A Universal Turing Machine 1 Conventions and Preliminaries

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Universal Turing Machine 1 Conventions and Preliminaries A Universal Turing Machine 1 Conventions and Preliminaries A Turing machine consists of an in¯nitely long tape divided into individual cells, a movable \head" to read and write characters on the cells, and a pro- gram that dictates how the head should react to the machine's potential tape con¯gurations. By convention, the leftmost cell on the tape always contains the special symbol B, which marks the edge of the tape. The remaining tape extends in¯nitely to the right, with each successive cell containing exactly one symbol from the ¯nite alphabet A = fB; a1; a2; : : : ; an; tg, where t is called a blank square. The Turing machine program invokes a ¯nite collection of Turing states Q = fq0; q1; : : : ; qk; qhg, where qh denotes the distinguished halting state. In each step of a computation, the Turing machine reads the symbol underneath its head, writes a symbol in the current cell, changes to a new Turing state, and ¯nally moves the head one cell to the left, right, or remains neutral. The details of this computation process are determined by the program. The input for the Turing machine is represented by the prepared initial pattern on the tape, and the output of the machine is given by the existing symbols on the tape when the machine reaches the halting state qh. We will assume that the input for any Turing machine is always ¯nite in the sense that to the right of some cell in the initial pattern, there will be an in¯nite string of blank cells. The output of the Turing machine may be interpreted in any way we like; we will not use the convention that the output consists only of those symbols residing to the left of the ¯rst blank. Ultimately, we will ¯nd this flexibility convenient when we both input and ¯nally read o® the output from our universal Turing machine. In addition to terminating upon reaching the halting state qh, a Turing machine will also halt if either the procedure for the current state and symbol pair (qi; aj) is not de¯ned in the program, or if the head falls o® the left end of the tape. We designate either of the last two cases to be an error, and we may consider the resulting output to be rubbish. It is also possible that the Turing program may not halt at all. By convention, we will assume that the Turing machine begins in the initial state q0, with the machine head covering the leftmost square, B. 1 Universal Turing Machine Jason Teutsch Formally, a program consists of a collection of transition functions (Q n fqhg) £ A 7! (Q n fq0g) £ A £ fL; N; Rg; where the codomain tells the Turing machine which state to change to, which symbol to write, and whether to move left, right, or neither (L, R, or N) when the machine head encounters a symbol while in a given state. We may thus think of a program as a collection of quintuples of the above form. By convention, the ¯rst line of the program describes what to do with initial state q0 and symbol B. A Turing program is best illustrated with an example. Consider the following program, which inputs a nonempty string without blanks from the alphabet A = ft; 1; 2; 3; Bg. This program outputs that same string with all of the 1's replaced with 2's, and changes the rightmost cell to a \3": hq0; Bi 7! hq0; B;Ri hq0; 1i 7! hq0; 2;Ri hq0; 2i 7! hq0; 2;Ri hq0; 3i 7! hq0; 3;Ri hq0; ti 7! hq1; t;Li hq1; 1i 7! hqh; 3;Ni hq1; 2i 7! hqh; 3;Ni hq1; 3i 7! hqh; 3;Ni Proposition 1.1 Each Turing machine can be encoded by a distinct, ¯nite string of 1's and 0's. Proof: Let M be a Turing machine with alphabet A = fa1; : : : ; ang, Turing states Q = fq0; q1; : : : ; qk; qhg, and individual program line quintuples ¢ = f±1; : : : ; ±rg. De¯ne the unary representation of a natural number n to be the length-n string of 1's, 11| {z::: 1}. We assign a distinct unary representation n to every symbol from the alphabet, including the auxiliary symbols t and B, as follows: t is 1, a1 is 11, a2 is 111, . 