Philippa Foot's Ethical Naturalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philippa Foot's Ethical Naturalism http://dx.doi.org/10.15801/je.1.101.201505.101 Philippa Foot’s Ethical Naturalism Philippa Foot’s Ethical Naturalism: A Defense Chung, Hun(PhD, Philosophy, Cornell University)* 1 Abstract The main purpose of this paper is to defend Philippa Foot’s ethical naturalism from D.Z. Phillips and H.O. Mounce’s criticisms. The paper as a whole consist of two main parts. In Part I, I will introduce and explain Foot’s ethical naturalism. In Part II, I will defend Foot’s ethical naturalism from Phillips and Mounce’s several criticisms. Key words - Philippa Foot; Ethical Naturalism; Emotivism; Non-Cognitivism; Phillips and Mounce * Postdoctoral Fellow in Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, University of Arizona (from Aug 2015) Visiting Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Rochester Institute of Technology PhD Candidate in Political Science, University of Rochester Main Areas: Ethics, Political Philosophy, Rational Choice Theory (viz. Decision, Game, Social Choice Theory), Philosophy of Science/Social Science, Comparative Politics 101 Journal of Ethics, Vol. 101 (May 30, 2015). INTRODUCTION: OUTLINE OF THE ENTIRE PAPER The purpose of this paper is to defend Philippa Foot’s ethical naturalism; the theoretical stance that claims that moral and certain evaluative terms are, not just externally or contingently, but also internally and logically related to appropriate facts and objects. The paper as a whole consists of two main parts: Part I: Foot’s Project: Defending Ethical Naturalism; and Part II: A Reply to Phillips and Mounce’s Reply. The main objective of the first part, which is titled “Foot’s Project: Defending Ethical Naturalism”, is to introduce and explain, in rather detail, Foot’s metaethical stance that she expressed in her early papers; “Moral Argument” and “Moral Beliefs”. The first part is, again, divided into two sections. In the first section of Part I, titled, “Non-cognitivism: The Refutation of Naturalism”, I explain the modern trends of non-cognitivism and emotivism and its main characteristics, which is expressed in the philosophical views of philosophers such as Charles Stevenson1 and R. M. Hare2. According to modern non-cognitivism, the essential nature of evaluative terms is in its practical and action-guiding function rather than its cognitive function of stating facts about the world. It can be said that Foot’s ethical naturalism was mostly a reaction against this dominant view in contemporary ethical theory. In the second section of Part I, titled, “Foot’s Project: How Moral Terms are Internally Related to Facts”, I explain how Foot reacted against the emotivist’s views and how she tried to establish what the non-cognitivist theorists virtually denied: the internal relation between value terms and facts. Foot’s main strategy was to work from analogy. That is, Foot starts out with ordinary value terms such as ‘rude’ and ‘dangerous’ and tries to show how they can be internally related to certain factual states. After showing that this kind of internal relation is possible, Foot extends the points she had made to these other evaluative terms and generalizes it to moral terms and human virtues. Foot concludes that moral goodness and human virtues are internally related to the facts about human good and flourishing. Part II, which is titled “A Reply to Phillips and Mounce’ Criticisms”, introduces several criticisms that Phillips and Mounce raise against Foot’s ethical naturalism. The main objective of Part II is to defend Foot’s view from these several attacks by 1 See Charles Stevenson, “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms” 2 See R. M. Hare, The Language of Morals 102 Philippa Foot’s Ethical Naturalism showing where Phillips and Mounce had gone wrong. Part two is divided into three sections, which each deals with one of the specific criticisms that Phillips and Mounce raises. In the first section of Part II, titled, “Counterexamples to the internal relation to ‘Rude’”, I introduce Phillips and Mounce’s argument that the term ‘rude’ cannot be internally related to facts, and then argue back that, given that the specific context is fixed the term, ‘rude’ is always internally related to specific facts. In the second section of Part II, titled, “Counterexamples to the Necessary Badness of ‘Injury’”, I introduce Phillips and Mounce’s attempt to rebut Foot’s claim that injury is necessarily a bad thing. To this, I claim that injury is necessarily a bad thing in the sense that it always gives a person a defeasible reason to avoid it, and Phillips and Mounce did not understand Foot’s claim in a proper way. In the last section of Part II, titled, “Contestable Views of Human Good and Harm”, I introduce Phillips and Mounce’s argument that moral disagreements cannot be resolved by appealing to the facts about the human good and