Islam in the Secular Nomos of the European Court of Human Rights

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Islam in the Secular Nomos of the European Court of Human Rights Michigan Journal of International Law Volume 32 Issue 4 2011 Islam in the Secular Nomos of the European Court of Human Rights Peter G. Danchin University of Maryland School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjil Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons, Courts Commons, European Law Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Recommended Citation Peter G. Danchin, Islam in the Secular Nomos of the European Court of Human Rights, 32 MICH. J. INT'L L. 663 (2011). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjil/vol32/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Journal of International Law at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ISLAM IN THE SECULAR NOMOS OF THE EUROPEAN COURT OF HUMAN RIGHTS Peter G. Danchin* INTRODUCTION ..................................................... 664 I. THE CONCEPT OF THE SECULAR PUBLIC SPHERE....................673 A. The Antinomies of Secularism ........................674 1. The Right to Freedom of Religion and Belief ............ 675 2. Public Reason and Private Faith ...... ......... 682 3. The Authority of Public Reason....... ............... 683 B. Rethinking the Secular .................... .... 685 C. Between Rationality and Reason. ........... ..... 690 II. RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN ECHR JURISPRUDENCE ........ ..... 692 A. The Rights of Religious Minorities........... ..... 692 B. Freedomfrom Injury to Religious Feelings.... ...... 693 C. The Claims of Muslim Communities ......... ........ 696 III. ISLAM IN ARTICLE 9 JURISPRUDENCE........................705 A. The Scope of the Right to Religious Freedom....................707 1. Enlightenment Rationalism......................709 2. Value Pluralism........................715 3. Pluralism and Islam ...............................723 B. Public Order and the Rights of Others.............728 1. Rival Enlightenments ..............................731 2. From Blasphemy to Incitement to Religious Hatred .. 735 C. Is "Secularism" Necessary in a Democratic Society?......741 CONCLUSION ............................................... ........ 744 * Associate Professor of Law and Director of the International and Comparative Law Program, University of Maryland School of Law. B.A., LL.B. (Hons.), University of Melbourne; LL.M., J.S.D., Columbia University. An early version of this Article was pre- sented at the 2010 Association of American Law Schools symposium on The Freedom of Religion and Belief Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights: Legal, Moral, Political and Religious Perspectives. I am grateful to Zachary Calo, Cole Durham, Carolyn Evans, Mark Modak-Truran, Gerhard Robbers, Brett Scharffs, and the other participants for their insights. Later versions were presented at workshops at the University of Maryland School of Law, Princeton University, and the University of California, Berkeley. I wish to thank Martha Ertman, Silvio Ferrari, Michelle Harner, Leslie Meltzer Henry, Elizabeth Shak- man Hurd, Saba Mahmood, and Winnifred Fallers Sullivan for their comments and criticisms. All errors and omissions are my own. 663 664 Michigan Journal of InternationalLaw [Vol. 32:663 We inhabit a nomos-a normative universe. We constantly create and maintain a world of right and wrong, of lawful and unlaw- ful, of valid and void. The student of law may come to identify the normative world with the professional paraphernaliaof so- cial control. The rules and principles of justice, the formal institutions of the law, and the conventions of social order are, indeed, important to that world; they are, however but a small part of the normative universe that ought to claim our attention. No set of legal institutions or prescriptionsexists apartfrom the narrativesthat locate it and give it meaning. -Robert Cover' INTRODUCTION In 1990, Mr. Choudhury, a British Muslim, sought to bring a private prosecution in the United Kingdom for what he regarded as blasphemous attacks on Islam in Salman Rushdie's The Satanic Verses. The Chief Metropolitan Magistrate refused, however, to issue a summons for blas- phemy against Rushdie and his publisher on the grounds that the offense could not be committed where the religion concerned is not Christianity.2 Mr. Choudhury sought review of the decision in the Queen's Bench Di- visional Court.' There, Lord Watkins confirmed that "as the law now stands it does not extend to religions other than Christianity,"A and the application was refused. Having exhausted his domestic remedies, Mr. Choudhury took his complaint to the European Commission on Human Rights where he claimed that the inability to prosecute Rushdie and his publisher in Eng- land for blasphemy violated his right to freedom of thought, conscience, and religion under Article 9 and constituted discrimination on the basis of religion under Article 14 of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR).' The nature of the complaint was not without precedent I. Robert M. Cover, The Supreme Court: 1982 Term: Foreword: Nomos and Narra- tive, 97 HARV. L. REv. 4, 4 (1983) (footnotes omitted). 