2 Universal Turing Machine Jason Teutsch an is| 1 :::{z 1}, and n+1 B is 1| :::{z 1} : n+2 Similarly, we can ¯nd a unary representation for each element in Q: q0 is 1, q1 is 11, . qn is 1| :::{z 1}, and n+1 qh is 1| :::{z 1}. n+2 We will code the direction symbols L, N, and R by 1, 11, and 111, respec- tively. We can thus represent any program line quintuple as a string of 1's and 0's by attaching the unary representation of each element in the ordered tuplet end-to-end, with a 0 to mark the separation between each element in the series. Finally, we can represent the entire series of program lines ¢ as a string of 1's and 0's by writing 00 as a separator between each quintuplet of the Turing program. The Turing machine from the example above thus corresponds to the following sequence of 1's and 0's: 1011111010111110111001011010111011100101110101110111001011110101111011100 101011010100110110111011110110011011101110111101100110111101110111101100. The sequence of 0's and 1's corresponding to a particular Turing machine is called the Turing number of that machine.¥ Corollary 1.2 There are countably many Turing machines. Proof: There are only countably many ¯nite strings of 0's and 1's.¥ 2 Tools We will need to code a few subroutines for use in the construction of our universal Turing machine. 3 Universal Turing Machine Jason Teutsch Lemma 2.1 (copying machine) Let X and Y be symbols on a tape, with X lying to the left of Y and only blanks and 1's written on the cells in between. Assume that the head of the Turing machine is initially covering the cell containing X. Then there is a Turing program that counts the number of contiguous 1's sitting to the immediate right of Y and pastes that same number of 1's to the right of X. We will assume that we start with su±cient blank cells to the right of X to contain the intended string of 1's. This copying process may also be implemented in the reverse direction, from X to Y . Proof: Let X and Y be as above, and let B be a symbol in the alphabet that is distinct from X, Y , t, and 1. The symbol B will be used to keep track of how many cells have been copied. The symbols X and Y will remain stationary throughout this construction. That is, X and Y will be neither written nor erased. The algorithm is as follows: Step 1: Move to the right and stop at the ¯rst 1. Mark this cell with a B. (If no \1" is found, that is, we reach either Y or a blank cell, go to Step 4.) Step 2: Move to the right and stop at the ¯rst blank cell beyond Y . Write a 1 in this cell. Step 3: Move back to the left until the ¯rst B is encountered, then go to Step 1. Step 4: Move to the left, changing B's into 1's until the symbol X is reached, at which point halt. The following time diagram illustrates a sample copy process. Lines (a){ (d) in the sequence shows the tape status at the beginning of Step 1, and the underlined character indicates the position of the the tape head at that moment: (a) 1 X 1 1 1 t 1 1 Y t t t t 1 (b) 1 XB 1 1 t 1 1 Y 1 t t t 1 (c) 1 XBB 1 t 1 1 Y 1 1 t t 1 (d) 1 XBBB t 1 1 Y 1 1 1 t 1 (e) 1 X 1 1 1 t 1 1 Y 1 1 1 t 1 The steps in this process suggest formal program lines for our Turing machine: 4 Universal Turing Machine Jason Teutsch hq0;Xi 7! hq0; X; Ri hq0; 1i 7! hq1; B; Ri hq0; ti 7! hq4; t;Li hq0;Y i 7! hq4; Y; Li hq0;Bi 7! hq0; B; Ri hq1; 1i 7! hq1; 1;Ri hq1; ti 7! hq1; t;Ri hq1;Y i 7! hq2; Y; Ri hq2; 1i 7! hq2; 1;Ri hq2; ti 7! hq3; 1;Li hq3; 1i 7! hq3; 1;Li hq3;Y i 7! hq3; Y; Li hq3;Bi 7! hq0; B; Ni hq4;Xi 7! hqh; X; Ni hq4;Bi 7! hq4; 1;Li ¥ Lemma 2.2 (matching machine) Let X and Y be symbols on a tape, with X lying to the left of Y and only blanks and 1's written on the cells in between. Assume that the head of the Turing machine is initially covering the cell containing X. Then there is a Turing program that compares the number of contiguous 1's sitting to the right of X to the number of contiguous 1's sitting to the right of Y . If these two quantities are the same, then the program terminates in one state. If they are di®erent, then it terminates in another. Proof: Let X and Y be as above, and, as in Lemma 2.1, let B be a symbol in the alphabet that is distinct from X, Y , t, and 1.