flourishing, since two people who agree on all of the non-evaluative facts, can, nonetheless, have different views about what constitute the human good and flourishing itself. To this, I contend that it is not obvious whether the two people in Phillips and Mounce’s example really had agreed on all of the non- evaluative facts that were relevant. So, it might turn out that their moral disagreement was essentially due to their disagreement in facts rather than due to their disagreement in their evaluative judgments. I then propose a distinction between the objective human good and the subjective human good, and argue that whenever there is a conflict between the two views about a certain matter’s goodness the correct answer would be the answer provided by the objective human good. PART I: FOOT’S PROJECT: DEFENDING EHTICAL NATURALISM I-1. Non-Cognitivism: The Refutation of Naturalism A lot of works in contemporary ethics have been devoted to what might be called the “refutation of naturalism”. Arguing against naturalism, or more specifically, arguing against ethical naturalism, has a long history that goes way back to David 103 Journal of Ethics, Vol. 101 (May 30, 2015). Hume who tried to show the impossibility of deducing an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’.3 The modern version of this stance has found its expression in the works of G. E. Moore4, who thought that if goodness cannot be a natural property, it must be a non-natural property. However, the most powerful version of contemporary anti-ethical naturalism was developed in the mid-20th century by philosophers such as R. M. Hare5, A. J. Ayer 6 and Charles Stevenson 7 . The position is now widely known as “Non- cognitivism”. According to non-cognitivism, moral judgments, and evaluative terms in general, have a very special function in our language that ordinary factual statements lack: namely, expressing one’s own feelings and attitudes about the matter in question. According to non-cognitivism, to judge that a certain behavior is morally good is simply to express one’s pro-attitude towards the behavior in question and to commend the person who has displayed such behavior. It is obvious that different people can have different attitudes towards the same subject matter: one person might enjoy heavy metal music, while another person abhors it. However, in such cases, neither of them could be said to be right or wrong. Each is simply entitled to his or her own musical tastes. According to non-cognitivism, the same thing applies to moral judgments and moral arguments in general. That is, two people who agree in all of the factual premises (about a certain behavior or a certain character trait) in a moral argument can, nonetheless, disagree in the final evaluative conclusion (that the behavior is morally good or that the character trait is a virtue) without any one of them committing a logical error. The non-cognitivist theorists contend that this never happens in a non-moral argument that deals with strictly factual matters. For example, if there is somebody who accepts all of the factual evidences that support the conclusion that the Earth is round, but denies this conclusion and rather contends that the Earth is flat, then we are justified in saying that this person is simply wrong and that this person doesn’t understand what the descriptive terms ‘round’ and ‘flat’ mean and uses them in his own peculiar way. In other words, for factual statements, it is already laid down by 3 This is not to deny that many people regard David Hume as an ethical naturalist himself. See David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, book III, part I, section I. 4 See G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica 5 See R. M. Hare, The Language of Morals 6 See A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic 7 See Charles Stevenson, “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms” 104 Philippa Foot’s Ethical Naturalism the meaning of the factual terms themselves on what can and what cannot count as evidence: that is, not anything can count as evidence that can support a factual statement saying that something is round, and, when proper evidence is shown, one cannot simply deny the conclusion by saying that he/she does not think that the proposed facts should count as evidence for the conclusion simply by pointing out that he/she has different standards. To say this is to simply commit a logical or a linguistic error. However, this is not the case with moral judgments and evaluations. One person might think that a certain fact about a behavior counts as evidence that supports the evaluative conclusion that the behavior is morally good, while another person refuses to count the same fact as evidence that supports the evaluative conclusion as such, without any one of them committing a logical or a linguistic error. In other words, there is no logical or necessary connection between evaluative terms and facts.
