Heidegger, Correspondence Truth and the Realist Theology of Thomas Forsyth Torrance John D

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Heidegger, Correspondence Truth and the Realist Theology of Thomas Forsyth Torrance John D Liberty University DigitalCommons@Liberty University Liberty Baptist Theological Seminary and Graduate Faculty Publications and Presentations School 4-1997 Heidegger, Correspondence Truth and the Realist Theology of Thomas Forsyth Torrance John D. Morrison Liberty University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/lts_fac_pubs Recommended Citation Morrison, John D., "Heidegger, Correspondence Truth and the Realist Theology of Thomas Forsyth Torrance" (1997). Faculty Publications and Presentations. Paper 100. http://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/lts_fac_pubs/100 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Liberty Baptist Theological Seminary and Graduate School at DigitalCommons@Liberty University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Liberty University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. EQ 69:2 (1997), 139-155 John D. Morrison Patenloster BIbHcal and ~Iogical Monol!I"aphs A new series of doctoral theses of high academic standard. Heidegger, COITespondence Truth Calvin and English Calvinism R.T. Kendall and the Realist Theology of To this ground-breaking work, originally published by the Oxford University Press in the 19805, the author has added a new preface and Thomas Forsyth TOlTance two appendices, one consisting of extracts from calvin's Commen­ taries and the second of an extract from a PhD thesis by Ktu1: Daniel. The author demonstrates that the English'Pmitans', which he calls 'experimental predestinarians', were followers of Jo~ ~'s suc­ cessor in Geneva, Theodore Beza, and not of Calvin himself. Dr Once known, Truths acquire a utilitarian crust; they no longer Kendall maintains that what became known as English Calvinism was interest us as truths but as useful recipes. That pure, sudden largely the thought of Beza not Calvin. illumination which characterizes truth accompanies the latter only at His book. is an important clarification ofcaIvin's position in relation the moment of discovery. Hence its Greek name aletheia, which to those who have been regarded as his followers. origtnally meant the same as the word apocalypsis later, that is, June, 1997 . discovery, revelation, or rather, unveiling, removing a veil or cover.1 ISBN: 0-85364-827-11300pp approx./pbl229 X 145mm £19.99 Ortega y Gasset The Extent of the Atonement The concept of truth enshrines at once the real being of things and A Dilemrrm for Refonned Theo~ from Calvin to the Consensus the revelation of things as they are in reality. The truth of being G. Michael Thomas comes to bear in its own light and in its own authority, constraining us by the power of what it is to assent to it and acknowledge it for This work traces the debate about the extent of the atonement in what it is in itself. 5t Anselm who developed that further in a more RefoImed theology to the Fonnula Consensus Helvetica of 1675. The realist way held truth to be the reality of things as they actually are introduction sketches the background in patristic and medieval independent of us before God and therefore as they ought to he theology and in the thought of Martin Luther and Martin Bucer. known and signified by us. Everything is what it actually is and not Chapter 2 identifies the dual approach in Calvin's thought on the atonement, and chapters 3-5 examine the approaches developed by something else and cannot according to its nature be other than it is. Theodore Beza, Heinrich Bullinger and Girolamo Zanchi and the That is what he called its inherent 'necessity" or 'truth.'2 Lutherans. Chapters 6 and 7 give an account of the development of a Thomas F. Torrance Covenant Theology and the reactions of the Refonned at the Synoo of Dort to Arminianism. Chapter 8 explores the teaching of John Cameron, whilst chapters 9 and 10 follow the development of I. Introduction Cameron's theology at the hands of Moise Amyraut. The final chapter The question and nature of truth has long been at the heart of concludes that the refonners never succeeded in defining the extent of various the atonement in a way which commanded general assent amongst philosophical ConCenl at levels and within and between themselves. It is proposed that a new approach is required and that schools of thought and method·. Truth as 'correspondence,' Karl Barth's reworking of the Refonned doctrine of predestination however that has been construed historically, has remained at makes significant progress in resolving the inconsistencies of the the center among the major competing views on the nature of classical refonned stance. truth. It has been called by some the 'common-sense' perspect­ June, 1997 ive. Yet in the last two centuries it has faced, as have emphases on ISBN: 0-85364-8Z8-X/OOOppl229 X 145mm £19.99 1 Jose Ortega y Gas.set, Meditations on Qui.rote, trans. E. Rugg and D. Marin Paternoster Press (New York: Norton, 1961) p. 67. PO Box 300 CarlIsle CumbrIa CAS 0QIi UK paternoster press • Thomas F. Torrance, Reality and Scientific ~ (Edinburgh: The Scottish • Academic Pre.., 1961), p. 141, Hereafter RST. 140 The Evangelical Qunrterly Correspondence Truth &' Realist Theo/o:!