Recommended publications
  • CS 154 NOTES Part 1. Finite Automata
    CS 154 NOTES ARUN DEBRAY MARCH 13, 2014 These notes were taken in Stanford’s CS 154 class in Winter 2014, taught by Ryan Williams. I live-TEXed them using vim, and as such there may be typos; please send questions, comments, complaints, and corrections to [email protected]. Thanks to Rebecca Wang for catching a few errors. CONTENTS Part 1. Finite Automata: Very Simple Models 1 1. Deterministic Finite Automata: 1/7/141 2. Nondeterminism, Finite Automata, and Regular Expressions: 1/9/144 3. Finite Automata vs. Regular Expressions, Non-Regular Languages: 1/14/147 4. Minimizing DFAs: 1/16/14 9 5. The Myhill-Nerode Theorem and Streaming Algorithms: 1/21/14 11 6. Streaming Algorithms: 1/23/14 13 Part 2. Computability Theory: Very Powerful Models 15 7. Turing Machines: 1/28/14 15 8. Recognizability, Decidability, and Reductions: 1/30/14 18 9. Reductions, Undecidability, and the Post Correspondence Problem: 2/4/14 21 10. Oracles, Rice’s Theorem, the Recursion Theorem, and the Fixed-Point Theorem: 2/6/14 23 11. Self-Reference and the Foundations of Mathematics: 2/11/14 26 12. A Universal Theory of Data Compression: Kolmogorov Complexity: 2/18/14 28 Part 3. Complexity Theory: The Modern Models 31 13. Time Complexity: 2/20/14 31 14. More on P versus NP and the Cook-Levin Theorem: 2/25/14 33 15. NP-Complete Problems: 2/27/14 36 16. NP-Complete Problems, Part II: 3/4/14 38 17. Polytime and Oracles, Space Complexity: 3/6/14 41 18.
    [Show full text]
  • Computability and Incompleteness Fact Sheets
    Computability and Incompleteness Fact Sheets Computability Definition. A Turing machine is given by: A finite set of symbols, s1; : : : ; sm (including a \blank" symbol) • A finite set of states, q1; : : : ; qn (including a special \start" state) • A finite set of instructions, each of the form • If in state qi scanning symbol sj, perform act A and go to state qk where A is either \move right," \move left," or \write symbol sl." The notion of a \computation" of a Turing machine can be described in terms of the data above. From now on, when I write \let f be a function from strings to strings," I mean that there is a finite set of symbols Σ such that f is a function from strings of symbols in Σ to strings of symbols in Σ. I will also adopt the analogous convention for sets. Definition. Let f be a function from strings to strings. Then f is computable (or recursive) if there is a Turing machine M that works as follows: when M is started with its input head at the beginning of the string x (on an otherwise blank tape), it eventually halts with its head at the beginning of the string f(x). Definition. Let S be a set of strings. Then S is computable (or decidable, or recursive) if there is a Turing machine M that works as follows: when M is started with its input head at the beginning of the string x, then if x is in S, then M eventually halts, with its head on a special \yes" • symbol; and if x is not in S, then M eventually halts, with its head on a special • \no" symbol.
    [Show full text]
  • COMPSCI 501: Formal Language Theory Insights on Computability Turing Machines Are a Model of Computation Two (No Longer) Surpris
    Insights on Computability Turing machines are a model of computation COMPSCI 501: Formal Language Theory Lecture 11: Turing Machines Two (no longer) surprising facts: Marius Minea Although simple, can describe everything [email protected] a (real) computer can do. University of Massachusetts Amherst Although computers are powerful, not everything is computable! Plus: “play” / program with Turing machines! 13 February 2019 Why should we formally define computation? Must indeed an algorithm exist? Back to 1900: David Hilbert’s 23 open problems Increasingly a realization that sometimes this may not be the case. Tenth problem: “Occasionally it happens that we seek the solution under insufficient Given a Diophantine equation with any number of un- hypotheses or in an incorrect sense, and for this reason do not succeed. known quantities and with rational integral numerical The problem then arises: to show the impossibility of the solution under coefficients: To devise a process according to which the given hypotheses or in the sense contemplated.” it can be determined in a finite number of operations Hilbert, 1900 whether the equation is solvable in rational integers. This asks, in effect, for an algorithm. Hilbert’s Entscheidungsproblem (1928): Is there an algorithm that And “to devise” suggests there should be one. decides whether a statement in first-order logic is valid? Church and Turing A Turing machine, informally Church and Turing both showed in 1936 that a solution to the Entscheidungsproblem is impossible for the theory of arithmetic. control To make and prove such a statement, one needs to define computability. In a recent paper Alonzo Church has introduced an idea of “effective calculability”, read/write head which is equivalent to my “computability”, but is very differently defined.