2. R v. Chief Metro. Stipendiary Magistrate (Er Parte Choudhury), [1991] 1 All E.R. 306 (Q.B) at 306; see also Robert McCorquodale, Blasphemous Verses, 50 CAMBRIDGE L.J. 22 (1991). 3. Ex Parte Choudhury, [1991] 1 All E.R. 306 (Q.B) at 308. 4. Id. at 318. 5. Id. at 308-09, 318, 323 (declining to extend the common law offense of blasphe- mous libel to cover religions other than Anglicanism and, in certain respects, to Christianity as a whole). 6. Choudhury v. United Kingdom, App. No. 17439/90, 12 HUM. RTs. L.J. 172 (1991); see also Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, arts. 9, 14, Mar. 20, 1952, 213 U.N.T.S. 222 [hereinafter ECHR]. Summer 201l]1 Islam in the Secular Nomos 665 in ECHR jurisprudence. Eight years previously, the Commission had upheld the successful prosecution of a British magazine for publishing a poem found to be blasphemous to Christians partly on the basis that the "main purpose" of the English common law offense of blasphemous li- bel is "to protect the rights of citizens not to be offended in their religious feelings by publications."7 In following the reasoning of the U.K. Divisional Court,' however, the Commission determined that the British government had not interfered with Mr. Choudhury's right to freedom of religion and belief because there was no positive obligation on states under the ECHR to protect all religious sensibilities.! The fact that the English law of blasphemy extended only to the Church of Eng- land was not, accordingly, discrimination on the basis of religion.'o The Commission's decision infuriated the Islamic community in Britain." It was soon followed in 1994 by a decision of the European Court of Human Rights (the Court) upholding the Austrian government's seizure of the film Das Liebeskonzil (Council in Heaven) on the basis that it constituted an attack on the Christian religion-Roman Catholi- cism in particular-by violating "[t]he respect for the religious feelings of believers as guaranteed in Article 9 . .. by provocative portrayals of objects of religious veneration." 2 Then, in 1996, the Court upheld again a refusal by the British government to permit circulation of a film, Vi- sions of Ecstasy, on the basis that the government had the legitimate aim to "protect 'the rights of others' " and to protect "against seriously offen- sive attacks on matters regarded as sacred by Christians."" 7. Gay News Ltd. v. United Kingdom, App. No. 8710/79, 5 Eur. H.R. Rep. 123, 130, 11(1982). 8. In considering the ECHR, the Divisional Court decided that "the provisions of the Convention concerning the right to freedom of religion and to protection from discrimination on the ground of religion did not require an English law of blasphemy to protect the beliefs of Islam." McCorquodale, supra note 2, at 23; cf infra text accompanying note 282 (discussing how the Select Committee on Religious Offenses in England and Wales considered that the law of blasphemy is discriminatory). 9. R v. Chief Metro. Stipendiary Magistrate (Ex Parte Choudhury), [1991] 1 All E.R. 306 (Q.B) at 308. 10. Choudhury v. United Kingdom, App. No. 17439/90, 12 HuM. RTs. L.J. 172, 172-73 (1991); see also STEPHEN H. BAILEY, DAVID J. HARRIS & DAVID C. ORMEROD, CIVIL LIBER- TIES: CASES AND MATERIALS 1050-53 (5th ed. 2001); Paul Kearns, The Uncultured God: Blasphemy Law's Reprieve and the Art Matrix, 5 EUR. HUM. RTs. L. REv. 512, 515 (2000). 11. Javaid Rehman, Religion, Minority Rights and Muslims of the United Kingdom, in RELIGION, HUMAN RIGHTS AND INTERNATIONAL LAw: A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF MUSLIM STATE PRACTICES 521, 531-32 (Javaid Rehman & Susan C. Breau eds., 2007). 12. Otto-Preminger-Institut v. Austria, 295 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 1, 17-18 (1994). 13. Wingrove v. United Kingdom, 23 Eur. Ct. H.R. 1937, 1957 (1996); see also infra note 105 and accompanying text (discussing the Court's analysis in Otto-Preminger-Institut v. Austria, 295 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A) at 1 (1994)). 