}l of Torrance 141 (critical) realist knowledge of the world, much negative re­ 'the true one states about you the things that are as they are,' and sponse.' In the twentieth centuIy such antagonism has arisen not 'the faIse statement states about you things different from the only from among neo-Kantians and some analytical philosophers things that are.'5 While the dialogue questions the human but from philosophers influenced by the thought of Martin capacity to know what is real and what is unreal at several Heidegger. It has been commonplace in some quarters to identifY points, the Stranger proposes a definition of 'real being' as that Heidegger's understanding of truth as 'disclosure' or 'uncovering' which is constituted so as to 'possess any sort of power either to (a-letheia) as an overthrowing of the old, static, constrictive affect anything else or to he affected.'" But if knowing is an correspondence notions of truth. But this is not in fact what 'acting upon' the object known, then to he known is to be Heidegger has expressed. In fact his point is to support or changed. But this cannot occur in that which is changeless.' But undergird correspondence truth by his emphasis on disclosure. It Plato, throu~ the Stranger, is not asserting that reality is only the is this interpretation of Heidegger which Reformed Christian 'changeless, that which cannot he acted upon by the knower. theolOgian Thomas Torrance carefully appropriates for his own Rather, as he later asserts, reality is comprised of both 'all that is discussions of the Truth of God disclosed in his Word-thus his changeless and all that is in change.'8 But in the Sophist, Plato's emphases on both correspondence and coherence truth, and on arguments are not brought to resolution in relation to presenta­ critical realism. tions of truth as correspondence. Correspondence theory is here qualified by attendant arguments which question the simplicity or self-evidence of perceptual givens as static realities which can II. COJTeSpondence Truth: Some Classical Expressions be 'read off the surface.' In the process of examining Martin Heidegger's apparently Similar {,oints are developed in the Theaetetus where Socrates negative response to 'correspondence theories' of truth, it is says that things are not given in themselves but rather 'for each necessary that one see clearly that against which Heidegger is other,' i.e., 'whether we speak of something's 'being' or its responding. For that reason we will examine briefly what are 'becoming,' we must speak of it as being or becoming for often regarded as three 'classical' formulations of correspond­ someone, or of something, or toward something.'" He then ence truth in the Western tradition: the Platonic, the Aristotelian develops the argument that 'agent' and 'patient' are relative to and the Thomistic. In the words of Richard Rorly, these three are each other, which raises the problem of relativism, that 'what all found (rightly or wrongly) to fall within the paradigm of 'the every man believes as a result of perception is ... true for him.' mind as a great mirror, containing various representations­ To avoid this, Socrates turns the argument away from perception some accurate, some not-and capable of being studied by pure, to the mental operations involved in perceptuaIly grounded nonempirical methods. '4 judgments. Knowledge occurs on a level that is as much mental Plato's understanding of correspondence truth is said to be as perceptual, as shown by knowledge based on memory, covertly developed in the Republic, with the first explicit formula­ knowledge of a fact not even present to the senses and thus tions of a correspondence theory to he found in the Sophist and de,!"ed not from sense experience but from mental operations the Theaetetus. Yet even here Plato seems to reflect some which transcend such (as in mathematics). Along simllar lines, hesitation about it. In the Sophist, truth as correspondence is ~ates finally ~oncludes that :we must not look for (knowledge) pres~ted ~ relation to basic inst~ces of human judgment ill sense perception at all, but ill what goes on when the mind is illvolvmg direct perceptual apprehenslon of the current condition of a particular given. Regarding the truth or falsity of statements, 5 Plato, Sophist 236a, trans. P.M. Comfocd, Collected Dialogues, ed. Edith 3 In contrast to naive realism, critical realism, as Torrance understands it, seeks Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (Princeton: Princeton University Press, knowledge of and correction by the external fuct of the object, 'the truth of 1961), pp.