    [Show full text]
  • Computability Theory
    CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook and T. Pitassi) Fall, 2019 Computability Theory This section is partly inspired by the material in \A Course in Mathematical Logic" by Bell and Machover, Chap 6, sections 1-10. Other references: \Introduction to the theory of computation" by Michael Sipser, and \Com- putability, Complexity, and Languages" by M. Davis and E. Weyuker. Our first goal is to give a formal definition for what it means for a function on N to be com- putable by an algorithm. Historically the first convincing such definition was given by Alan Turing in 1936, in his paper which introduced what we now call Turing machines. Slightly before Turing, Alonzo Church gave a definition based on his lambda calculus. About the same time G¨odel,Herbrand, and Kleene developed definitions based on recursion schemes. Fortunately all of these definitions are equivalent, and each of many other definitions pro- posed later are also equivalent to Turing's definition. This has lead to the general belief that these definitions have got it right, and this assertion is roughly what we now call \Church's Thesis". A natural definition of computable function f on N allows for the possibility that f(x) may not be defined for all x 2 N, because algorithms do not always halt. Thus we will use the symbol 1 to mean “undefined". Definition: A partial function is a function n f :(N [ f1g) ! N [ f1g; n ≥ 0 such that f(c1; :::; cn) = 1 if some ci = 1. In the context of computability theory, whenever we refer to a function on N, we mean a partial function in the above sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Models of Computation
    MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 6.004 Computation Structures Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. Models of computation Problem 1. In lecture, we saw an enumeration of FSMs having the property that every FSM that can be built is equivalent to some FSM in that enumeration. A. We didn't deal with FSMs having different numbers of inputs and outputs. Where will we find a 5-input, 3-output FSM in our enumeration? We find a 5-input, 5-output FSM and don't use the extra outputs. B. Can we also enumerate finite combinational logic functions? If so, describe such an enumeration; if not, explain your reasoning. Yes. One approach is to enumerate ROMs, in much the same way as we did for the logic in our FSMs. For single-output functions, we can enumerate 1-input truth tables, 2-input truth tables, etc. This can clearly be extended to multiple outputs, as was done in lecture. An alternative approach is to enumerate (say) all possible acyclic circuits using 2-input NAND gates. C. Why do 6-3s think they own this enumeration trick? Can we come up with a scheme for enumerating functions of continuous variables, e.g. an enumeration that will include things like sin(x), op amps, etc? No. The thing that makes enumeration work is the finite number of combination functions there are for each number of inputs. There are only 16 2-input combinational functions; but there are infinitely many continuous 2-input functions.
    [Show full text]
  • Turing Machines and Separation Logic (Work in Progress)
    Turing Machines and Separation Logic (Work in Progress) Jian Xu Xingyuan Zhang PLA University of Science and Technology Christian Urban King's College London Imperial College, 24 November 2013 -- p. 1/26 Why Turing Machines? we wanted to formalise computability theory at the beginning, it was just a student project Computability and Logic (5th. ed) Boolos, Burgess and Jeffrey found an inconsistency in the definition of halting computations (Chap. 3 vs Chap. 8) Imperial College, 24 November 2013 -- p. 2/26 Why Turing Machines? we wanted to formalise computability theory atTMs the beginning, are a fantastic it was model just a of student low-level project code completely unstructured Spaghetti Code good testbed for verification techniques . Can we verify a program with 38 Mio instructions? we can delayComputability implementing and Logic a (5th.concrete ed) machine model (for OS/low-levelBoolos, Burgess code and Jeffrey verification) found an inconsistency in the definition of halting computations (Chap. 3 vs Chap. 8) Imperial College, 24 November 2013 -- p. 2/26 Why Turing Machines? we wanted to formalise computability theory atTMs the beginning, are a fantastic it was model just a of student low-level project code completely unstructured Spaghetti Code good testbed for verification techniques . Can we verify a program with 38 Mio instructions? we can delayComputability implementing and Logic a (5th.concrete ed) machine model (for OS/low-levelBoolos, Burgess code and Jeffrey verification) found an inconsistency in the definition of halting computations
    [Show full text]
  • Alan Turing and the Unsolvable Problem [8Pt] to Halt Or Not to Halt
    Alan Turing and the Unsolvable Problem To Halt or Not to Halt|That Is the Question Cristian S. Calude 26 April 2012 Alan Turing Alan Mathison Turing was born in a nursing home in Paddington, London, now the Colonnade Town House on 23 June 1912, less than three months after the sinking of the Titanic. He was to become, like Freud, who stayed briefly in the House in 1938, an explorer of the mind. But his life would not make him as famous as Freud, at least for a while. Sherborne School Turing started at Sherborne School, a classic English \public school" in the town of Sherborne, Dorset, in south-west England. Sherborne was a boys boarding school and isolation from family had a life-long affect. With very bad reports he was nearly stopped from taking the School Certificate. Reports English: I can forgive his writing, though it is the worst I have ever seen, and I try to view tolerantly his unswerving inexactitude and slipshod, dirty, work, inconsistent though such inexactitude is in a utilitarian; but I cannot forgive the stupidity of his attitude towards sane discussion on the New Testament. Bottom of the class. Maths and science: His work is dirty. Maths and science In spite of the difficult start, in 1928 he was admitted to enter the sixth form of Sherborne School to study mathematics and science. He read mathematics as an undergraduate stu- dent at King's College, Cambridge, 1931{1934. He read J. von Neumann (quantum physics) and B. Russell (logic). He was elected fellow of King's College, 1935.