666 Michigan Journal of InternationalLaw [Vol. 32:663 As scholars have noted, these early cases in the Court's Article 9 ju- risprudence provide evidence of a disparity in the treatment of the claims of majority and minority religious groups.14 Ghandhi and James thus ob- serve: The publication in September 1988 of Salman Rushdie's book The Satanic Verses, as is very well known, caused outrage among both British and non-British Muslims. Copies of the book were burned publicly across the world. Riots on the Indian sub-continent resulted in deaths. The Ayatollah Khomeini issued his notorious fatwa, which is still in existence. Yet the Divisional Court concluded that, inter alia, the blasphemous libel of Allah (Almighty God), the prophet Ibrahim, Muhammad the Holy Prophet of Islam and the religion of Islam was not an offence known to English law.
Recommended publications
  • John Milbank and Adrian Pabst, the Politics of Virtue: Post-Liberalism and the Human Future
    Radical Orthodoxy: Theology, Philosophy, Politics, Vol. 3, Number 2 (June 2017): 42-49. ISSN 2050-392X John Milbank and Adrian Pabst, The Politics of Virtue: Post-Liberalism and the Human Future. London and New York: Rowman and Lititlefield, 2016, 24.95, pp. x & 406. The British campaign to leave the European Union, and the campaign of Donald Trump for the Presidency of the United States, channeled and legitimised vicious elements in contemporary political culture: xenophobia, pride, lying, irrationality, hate, greed, anger, and naked ambition were much to the fore in the campaigns. And they have, sadly, remained to the fore in the public conversations which have followed. Without Boris Johnson, the British ‘Leave’ campaign would likely have lost and it is widely recognised that he joined the campaign not out of anti- EU or anti-migrant conviction but from ambition to replace David Cameron—his rival since school days at Eton—as Prime Minister. Donald Trump began a low key campaign for the Republican candidacy out of wounded pride, having on a number of occasions been told by other Republicans that he was not fit for the office of the Presidency. Written in the two years prior to these campaigns, Milbank and Pabst’s historically and philosophically deep, and yet policy rich, book is prescient in its prediction of the collapse of the liberal status quo in the UK and the USA which is now evident in the populist turn of the globally ‘left behind’ against the perceived liberal cosmopolitan consensus in the Brexit and Trump victories. The core of Milbank and Pabst’s argument is that what they call ‘liberalism’— which they define through an amalgam of Hobbes’ account of the State as Leviathan restraining the war of all against all, Locke’s individualist concept of self-ownership, and Hume and Smith’s claim that economic exchanges governed by little more than the law of price turn individual vices into collective well being—is the origin of the current ‘metacrises’ of capitalism, politics, culture, and Radical Orthodoxy 3, No.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking the French Liberal Moment: Some Thoughts on the Heterogeneous Origins of Lefort and Gauchet's Social Philosophy
    CHAPTER 3 Rethinking the French Liberal Moment: Some Thoughts on the Heterogeneous Origins of Lefort and Gauchet’s Social Philosophy Noah Rosenblum ecent scholarship has taken an interest in the renaissance of French liberal thought in the second half of the twentieth century. This R“French liberal revival” has swept up scholars and commentators alike, and is often thought to include the important French philosophers Claude Lefort and Marcel Gauchet. But, as work in intellectual history has shown,1 the term sits uneasily on at least these two. On close examination, we see that some of their mature thought is only ambiguously committed to liberal goals and rests on complex philosophical premises that are incompatible with some traditional liberal arguments. Tracing aspects of their social thought back to its roots reveals how deeply opposed to liberalism some of their premises were and helps us see how they carried illiberal ideas forward into new contexts. This forces us to take a new perspective on at least this piece of the twentieth century’s French liberal moment, revising accepted stories of its origins and meaning. Recognizing the heterogeneous sources of their argument leads us to appreciate Lefort and Gauchet’s creative work of reconstruction and resist the urge to canalize their powerful social philosophy. Conceptualizing the “French Liberal Revival” In a purely analytic sense, we can understand the idea of a “French liberal revival” in two different ways. The phrase describes, first, a new or renewed interest in traditional liberal themes by thinkers writing in French. We can S. W. Sawyer et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Jean-Luc Nancy and the Deconstruction of Christianity By