Recommended publications
  • Transition Booklet
    Religious Studies Year 11-12 Bridging Project Welcome to Religious Studies at A Level! Now that you’ve decided to study Religious Studies at A level, you’ll need to do a bit of preparation. This pack contains activities and resources to prepare you to start your A level in September. It is aimed to be used throughout the rest of the summer term and over the summer holidays to ensure you are ready to start your course in September. When you arrive to your first lesson in September you should also bring a folder, lined paper, dividers and plastic wallets. This course is split into 3 components: 1. Study of a Religion (Hinduism) 2. Ethics 3. Philosophy The resources include: A task for each of the three components. Including research, podcasts, reviews, questions and videos. There is also some suggested tasks to complete and books you could read. 1. Study of a Religion The religion you will be studying is Hinduism. Please read through this article https://www.hinduamerican.org/blog/12-things-you- need-to-know-about-hinduism/ from the article add a list of key terms and definitions you think will be useful for the course. You could also watch the following BBC documentary on Gandhi. Watch all 3 episodes and make notes on what Gandhi believed and why he was so important to the development of modern India. https://youtu.be/TQNbHVjC0sQ 2. Ethics Use the following website to choose a podcast that interests you. Listen to the podcast and write a review below. Think about the ethical issues that arise and arguments for and against the issue.
    [Show full text]
  • Educational Rights and the Roles of Virtues, Perfectionism, and Cultural Progress
    The Law of Education: Educational Rights and the Roles of Virtues, Perfectionism, and Cultural Progress R. GEORGE WRIGHT* I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 385 II. EDUCATION: PURPOSES, RECENT OUTCOMES, AND LEGAL MECHANISMS FOR REFORM ................................................................ 391 A. EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES AND RIGHTS LANGUAGE ...................... 391 B. SOME RECENT GROUNDS FOR CONCERN IN FULFILLING EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES ............................................................. 393 C. THE BROAD RANGE OF AVAILABLE TECHNIQUES FOR THE LEGAL REFORM OF EDUCATION ............................................................... 395 III. SOME LINKAGES BETWEEN EDUCATION AND THE BASIC VIRTUES, PERFECTIONISM, AND CULTURAL PROGRESS ..................................... 397 IV. VIRTUES AND THEIR LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM ...................................................................... 401 V. PERFECTIONISM AND ITS LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM ...................................................................... 410 VI. CULTURAL PROGRESS OVER TIME AND ITS LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM .............................................. 417 VII. CONCLUSION: EDUCATION LAW AS RIGHTS-CENTERED AND AS THE PURSUIT OF WORTHY VALUES AND GOALS: THE EXAMPLE OF HORNE V. FLORES ............................................................................................ 431 I. INTRODUCTION The law of education
    [Show full text]
  • Anscombe, Foot, and Contemporary Virtue Ethics
    J Value Inquiry (2010) 44:209–224 DOI 10.1007/s10790-010-9218-0 Virtue Ethics without Right Action: Anscombe, Foot, and Contemporary Virtue Ethics John Hacker-Wright Published online: 5 March 2010 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 1 Introduction Working out a criterion of morally right action is central to developing virtue ethics.1 Most advocates of virtue ethics believe that achieving such a criterion is crucial to vindicating virtue ethics as a normative theory. Yet the centrality of this task marks a departure from the views of at least some of the philosophers credited with the revival of virtue ethics in the twentieth century, especially from the views of G.E.M. Anscombe and Philippa Foot. Anscombe especially has sharp criticisms of the way philosophers handle the concept of morally right action along with related concepts like moral obligation. Yet the work of contemporary virtue ethicists such as Rosalind Hursthouse, Michael Slote, and Christine Swanton features little discussion of Anscombe’s criticisms or the reasons that the other virtue revivalists avoided providing a criterion of moral rightness. The dominant assumption appears to be that the earlier virtue revivalists neglect establishing a criterion of morally right action because their concern is to give priority to the evaluation of an agent over his acts as a corrective to the exclusive attention given to act-evaluation in the moral philosophy of the time. For Anscombe and Foot, at least, the concern to give priority to agent-evaluation is not among their motives for advocating a return to virtues.2 Instead, they believe that moral philosophers from the modern period forward have given the terms ‘‘right’’ and ‘‘ought’’ an artificial and incoherent sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Bernard Williams's Criticism of Aristotelian Naturalism