Recommended publications
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • 52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich
    52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich TIMOTHY O’HAGAN Like Oscar Wilde I can resist everything except temptation. So when I re- ceived Anne Meylan’s tempting invitation to contribute to this Festschrift for Pascal Engel I accepted without hesitation, before I had time to think whether I had anything for the occasion. Finally I suggested to Anne the text of a pub- lic lecture which I delivered in 2008 and which I had shown to Pascal, who responded to it with his customary enthusiasm and barrage of papers of his own on similar topics. But when I re-read it, I realized that it had been written for the general public rather than the professional philosophers who would be likely to read this collection of essays. So what was I to do with it? I’ve decided to present it in two parts. In Part One I reproduce the original lecture, unchanged except for a few minor corrections. In Part Two I engage with a tiny fraction of the vast secondary literature which has built up over the years and which shows no sign of abating. 1. Part One: The 2008 Lecture Curtain-Raiser Let us start with two dates, 1927 and 1933. In 1927 Adolf Hitler’s Mein Kampf (volume II) was published. So too was Martin Heidegger’s magnum opus Being and Time. In 1933 two appointments were made: Hitler as Chancellor of the German Reich and Heidegger as Rector of Freiburg University. In 1927 it was a case of sheer coincidence; in 1933 the two events were closely linked.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporality and Historicality of Dasein at Martin Heidegger
    Sincronía ISSN: 1562-384X [email protected] Universidad de Guadalajara México Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Javorská, Andrea Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=513852378011 This work is licensed under Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. PDF generated from XML JATS4R by Redalyc Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Filosofía Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Andrea Javorská [email protected] Constantine the Philosopher University in Nitra, Eslovaquia Abstract: Analysis of Heidegger's work around historicity as an ontological problem through the existential analytic of Being Dasein. It seeks to find the significant structure of temporality represented by the historicity of Dasein. Keywords: Heidegger, Existentialism, Dasein, Temporality. Resumen: Análisis de la obra de Heidegger en tornoa la historicidad como problema ontológico a través de la analítica existencial del Ser Dasein. Se pretende encontrar la estructura significativa de temporalidad representada por la historicidad del Dasein. Palabras clave: Heidegger, Existencialismo, Dasein, Temporalidad. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Martin Heidegger and his fundamental ontology shows that the question Received: 03 August 2015 Revised: 28 August 2015 of history belongs among the most fundamental questions of human Accepted:
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Heidegger's Phenomenology and the Science of Mind
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2005 Martin Heidegger's phenomenology and the science of mind Charles Dale Hollingsworth Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Hollingsworth, Charles Dale, "Martin Heidegger's phenomenology and the science of mind" (2005). LSU Master's Theses. 2713. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/2713 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MARTIN HEIDEGGER’S PHENOMENOLOGY AND THE SCIENCE OF MIND A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts In The Department of Philosophy by Charles Dale Hollingsworth B.A., Mississippi State University, 2003 May 2005 TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract.......................................................................................iii Chapter 1 The Computational Model of Mind and its Critics..........1 2 One Attempt at a Heideggerean Approach to Cognitive Science...........................................................................14 3 Heidegger on Scientific
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz, Mysticism and Religion Archives Internationales D'histoire Des Idees
    LEIBNIZ, MYSTICISM AND RELIGION ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDEES INTERNATIONAL ARCHIVES OF THE HISTORY OF IDEAS 158 LEIBNIZ, MYSTICISM AND RELIGION edited by ALLISON P. COUDERT, RICHARD H. POPKIN and GORDON M. WEINER Founding Directors: P. Dibon t (Paris) and R.H. Popkin (Washington University, St. Louis & UCLA) Director: Sarah Hutton (The University of Hertfordshire, Uni ted Kingdom) Associate Directors: lE. Force (Lexington); lC. Laursen (Riverside) Editorial Board: J.F. Battail (Paris); F. Duchesneau (Montreal); A. Gabbey (New York); T. Gregory (Rome); J.D. North (Groningen); MJ. Petry (Rotterdam); J. Popkin (Lexington); G.A.J. Rogers (Keele); Th. Verbeek (Utrecht) Advisory Editorial Board: J. Aubin (Paris); B. Copenhaver (Los Angeles); A. Crombie (Oxford); H. Gadamer (Heidelberg); H. Gouhier (Paris); K. Hanada (Hokkaido University); W. Kirsop (Melbourne); P.O. Kristeller (Columbia University); E. Labrousse (Paris); A. Lossky (Los Angeles); J. Malarczyk (Lublin); J. Orcibal (Paris); W. Röd (München); G. Rousseau (Los Angeles); H. Rowen (Rutgers University, NJ.); J.P. Schobinger (Zürich); J. Tans (Groningen) LEIBNIZ, MYSTICISM AND RELIGION Edited by ALLISON P. COUDERT Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona, U.S.A. RICHARD H. POPKIN University ofCalifornia, Los Angeles, California, U.S.A. and GORDON M. WEINER Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona, U.s.A. Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V. A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5088-5 ISBN 978-94-015-9052-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-9052-5 Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved @1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1998.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School November 2019 Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism Megan Flocken University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Flocken, Megan, "Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism" (2019). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/8098 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism by Megan Flocken A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Lee Braver, Ph.D. Charles Guignon, Ph.D. Ofelia Schutte, Ph.D. Iain Thomson, Ph.D. Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 12, 2019 Keywords: continental philosophy, ontology, comparative philosophy, Kehre Copyright © 2019, Megan Flocken TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................... ii CHAPTER ONE: HEIDEGGER’S WILL TO POWER AND THE PROBLEM OF NIETZSCHE’S
    [Show full text]
  • Was Heidegger a Mystic?