    Jean-Luc Nancy and the Deconstruction of Christianity by Tenzan Eaghll A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department for the Study of Religion University of Toronto ©Copyright by Tenzan Eaghll 2016 Jean-Luc Nancy and the Deconstruction of Christianity Tenzan Eaghll Doctor of Philosophy Department for the Study of Religion University of Toronto 2016 Abstract This dissertation is a study of the origins and development of the French philosopher Jean- Luc Nancy’s work on the “deconstruction of Christianity.” By situating Nancy's work in light of the broader Continental philosophical analysis of religion in the 20th Century, it argues that what Nancy calls the "deconstruction of Christianity" and the "exit from religion" is his unique intervention into the problem of metaphysical nihilism in Western thought. The author explains that Nancy’s work on religion does not provide a new “theory” for the study of religion or Christianity, but shows how Western metaphysical foundations are caught up in a process of decomposition that has been brought about by Christianity. For Nancy, the only way out of nihilism is to think of the world as an infinite opening unto itself, for this dis- encloses any transcendent principle of value or immanent notion of meaninglessness in the finite spacing of sense, and he finds the resources to think this opening within Christianity. By reading Christian notions like "God" and "creation ex nihilo" along deconstructive lines and connecting them with the rise and fall of this civilization that once called itself "Christendom," he attempts to expose "the sense of an absenting" that is both the condition of possibility for the West and what precedes, succeeds, and exceeds it.
    [Show full text]
  • Habermas, Taylor, and Connolly on Secularism, Pluralism, and the Post-Secular Public Sphere
    Article Habermas, Taylor, and Connolly on Secularism, Pluralism, and the Post-Secular Public Sphere Spyridon Kaltsas Department of Political Science and Public Administration, National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, 106 78 Athens, Greece; [email protected] Received: 17 June 2019; Accepted: 31 July 2019; Published: 1 August 2019 Abstract: The main purpose of this paper is to explore and understand the relationships between secularism, pluralism, and the post-secular public sphere in the thought of Jürgen Habermas, Charles Taylor, and William Connolly. The three authors develop a thorough critique of secularism which implies a radical break with the dogmatic idea of removing religion from the public sphere. My main objective is to show that this critique is related to a normative understanding of our post- secular situation and requires a rethinking of the boundaries of the public sphere in relation to the predicament of pluralism. Arguing against the post-metaphysical conception of secularism, Taylor develops a critique of Habermas’s “institutional translation proviso”, and Connolly stresses the agonistic dimension of the post-secular public sphere. I take these criticisms into account, while arguing that Taylor and Connolly are unable to provide a sound basis for the legitimacy of our institutional settings. In contrast to Taylor and Connolly, I propose a reading of Habermas’s theory based on the internal relationship between universal justification and the everyday contexts of pre- political solidarity. I conclude with a focus on the need to take into account the agonistic dimension of the post-secular public sphere. Keywords: post-secular society; secularism; public sphere; pluralism; legitimation; ethics of citizenship; Jürgen Habermas; Charles Taylor; William Connolly 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Books Added to Benner Library from Estate of Dr. William Foote