    UNDERSTANDING BERNARD WILLIAMS’S CRITICISM OF ARISTOTELIAN NATURALISM Michael Addison A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of MPhil at the University of St Andrews 2015 Full metadata for this item is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/9315 This item is protected by original copyright Understanding Bernard Williams’s Criticism of Aristotelian Naturalism. Michael Addison This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of MPhil at the University of St Andrews 19th November 2015 Abstract: In Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (henceforth ELP) Williams claims that holding a naturalistic Aristotelian ethical theory is no longer an option for us—we cannot believe what Aristotle believed about human beings. It is the purpose of this thesis to understand what Williams means by this claim and to evaluate whether or not it constitutes a pressing argument against Aristotelian naturalism. The modern Aristotelian (represented here by Martha Nussbaum, Philippa Foot and Rosalind Hursthouse) seems to be untouched by the claim as presented—they do not have to hold Aristotle’s view of human nature. The Aristotelian approaches human nature, not from an “outside” perspective, like the scientist, but from an “inside” perspective—from the point of view of an ethically engaged agent. The method does not seek to use a theory-independent notion of human nature to vindicate the Aristotelian claim that the properly functioning human being is virtuous. Rather, the Aristotelian is engaged in a project of using the notions of virtue that we already possess, to paint a picture of the kind of lives that we can all identify with, and endorse as properly functioning.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Intention and Normative Belief Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/8725w3wp Author Chislenko, Eugene Publication Date 2016 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Intention and Normative Belief By Eugene Chislenko A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in Charge: Professor Hannah Ginsborg, Co-Chair Professor R. Jay Wallace, Co-Chair Professor Hubert Dreyfus Professor Tania Lombrozo Spring 2016 Copyright by Eugene Chislenko 2016 Abstract Intention and Normative Belief by Eugene Chislenko Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor Hannah Ginsborg and Professor R. Jay Wallace, Co-Chairs People can be malicious, perverse, compulsive, self-destructive, indifferent, or in conflict with their own better judgment. This much is obvious—but on many traditional views, it seems puzzling or even impossible. Many philosophers, from Plato and Aristotle to Kant, Davidson, and others, have thought that we act only “under the guise of the good,” doing only what we see as good, or best, or what we ought to do. These “guise-of-the-good” views offered a way to make sense of the attribution and explanation of action, while maintaining a generous view of human nature as essentially pursuing the good. But are they not hopelessly narrow and naïve? It seems clear that we often do what we do not see as good, and even what we see as bad.
    [Show full text]
  • Anscombe Reading Aristotle*
    Enrahonar. An International Journal of Theoretical and Practical Reason 64, 2020 63-79 Anscombe reading Aristotle* Susana Cadilha Universidade Nova de Lisboa – IFILNOVA [email protected] Reception date: 4-11-2019 Acceptance date: 2-12-2019 Abstract Under one particular reading of it, Anscombe’s ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ is considered a seminal text in the revival of virtue ethics. Seen thus, Anscombe is implying that it is possible to do ethics without using concepts such as ‘moral ought’ or ‘moral obligation’, the perfect example being Aristotelian ethics. On the other hand, Anscombe claims that it is not useful at present to engage in moral philosophy since she finds that ‘philosophically there is a huge gap… which needs to be filled by an account of human nature, human action, …and above all of human “flourishing”’ (Anscombe, 1958: 18). The gap Anscombe refers to appears where there should be a ‘proof that an unjust man is a bad man’. My aim in this paper is to discuss the various ways in which Anscombe’s theses can be interpreted, recalling two other philosophers for whom Aristotelian virtue ethics was also essential: P. Foot and J. McDowell. I will argue that Anscombe did not expect Aristotelian ethics to answer the problems modern ethics poses. Keywords: ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’; Aristotelian ethics; virtue ethics; moral naturalism; Philippa Foot; John McDowell Resum. Anscombe llegint a Aristòtil Fent-ne una lectura particular, «Modern Moral Philosophy» (La filosofia moral moder- na) d’Anscombe es considera un text fundador en el renaixement de l’ètica de la virtut. Vist així, Anscombe insinua que és possible fer ètica sense emprar conceptes com «deure moral» o «obligació moral»; l’exemple perfecte n’és l’ètica aristotèlica.