    Was Heidegger a Mystic? Jeff Guilford North Carolina State University Faculty Mentor: Marina Bykova North Carolina State University ABSTRACT The goal of Martin Heidegger’s philosophy is to lead his readers to an experience of Being. Because Being is not conceived of as a thing, but as that which ‘transcends’ things, thinking and talking about it in traditional terms becomes impossible. Such a goal is strikingly similar to the goals of many of the world’s most prominent mystical traditions, and prompts the question, was Heidegger a mystic? In this paper I seek to answer this question by comparing the ways in which Heidegger be- lieves that an experience of Being may be attained to the ways that mystics from many cultures have gone about bringing themselves to an experience of the transcendent. After demonstrating the strong analogies between the methods of Heidegger and of the mystics, I conclude that Heidegger is indeed a mystic and that the experience that he hopes to help people attain is probably the same experience toward which the mystics have traditionally striven. “There is a thinking more rigorous than the not red,’ the house is presented as an ob- conceptual” ~Martin Heidegger ject that lacks the property of redness. Similarly, in the statement, ‘Being is not a “The Tao is beyond is and is not. How do I thing,’ Being is presented as an object that know this? I look inside myself and see.” lacks the property of thing-ness. But this is ~Lao Tzu a misunderstanding, and we must learn to think differently if we want to understand dmittedly, grasping the objective of and experience Being.
    [Show full text]
  • Anxiety" in Heidegger's Being and Time: the Harbinger of Authenticity James Magrini College of Dupage, [email protected]
    College of DuPage [email protected]. Philosophy Scholarship Philosophy 4-1-2006 "Anxiety" in Heidegger's Being and Time: The Harbinger of Authenticity James Magrini College of DuPage, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.cod.edu/philosophypub Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Magrini, James, ""Anxiety" in Heidegger's Being and Time: The aH rbinger of Authenticity" (2006). Philosophy Scholarship. Paper 15. http://dc.cod.edu/philosophypub/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at [email protected].. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Scholarship by an authorized administrator of [email protected].. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DIALOGUE April, 2006 "Anxiety" in Heidegger's Being and Time: The Harbinger of Authenticity J.M. Magrini DePaul University ABSTRACT: Analyzing the fundamental ontology of Dasein in Martin Heidegger's Being and Time, this essay details the essential relationship between the mood of "anxiety" (Angst) and Dasein ' s authentic comportment to existence. Although a highly disturbing experience, anxiety holds the potential for enlightenment, as it opens Dasein to the fundamental characteristics of its temporal authenticity. Dasein assents to its Selfhood and enacts its freedom in a "resolute," authentic manner only when it grasps the difficult and burdensome aspects of life revealed by way of Angst's attunement. Thus, I argue that anxiety is the single most important mode of human attunement that Heidegger describes. This essay examines the relationship understanding in which the existent between the mood of anxiety (Angst) and Dasein does not understand itself primar­ Dasein's authentic comportment to ily by that apprehended possibility of existence.
    [Show full text]
  • Remembrances of Martin Heidegger in Marburg
    (Originally Published in Philosophy Today, Swnmer 1979, Pages 160-169) (© 1979 by the Messenger Press. Reprinted by Permission) REMEMBRANCES OF MARTIN HEIDEGGER IN MARBURG elisabeth hirsch According to Heidegger's own bered houses and the castle on a hill, words the years of his teaching career Marburg exuded a romantic· atmos­ he enjoyed most were those in Marburg phere. In addition, in a few minutes from 1923-1928. These were also the one was deep in nature and so Hei­ best years of the Weimar Republic. The degger could enjoy his customary af­ German mark was stabilized, the econ­ ternoon walks. If one was lucky to omy greatly improved and the cultural meet him, he would always stop for life reached a high point. Dance, music, a short talk. theater, the visual arts and poetry Today Marburg has 1;),000 students flourished as never before and created and half of them are Communists. But an atmosphere of excitement among when Heidegger was there, Marburg young people. And the immensely pro­ had only 3,000 students; their contact ductive intellectual and artistic actiY­ with thl' professors was close. Marburg ity did not fail to have an impact on was rather notorious for hE'r many the academic community. The French dueling fraternities; the students be­ writer Paul Duhamel was greatly im­ lansing to them were mostly conserva­ pressed by the German universities. In tiYes in politics. In opposition to them a lecture he delivered at Marburg Uni­ the liberal students founded the aca­ versity he remarked: "There are said demic association; if my memory is to be seven world wonders but the Ger­ correct, Heidegger attended some of man universities must be added as the its meetings.