    [Show full text]
  • Fsms and Turing Machines
    Designing Sequential Logic Sequential logic is used when the solution to some design problem involves a sequence of steps: How to open digital combination lock w/ 3 buttons (“start”, “0” and “1”): Step 1: press “start” button Step 2: press “0” button Information Step 3: press “1” button remembered between Step 4: press “1” button steps is called state. Step 5: press “0” button Might be just what step we’re on, or might include results from earlier steps we’ll need to complete a later step. 11/1/2017 Comp 411 - Fall 2017 1 Implementing a “State Machine” Current State “start” “1” “0” Next State unlock --- 1 --- --- start 0 000 This flavor of “truth-table” is start 000 0 0 1 digit1 0 001 called a start 000 0 1 0 error 0 101 “state-transition start 000 0 0 0 start 0 000 table” digit1 001 0 1 0 digit2 0 010 digit1 001 0 0 1 error 0 101 digit1 001 0 0 0 digit1 0 001 digit2 010 0 1 0 digit3 0 011 This is starting to look like a … PROGRAM digit3 011 0 0 1 unlock 0 100 … unlock 100 0 1 0 error 1 101 unlock 100 0 0 1 error 1 101 unlock 100 0 0 0 unlock 1 100 error 101 0 --- --- error 0 101 6 different states → encode using 3 bits 11/1/2017 Comp 411 - Fall 2017 2 Now, We Do It With Hardware! 6 inputs →26 locations each location supplies 4 bits “start” button “0” button unlock “1” button ROM 64x4 Current state Next state 3 3 Q D Trigger update periodically (“clock”) 11/1/2017 Comp 411 - Fall 2017 3 Abstraction du jour: A Finite State Machine m n Clocked FSM A Finite State Machine has: ● k States S1, S2, … Sk (one is the “initial” state) ● m inputs I1, I2, … Im ● n outputs O1, O2, … On ● Transition Rules, S’(Si,I1, I2, … Im) for each state and input combination ● Output Rules, O(Si) for each state 11/1/2017 Comp 411 - Fall 2017 4 Discrete State, Discrete Time While a ROM is shown here in the feedback path any form of combinational logic inputs outputs can be used to construct a state machine.
    [Show full text]
  • Turing Machines 1
    CS1010: Theory of Computation Lecture 8: Turning Machines Lorenzo De Stefani Fall 2020 Outline • What are Turing Machines • Turing Machine Scheme • Formal Definition • Languages of a TM • Decidability From Sipser Chapter 3.1 Theory of Computation - Fall'20 10/8/20 1 Lorenzo De Stefani FA, PDA and Turing Machines • Finite Automata: – Models for devices with finite memory • Pushdown Automata: – Models for devices with unlimited memory (stack) that is accessible only in Last-In-First-Out order • Turing Machines (Turing 1936) – Uses unlimited memory as an infinite tape which can be read/written and moved to left or right – Only model thus far that can model general purpose computers – Church-Turing thesis – Still, TM cannot solve all problems Theory of Computation - Fall'20 10/8/20 2 Lorenzo De Stefani Turing Machine Scheme Control Head Tape – a b a b – – – … Turing machines include an infinite tape – Tape uses its own alphabet Γ, with ⌃<latexit sha1_base64="(null)">(null)</latexit> Γ – Initially contains the input string and blanks⇢ everywhere else – Machine can read and write from tape and move left and right after each action – Much more powerful than FIFO stack of PDAs Theory of Computation - Fall'20 10/8/20 3 Lorenzo De Stefani Turing Machine Scheme Control a b a b – – – … The control operates as a state machine – Starts in an initial state – Proceeds in a series of transitions triggered by the symbols on the tape (one at a time) – The machine continues until it enters an accept or reject state at which point it immediately halts and
    [Show full text]
  • Turing Machines: an Introduction