    Books added to Benner Library from estate of Dr. William Foote # CALL NUMBER TITLE Scribes and scholars : a guide to the transmission of Greek and Latin literature / by L.D. Reynolds and N.G. 1 001.2 R335s, 1991 Wilson. 2 001.2 Se15e Emerson on the scholar / Merton M. Sealts, Jr. 3 001.3 R921f Future without a past : the humanities in a technological society / John Paul Russo. 4 001.30711 G163a Academic instincts / Marjorie Garber. Book of the book : some works & projections about the book & writing / edited by Jerome Rothenberg and 5 002 B644r Steven Clay. 6 002 OL5s Smithsonian book of books / Michael Olmert. 7 002 T361g Great books and book collectors / Alan G. Thomas. 8 002.075 B29g Gentle madness : bibliophiles, bibliomanes, and the eternal passion for books / Nicholas A. Basbanes. 9 002.09 B29p Patience & fortitude : a roving chronicle of book people, book places, and book culture / Nicholas A. Basbanes. Books of the brave : being an account of books and of men in the Spanish Conquest and settlement of the 10 002.098 L552b sixteenth-century New World / Irving A. Leonard ; with a new introduction by Rolena Adorno. 11 020.973 R824f Foundations of library and information science / Richard E. Rubin. 12 021.009 J631h, 1976 History of libraries in the Western World / by Elmer D. Johnson and Michael H. Harris. 13 025.2832 B175d Double fold : libraries and the assault on paper / Nicholson Baker. London booksellers and American customers : transatlantic literary community and the Charleston Library 14 027.2 R196L Society, 1748-1811 / James Raven.
    [Show full text]
  • Catholic Social Thought, Political Liberalism and the Idea of Human Rights
    Journal of Christian legal Thought fall 2011 Catholic Social Thought, Political Liberalism and the Idea of Human Rights By Zachary R. Calo, Valparaiso University School of Law I. The Morality of Human Rights own assumptions, methods, and anthropology. The Human rights is the dominant moral category plurality that resides within the liberal human rights of modernity. As both a theoretical concept and tradition, particularly that located on the boundary the basis of legal norms, human rights shapes the of secularism and religion, is a necessary backdrop way we think and talk about personhood, social to engaging emerging debates about such significant justice, and political obligation. Yet, it is also the topics as religious pluralism and religious law. It case that there is no one account of human rights, also must shape our reflections on foundational but rather competing traditions of human rights questions about the limits and possibilities of human that strive for primacy. Human rights, in short, is a rights law.1 deeply contested category through which different This paper does not engage these broader moral visions aim to shape institutions and policies. contested issues but rather considers the background In spite of the label, human rights claims are not question of how religious traditions, in this case the universal either methodologically or substantively. social thought of the Catholic church, has engaged Rather, under the umbrella of human rights is the idea of human rights and the liberal tradition located a constant struggle between the universal more generally. In particular, this case study aims and the particular. How this tension unfolds, and to illuminate the process by which Catholicism whether it does so in a constructive or disruptive developed a native human rights tradition and manner, is one of the foundational questions that how, in turn, this tradition is distinguished from must be engaged in coming years.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparison of Constitutionalism in France and the United States, A
    A COMPARISON OF CONSTITUTIONALISM IN FRANCE AND THE UNITED STATES Martin A. Rogoff I. INTRODUCTION ....................................... 22 If. AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM ..................... 30 A. American constitutionalism defined and described ......................................... 31 B. The Constitution as a "canonical" text ............ 33 C. The Constitution as "codification" of formative American ideals .................................. 34 D. The Constitution and national solidarity .......... 36 E. The Constitution as a voluntary social compact ... 40 F. The Constitution as an operative document ....... 42 G. The federal judiciary:guardians of the Constitution ...................................... 43 H. The legal profession and the Constitution ......... 44 I. Legal education in the United States .............. 45 III. THE CONsTrrTION IN FRANCE ...................... 46 A. French constitutional thought ..................... 46 B. The Constitution as a "contested" document ...... 60 C. The Constitution and fundamental values ......... 64 D. The Constitution and nationalsolidarity .......... 68 E. The Constitution in practice ...................... 72 1. The Conseil constitutionnel ................... 73 2. The Conseil d'ttat ........................... 75 3. The Cour de Cassation ....................... 77 F. The French judiciary ............................. 78 G. The French bar................................... 81 H. Legal education in France ........................ 81 IV. CONCLUSION ........................................