    [Show full text]
  • The Experience of Nature in Heidegger
    OPO 6 Conference Memphis, TN January 4, 2019 The Experience of Nature in Heidegger Yuto KANNARI1 In phenomenology, “Nature (Natur)” has a highly complex character, which has been extensively discussed in the literature. In Husserl, three types of nature can be identified: 1) the nature as physical, causal, mechanical nature in the naturalistic attitude: 2) the living nature as the natural basis of the spiritual Ego: and 3) the primal nature, which should have been given before any sedimentation of spiritual products.2 Nature appears as what is constituted, what constitutes and the premise of what constitutes. The circumstances are similar for Heidegger. While nature appears in the context of criticizing the traditional concept of the world in Being and Time (BT), it appears as ready-to-hand (Zuhandenes) and present-at-hand (Vorhandenes) in everyday life. Furthermore, after BT, apart from nature as individual entities, nature is the presupposition of the factical existence of Dasein. On the other hand, nature is connected with the truth (ἀ-λήθεια), the happening (Ereignis), and the fourfold (Geviert), which are the keywords in middle and late Heidegger. What is nature? How can we describe the experience of nature? The whole picture of the concept of nature has not been disclosed. In this article, by following the development of the concept of nature in Heidegger, we clarify indices that distinguish nature, and what is the experience of nature that is the presupposition of experience. This article proceeds as follows. First, we will organize the multiple meanings of nature that are ambiguously used in BT through criticizing several previous studies (Section 1).
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger and Deleuze: the Groundwork of Evental Ontology James Scott Ahohb
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 5-6-2016 Heidegger and Deleuze: The Groundwork of Evental Ontology James Scott ahohB Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bahoh, J. (2016). Heidegger and Deleuze: The Groundwork of Evental Ontology (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/1520 This One-year Embargo is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE: THE GROUNDWORK OF EVENTAL ONTOLOGY A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By James Scott Bahoh May 2016 Copyright by James Scott Bahoh 2016 HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE: THE GROUNDWORK OF EVENTAL ONTOLOGY By James Scott Bahoh Approved April 6, 2016 ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. Daniel Selcer Dr. Fred Evans Associate Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ Dr. Andrew Mitchell Associate Professor of Philosophy (External Committee Member: Emory University) ________________________________ ________________________________ Dr. James Swindal Dr. Ronald Polansky Dean, McAnulty College and Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT HEIDEGGER AND DELEUZE: THE GROUNDWORK OF EVENTAL ONTOLOGY By James Scott Bahoh May 2016 Dissertation supervised by Professor Daniel Selcer This dissertation examines the concept of event, as found in the ontologies developed by Martin Heidegger (1889-1976) and Gilles Deleuze (1925-1995).
    [Show full text]
  • Jussi Backman, “The Absent
    [This is the submitted manuscript of Jussi Backman, “The Absent Foundation: Heidegger on the Rationality of Being,” Philosophy Today 49 (5): 175–84, available in published form at http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/philtoday200549Supplement22.] THE ABSENT FOUNDATION: HEIDEGGER ON THE RATIONALITY OF BEING Jussi Backman Nihil est sine ratione, “nothing is without reason.” For everything that is, there is an answer to the question why it is just so and not otherwise—and, ultimately, there is a reason (ratio) grounding the fact that there is something rather than nothing. Reality as a whole is thus “rational” or “reasonable,” in the sense that everything is based on something and has a “why” or a “how come” that grounds it, rendering it comprehensible and meaningful and thus letting it be part of meaningful reality. Nothing is without something that lets it be what it is. This is the famous “principle of reason” (principium rationis)—in a slightly different formulation, the “principle of the restoration of sufficient reason” (principium reddendae rationis sufficientis)—which was first explicitly 1 formulated in these words by G. W. Leibniz, although not as a doctrine of his own but as a fundamental and generally accepted philosophical principle. There is in Nature a reason [ratio] why something should exist rather than nothing. This is a consequence of the great principle that nothing comes to be without reason, just as there also must be a reason why this exists, rather than something else.1 Indeed, in one form or another, the principle of reason has been an integral part of Occidental metaphysics ever since antiquity.
    [Show full text]