    CIT 596 – Theory of Computation 1 Turing Machines: An Introduction We have seen several abstract models of computing devices: Deterministic Finite Automata, Nondeterministic Finite Automata, Non- deterministic Finite Automata with ²-Transitions, Pushdown Automata, and Deterministic Pushdown Automata. However, none of the above “seem to be” as powerful as a real com- puter, right? We now turn our attention to a much more powerful abstract model of a computing device: a Turing machine. This model is believed to do everything that a real computer can do. °c Marcelo Siqueira — Spring 2005 CIT 596 – Theory of Computation 2 Turing Machines: An Introduction A Turing machine is somewhat similar to a finite automaton, but there are important differences: 1. A Turing machine can both write on the tape and read from it. 2. The read-write head can move both to the left and to the right. 3. The tape is infinite. 4. The special states for rejecting and accepting take immediate effect. °c Marcelo Siqueira — Spring 2005 CIT 596 – Theory of Computation 3 Turing Machines: An Introduction Formally, a Turing machine is a 7-tuple, (Q, Σ, Γ, δ, q0, qaccept, qreject), where Q is the (finite) set of states, Σ is the input alphabet such that Σ does not contain the special blank symbol t, Γ is the tape alphabet such that t∈ Γ and Σ ⊆ Γ, δ : Q × Γ → Q × Γ ×{L, R} is the transition function, q0 ∈ Q is the start state, qaccept ∈ Q is the accept state, and qreject ∈ Q is the reject state, where qaccept 6= qreject.
    [Show full text]
  • Finite Automata
    Finite Automata CS 2800: Discrete Structures, Spring 2015 Sid Chaudhuri A simplified model String Machine String A simplified model String Machine String Finite sequence of letters from an alphabet Σ, e.g. {0, 1} A general-purpose computer String #uring String Machine A general-purpose computer We might revisit these later String #uring String Machine A general-purpose computer String #uring String Machine Church$#uring #hesis: An% “effecti(e/mechanical/real-*orld” calculation can be carried out on a #uring machine Alan #uring, 1-12 – 1-5/ A simple &computer” Deterministic Finite String 2es/3o Automaton 0DFA1 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 05inary input) An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6nput: 01001 7utput: 2es8 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 6n general, on what binary strings does this DFA return 2es9 An example 1 0 2es 3o 0 1 Ans: All strings with an e(en number of 1's Deterministic Finite Automaton ● A DFA is a 5-tuple M = (Q, Σ, δ, q0, F) Deterministic Finite Automaton ● A DFA is a 5-tuple M = (Q, Σ, δ, q0, F) – Q is a finite set ofstates 2es 3o Deterministic Finite Automaton ● A DFA is a 5-tuple M = (Q, Σ, δ, q0, F) – Q is a finite set ofstates – Σ is a finite input alphabet (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Turing Machines Part Two
    Turing Machines Part Two Recap from Last Time Our First Turing Machine qacc ☐ → ☐, R a → ☐, R start q0 q1 a → ☐, R ☐ → ☐, R ThisThis is is the the Turing Turing machine’s machine’s finite state control. It issues finite state control. It issues qrej commandscommands that that drive drive the the operationoperation of of the the machine. machine. Our First Turing Machine qacc ☐ → ☐, R a → ☐, R start q0 q1 a → ☐, R ☐ → ☐, R ThisThis is is the the TM’s TM’s infinite infinite tape tape. Each tape cell holds a tape Each tape cell holds a tape qrej symbolsymbol. .Initially, Initially, all all (infinitely (infinitely many)many) tape tape symbols symbols are are blank. blank. … … Our First Turing Machine qacc ☐ → ☐, R a → ☐, R start q0 q1 a → ☐, R TheThe machine machine is is started started with with the the ☐ → ☐, R inputinput string string written written somewhere somewhere onon the the tape. tape. The The tape tape head head initially points to the first symbol initially points to the first symbol qrej ofof the the input input string. string. … a a a a … Our First Turing Machine qacc ☐ → ☐, R a → ☐, R start q0 q1 a → ☐, R ☐ → ☐, R LikeLike DFAs DFAs and and NFAs,NFAs, TMs TMs begin begin executionexecution in in their their q startstart state state. rej … a a a a … Our First Turing Machine qacc ☐ → ☐, R a → ☐, R start q0 q1 a → ☐, R ☐ → ☐, R AtAt each each step, step, the the TMTM only only looks looks at at thethe symbol symbol q immediatelyimmediately under under rej thethe tape tape head head.
    [Show full text]