    [Show full text]
  • Nomos </Em> of the European Court of Human Rights
    University of Maryland Francis King Carey School of Law DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law Faculty Scholarship Francis King Carey School of Law Faculty 2011 Islam in the Secular Nomos of the European Court of Human Rights Peter G. Danchin University of Maryland School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/fac_pubs Part of the Human Rights Law Commons, and the International Law Commons Digital Commons Citation 32 Michigan Journal of International Law 663 (2011). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Francis King Carey School of Law Faculty at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DANCHIN FTP 1_C.DOC 7/8/2011 9:24:23 AM ISLAM IN THE SECULAR NOMOS OF THE EUROPEAN COURT OF HUMAN RIGHTS Peter G. Danchin* Introduction...................................................................................... 664 I. The Concept of the Secular Public Sphere.................... 673 A. The Antinomies of Secularism ........................................... 674 1. The Right to Freedom of Religion and Belief ............ 675 2. Public Reason and Private Faith ................................. 682 3. The Authority of Public Reason.................................. 683 B. Rethinking the Secular ...................................................... 685 C. Between Rationality and Reason....................................... 690 II. Religious Freedom in ECHR Jurisprudence ..................... 692 A. The Rights of Religious Minorities.................................... 692 B. Freedom from Injury to Religious Feelings ....................... 693 C. The Claims of Muslim Communities ................................. 696 III. Islam in Article 9 Jurisprudence....................................... 705 A. The Scope of the Right to Religious Freedom.................... 707 1.
    [Show full text]
  • DEMOCRACY AS SOCIO- CULTURAL PROJECT of INDIVIDUAL and COLLECTIVE SOVEREIGNTY Claude Lefort, Marcel Gauchet and the French Debate on Modern Autonomy
    DEMOCRACY AS SOCIO- CULTURAL PROJECT OF INDIVIDUAL AND COLLECTIVE SOVEREIGNTY Claude Lefort, Marcel Gauchet and the French Debate on Modern Autonomy Natalie Doyle ABSTRACT French political philosophy has experienced a renewal over the last twenty years. One of its leading projects is Marcel Gauchet’s reflection on democracy and religion. This project situates itself within the context of the French debate on modernity and autonomy launched by the work of Cornelius Castoriadis. Gauchet’s work makes a significant contribution to this debate by building on the pioneering work of Lefort on the political self-instituting capacity of modern societies and the associated shift from religion to ideology. It thus explores the centrality of the notion of sovereignty in the advent of liberal democracy and conducts this reflection within an overall discussion of the role played by Christianity in the genesis of European modernity. It elaborates an anthropology of modernity which explores the relationship between indi- vidualism and democracy and redefines modernity as a project of sovereignty which aims at creating a radically new society, the society of individuals. KEYWORDS democracy • individualism • modernity • religion • sovereignty French political philosophy has experienced a renewal over the last twenty years. One of its most significant projects has been Marcel Gauchet’s reflection on democracy, grounded in an original social theory. Although Thesis Eleven, Number 75, November 2003: 69–95 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) Copyright © 2003 SAGE Publications and Thesis Eleven Co-op Ltd [0725-5136(200311)75;69–95;037127] 70 Thesis Eleven (Number 75 2003) already foreshadowed in his major work Le Désenchantement du monde: Une histoire politique de la religion, this social theory only revealed its full political significance in Gauchet’s historical research on the French Revolution in La Révolution des droits de l’homme et La Révolution des pouvoirs.