    [Show full text]
  • Maynooth Philosophical Papers Issue 5 (2008)
    MAYNOOTH PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS ISSUE 5 (2008) An Anthology of Current Research from the Department of Philosophy, NUI Maynooth Issue Editor: Simon Nolan General Editor: Michael Dunne This issue of Maynooth )hilosophical apers is dedicated to the memory of !r#$%&&#r J#)n ,%ary M123 Associate Professor of Philosophy at NUI, Maynooth who died on April 12th, 2009. ISBN 978 0 901519 627 © 2009 The Department of Philosophy, National University of Ireland — Maynooth, and the Individual Authors +4567568 rrd by Dr Michael Dunne i u dr nrdun ii Michael Dunne Aodh Mac Aingil (Hugo Cavellus, 1571–1626) on Doubt, Evidence and Certitude 1 Patrick Gorevan Philippa Foot’s ‘Natural Goodness’ 9 Mette Lebech Stein’s Phenomenology of the Body: The constitution of the human being between description of experience and social construction 16 Cyril McDonnell Why Punish the Guilty? Towards a Philosophical Analysis of the State’s Justification of Punishment 21 Simon Nolan Teaching and Learning in the Summa theologiae of Gerard of Bologna (d. 1317) 35 Wayne Waxman Universality and the Analytic Unity of Apperception in Kant: a reading of CPR B133-4n 42 178731+ Susan Byrne Remarks on Ludwig Wittgenstein and Behaviourism 49 John Haydn Gurmin A Bibliography of English Language Commentaries on the Philosophy of Edith Stein 57 Conleth Loonan The De mixtione elementorum of Thomas Aquinas 75 9#r%:#rd It is my great pleasure as general editor of the Maynooth hilosophical apers to write the foreword to this year’s edition of our journal which is the fifth volume in the series. My heartfelt thanks and warmest congratulations to all of the contributors, both staff and students, and especially to the volume editor, Fr Simon Nolan, for doing such a wonderful job in bringing together this valuable collection of papers.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Problems for Aristotelian Naturalism in Contemporary Moral Philosophy
    SOFIA MIGUENS* IS THERE A SINGLE WAY FOR ALL HUMANS TO BE HUMAN? SOME PROBLEMS FOR ARISTOTELIAN NATURALISM IN CONTEMPORARY MORAL PHILOSOPHY Abstract Aristotelian naturalists may have diverging interpretations of Aristotle’s idea that the good life for a human being is a life of activity in accordance with the virtues. Such is the case of John McDowell (McDowell 1998) and Philippa Foot (Foot 1978). One important question here is whether Aristotelian naturalism in moral philoso- phy commits one to the idea of a good, or goods, which are natural to humans qua humans. Naturalism is a very widespread position in contemporary analytic philoso- phy yet not always very clearly spelled out. In order to search for clarity regarding what one means by naturalism, I explore several strands of McDowell’s case for sec- ond-nature naturalism as a position in moral philosophy. I then assess an argument put forward against it by Bernard Williams in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Williams 1985). Building on a suggestion by Alan Thomas in Value and Context –1 The nature of moral and political knowledge (Thomas 2006) and complementing * Associate Professor at the Department of Philosophy and researcher at the Institute of Philosophy, University of Porto. Director of Modern and Contemporary Philosophy Bureau and Principal Investigator of the Mind, Language and Action Group (MLAG). Research interests: Philosophy of Mind and Language, Epistemology and Cognitive Science, Moral Philosophy. Filosofia. Revista da Faculdade de Letras da Universidade do Porto, 34 (2017) 167-186 167 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.21747/21836892/fil34a7 SOFIA MIGUENS it with a view of rationality inspired by S.Stich (The Fragmentation of Reason, Stich 1990) I end with a proposal on how to keep Aristotelianism in moral philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILIPPA FOOT Philippa Ruth Foot 1920–2010
    PHILIPPA FOOT Philippa Ruth Foot 1920–2010 I PHILIPPA RUTH FOOT was born on 3 October 1920, the second daughter of William Bosanquet, who had done mathematics at Cambridge and became the manager of a steelworks in Yorkshire, and Esther Cleveland, daughter of President Grover Cleveland. She was educated mainly at home in the country by governesses, and not well. She said, many years later, that, ‘unsurprisingly’, she had been left ‘extremely ignorant’, and when the last one, ‘who actually had a degree’, suggested to her that she should go to Oxford, she had to work for it. She spent a year with an established Oxford entrance coach and took a correspondence course to acquire the necessary entrance Latin; the result was a place at Somerville College, where she went to read Philosophy, Politics