant by \the problem of units for proof nets." In this paper we begin to develop a geometric approach to the proof the- ory of linear logic which depicts proofs as three-dimensional surfaces. This line of research is made possible by Street's observation that ∗-autonomous categories are particular Frobenius pseudoalgebras in a monoidal bicate- gory prof. In some sense, proof nets can be embedded into these surfaces, but with a sort of \extra dimension." The central idea being developed is that coherence can be seen by visually exposing this extra structure and considering the result up to a suitable topological equivalence.
    [Show full text]
  • What You Needa Know About Yoneda: Profunctor Optics and the Yoneda Lemma (Functional Pearl)
    What You Needa Know about Yoneda Profunctor Optics and the Yoneda Lemma (Functional Pearl) GUILLAUME BOISSEAU, Department of Computer Science, University of Oxford, UK JEREMY GIBBONS, Department of Computer Science, University of Oxford, UK Profunctor optics are a neat and composable representation of bidirectional data accessors, including lenses, and their dual, prisms. The profunctor representation exploits higher-order functions and higher-kinded type constructor classes, but the relationship between this and the familiar representation in terms of ‘getter’ and ‘setter’ functions is not at all obvious. We derive the profunctor representation from the concrete representation, making the relationship clear. It turns out to be a fairly direct application of the Yoneda Lemma, arguably the most important result in category theory. We hope this derivation aids understanding of the profunctor representation. Conversely, it might also serve to provide some insight into the Yoneda Lemma. CCS Concepts: • Theory of computation → Program constructs; Categorical semantics; Type theory; • Software and its engineering → Abstract data types; Data types and structures; Patterns; Polymor- phism; Semantics; Additional Key Words and Phrases: Lens, prism, optic, profunctors, composable references, Yoneda Lemma. ACM Reference Format: Guillaume Boisseau and Jeremy Gibbons. 2018. What You Needa Know about Yoneda: Profunctor Optics and the Yoneda Lemma (Functional Pearl). Proc. ACM Program. Lang. 2, ICFP, Article 84 (September 2018), 27 pages. 84 https://doi.org/10.1145/3236779 1 INTRODUCTION There is a saying in English that you can tell a lot about a person by the company they keep. Similarly, the Dutch say zeg me wie uw vrienden zijn, dan zeg ik wie u bent—“tell me who your friends are, and I will tell you who you are”; and the Japanese for ‘human being’ is , constructed from the two kanji (‘nin’, meaning ‘person’) and (‘gen’, meaning ‘between’), conveying the idea that “you as a human being only exist through your relations with others” [Matsumoto 2018].
    [Show full text]