    [Show full text]
  • Tocqueville Chapter Craiutu and Holbreich FINAL (February 7, 2015)
    1 To be published in Combining the Spirit of Religion and the Spirit of Liberty: Tocqueville’s Thesis Revisited, ed. Michael Zuckert (University of Chicago Press, 2015) Aurelian Craiutu and Matthew N. Holbreich On Faith and Democracy as a New Form of Religion: A Few Tocquevillian Reflections1 “Faith in common opinion will become a sort of religion whose prophet will be the majority” ~ Tocqueville I. A problem of liberal modernity? Three decades ago, in his influential book After Virtue (1981), Alasdair MacIntyre advanced one of the most trenchant arguments against liberalism that has elicited a wide array of responses and heated debates. The values of economic and political liberalism, he argued, are based on (what he called) an emotivist and relativist culture which uncritically celebrates the total autonomy of the individual will and slowly leads to the gradual but inevitable decomposition of the social fabric. The main culprit, in MacIntyre’s view, is liberal individualism, the dominant doctrine of the last three centuries that shapes our norms and beliefs and has had a strong influence upon our social institutions and values. As society becomes atomized, so the story goes, it eventually turns into a mere “collection of citizens of nowhere,”2 detached from each other and pursuing interests that are often at odds with the common good. “The barbarians are not waiting beyond the frontiers,” MacIntyre warned his readers, “they have already been governing us for quite some time and it is our lack of consciousness of this that constitutes part of our predicament.”3 2 MacIntyre’s critique of liberal modernity still resonates today and the debate seems unlikely to be settled anytime soon.
    [Show full text]
  • Faith, Reason, and Liberal Legal Neutrality
    Tulsa Law Review Volume 53 Issue 2 Article 28 Winter 2018 Faith, Reason, and Liberal Legal Neutrality Jason E. Whitehead [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.utulsa.edu/tlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Jason E. Whitehead, Faith, Reason, and Liberal Legal Neutrality, 53 Tulsa L. Rev. 375 (2018). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.utulsa.edu/tlr/vol53/iss2/28 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by TU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Tulsa Law Review by an authorized editor of TU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Whitehead: Faith, Reason, and Liberal Legal Neutrality WHITEHEAD, BOOK REVIEW_FINAL (375) (CORRECTED2) (DO NOT DELETE) 3/8/2018 10:01 AM FAITH, REASON, AND LIBERAL LEGAL NEUTRALITY Jason E. Whitehead* FRANCIS J. BECKWITH, TAKING RITES SERIOUSLY: LAW, POLITICS, AND THE REASONABLENESS OF FAITH (CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS 2015). PP. 225. HARDCOVER $99.99. RELIGION, SECULARISM, AND CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRACY (JEAN L. COHEN & CÉCILE LABORDE EDS.) (COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS 2015). PP. 456. HARDCOVER $120.00. INTRODUCTION: THE CONTINUING “WARS OF RELIGION” Nearly 370 years after the Peace of Westphalia, the conflict between religious faith and modern political sovereignty continues to rage. Whether the issue is the right of religious citizens to exempt themselves from generally applicable public laws or the legitimacy of public laws motivated by religious values, Western
    [Show full text]
  • Dworkin's Freedom of Religion Without
    DWORKIN’S FREEDOM OF RELIGION WITHOUT GOD CÉCILE LABORDE∗ INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................. 1255 I. DWORKIN ON RELIGION AND LIBERAL NEUTRALITY ........................ 1258 A. Freedom of Religion Is a General Right, Not a Special Right .......................................................................................... 1258 B. Neutral Justification as a Way to “Generalize Nonestablishment” .................................................................... 1260 C. Substantive Liberal Policies Are Mandated by Neutral Justification ............................................................................... 1261 II. A CRITIQUE OF DWORKIN ................................................................. 1261 A. Freedom of Religion Can Generate Special Rights on Dworkin’s Own Theory ............................................................. 1262 B. Nonestablishment Cannot Be Easily Generalized ..................... 1264 C. Liberal Neutrality Is Not Sufficiently Conclusive to Justify Substantive Liberal Policies ...................................................... 1269 CONCLUSION ................................................................................................. 1271 INTRODUCTION There is a common view among critics of secular liberalism that liberal neutrality – for all its claims to be neutral towards religion – is itself a religion, albeit one without God. This common view, however, begs the central question: What do we mean by a “religion”
    [Show full text]