and Economics (PPE) in 1939. She graduated with First Class Honours in 1942, and, like many of her female contemporaries, immediately looked for ‘war work’. After a year working in Oxford for the Nuffield Social Reconstruction Survey, she moved to work in London where she remained until the end of the war. There she married the historian M. R. D. Foot in June 1945 and, with him, returned to Oxford later that year where she took up a teaching posi- tion at Somerville (the marriage was dissolved in 1960). She became their first Tutorial Fellow in Philosophy in 1949, Vice-Principal in 1967, and, although she resigned her fellowship in 1969, she retained, as a Senior Research Fellow and then Honorary Fellow, very close links with the College and Somervillians, past and present, until the end of her life.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy
    Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy Philippa Foot Great Clarendon Street, Oxford Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi São Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © in this edition, Philippa Foot 2002 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 1978 by Blackwell Publishers and University of California Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Philippa Foot Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Foot, Philippa. Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy/Philippa Foot.
    [Show full text]
  • International Journal of Applied Science and Research
    International Journal of Applied Science and Research THE PRIMACY OF VIRTUES IN PREVENTING AND ERADICATING SOCIO- POLITICAL EVIL, IN THE PERSPECTIVE OF PHILIPPAFOOT Benoît, Mondji, Kodjo, Agbégnigan 1st Co-author: Rev. Dr. Simon, Njuguna 2nd Co-author: Rev. Dr. Paul, Nyaga Faculty of Arts and Social Science/Philosophy, the Catholic University of Eastern Africa (CUEA), Nairobi, Kenya IJASR 2020 VOLUME 3 ISSUE 3 MAY – JUNE ISSN: 2581-7876 Abstract – Among all animals, the human person is capable of leading a moral life. He is a rational being who is able to live a virtuous life. We can see that virtuous life which is solely human. Unfortunately, the same human person who is imbued with rationality and free-will, becomes an obstacle to the expression of that freedom and rationality of others, when it is a matter of politics and development. This is because people overthrow ethical values by promoting other values which are contrary to the virtues because of the schools of thought to which one belongs. This situation brings into our society, the perpetuation of many evils: moral, physical and metaphysical. In such conditions who shall we blame? Is it the socio-political system that transforms human person or the human person that transforms society? Where has gone the notion of virtue which is intrinsic to human being gone to? This study is meant to help human persons understand the importance of virtue in one’s life and its role in socio- political and development agenda. The reawakening of virtue in society becomes a way for us to rebuild a firm foundation for society.
    [Show full text]
  • Sui Generis Or Supernatural?
    NON-NATURAL MORAL PROPERTIES: SUI GENERIS OR SUPERNATURAL? Jessica Katz A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY December 2018 Committee: Christian Coons, Advisor Alfred DeMaris, Graduate Faculty Representative Michael Weber Sara Worley Copyright c August 2018 Jessica Katz All rights reserved iii ABSTRACT Christian Coons, Advisor If we grant that some moral claims are true, what is it that makes them true? Throughout the vast majority of history, it was believed that God was the source of morality. But the twentieth century saw a shift in ethics. Influenced by logical positivism and a broadly naturalistic worldview, scholars sought to develop a theory of ethics that did not depend on God’s existence. One leading approach was moral naturalism, the view that moral properties are natural and thus can be investigated by scientific methods. But this view was plagued with problems, leading many to conclude that moral and natural facts were just too different to be one and the same. Having rejected a divine conception of ethics and moral naturalism, some scholars turned to moral non-naturalism - the view that moral properties are not natural. One particular form of moral non-naturalism entails that moral properties are sui generis. I call this view Moorean realism. The current trend suggests that Moorean realism is preferable to divine command theory, a competing form of moral non-naturalism wherein moral properties are reducible to supernatural properties. But, as far as the salient objections go, divine command theory is at least as plausible as Moorean realism.
    [Show full text]