On the Development of Dialectical Materialism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Development of Dialectical Materialism Munich Personal RePEc Archive You Cannot Swim Twice in the Same River: The Genesis of Dialectical Materialism Pillai N., Vijayamohanan Centre for Development Studies January 2013 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/45011/ MPRA Paper No. 45011, posted 13 Mar 2013 11:58 UTC You Cannot Swim Twice in the Same River: The Genesis of Dialectical Materialism Vijayamohanan Pillai N. Centre for Development Studies, Trivandrum, India E-mail: [email protected] © Vijayamohanan Pillai N. 1 You Cannot Swim Twice in the Same River: The Genesis of Dialectical Materialism Vijayamohanan Pillai N. Abstract: This constitutes a chapter of a book on ‘Poverty of Communism: The Game of Filling in the Marxian Blanks’. Dialectical materialism is the world outlook of Marxism; it is so called, because its approach to the phenomena of nature is dialectical, and its interpretation of these phenomena, its theory, is materialistic. Though the term ‘dialectical materialism’ owes its origin to Plekhanov and Lenin, its first expositor was Engels, who simply called it ‘modern materialism’ and asserted that it was essentially connected with the name of Marx. The present paper traces out the historical development of dialectical materialism, starting with its Greek philosophical origin in Heraclitus, who stressed the unity of opposites in a world of change, and passing through the dialogues of Socrates, and logic of Aristotle, Kant, Hegel, Chalybäus (famous for his exegetical characterization of Hegel’s dialectics in terms of thesis- antithesis-synthesis triad) and Feuerbach, all culminating in Marxism. The paper also discusses the experimental games of Lenin and his followers in filling in the Marxian blanks in dialectical materialism. 2 You Cannot Swim Twice in the Same River: The Genesis of Dialectical Materialism Vijayamohanan Pillai N. “And so with dialectic; when a person starts on the discovery of the absolute by the light of reason only, and without any assistance of sense, and perseveres until by pure intelligence he arrives at the perception of the absolute good, he at last finds himself at the end of the intellectual world, as in the case of sight at the end of the visible.” Plato, The Commonwealth As we have already noted, dialectical materialism is the world outlook of Marxism; it is so called, because its approach to the phenomena of nature is dialectical, and its interpretation of these phenomena, its theory, is materialistic. Though the term ‘dialectical materialism’ owes its origin to Plekhanov and Lenin, its first expositor was Engels, who simply called it ‘modern materialism’, though he firmly asserts that it “is essentially connected with the name of Marx.” (Engels 1886 [1970]). It goes without saying that the oldest and most authoritative exposition of the doctrine appeared in Engels’ Anti-Dühring (1878). Another important sourcebook is his Dialectics of Nature, written during 1873 – 1886 and published posthumously only in 1925. It is widely accepted that Anti-Dühring has been second only to Capital in boosting the dissemination of Marxian thought. The Italian Marxist theoretician, Antonio Labriola (1843-1904), wrote that this work is “the most accomplished work of critical socialism and contains in a nutshell the whole philosophy required for the thinkers of socialism” (Labriola 1897), and that “This work of Engels remains the unexcelled book in the 3 literature of socialism” (Part 4). According to Lenin, Anti-Dühring “is a wonderfully rich and instructive book”, “analysing highly important problems in the domain of philosophy, natural science and the social sciences” (Lenin 1895). However, it should be noted that dialectical materialism as formulated in Anti-Dühring has been traditionally regarded as the joint contribution of Marx and Engels. Engels himself admits: “I must note in passing that inasmuch as the mode of outlook expounded in this book was founded and developed in far greater measure by Marx, and only in an insignificant degree by myself, it was understood between us that this exposition of mine should not be issued without his knowledge. I read the whole manuscript to him before it was printed and the tenth chapter of the part of economics (From the Critical History) was written by Marx, but unfortunately had to be shortened somewhat by me for purely external reasons. As a matter of fact, we had always been accustomed to helping each other out in special subjects.” (Engels 1878 [1947]. The term ‘dialectics’ is derived from the Greek verb for ‘to talk’) and the preposition ‘through’); the middle form means ‘talking over’, and means ‘I converse or discuss or debate’. The adjective then means ‘pertaining to dialectics, or to proficiency in dialectics’. In Greek philosophy the concept originally signified a ‘quest by means of dialogue’, as in the heuristic method of Socrates that found perfection in the dialogues (Phaidros) of Plato. The method consisted in competence in conversation, conducted in the form of a question-answer game aimed at bringing out the contradiction in the opponent’s arguments and thus reaching consensus regarding truth. Thus dialectics implied opposites and contradictions. Heraclitus, who stressed the unity of opposites in a world of change (“All things come into being by conflict of opposites, and ‘the whole’ flows like a stream.”), is commonly regarded as one of the pre-Socratic dialecticians. He hypothesized the oppositional processes as ‘strife’ and the apparently stable state, which he called ‘justice’, as a harmony of strife. He said: “Opposition brings concord; and out of discord comes the fairest harmony.” Aristotle, however, attributed the earliest use of dialectics to Zeno (c. 490 – 430 B. C.) of Elea, who defended the monistic doctrines of Parmenides through arguments based on paradoxes against opposing pluralist views. These paradoxes had the form of an antinomy, a special kind of reductio argument. That is, he sought to refute the hypotheses of opponents by drawing contradictory and thus unacceptable consequences from those hypotheses. Note that in the sense of the art of inference or argument based on reasoning, Zeno’s dialectics is 4 synonymous with logic; for example, consider the law of formal logic known as ‘removing method’ (if p implies q, and q is false, then p is false). The next historical turn was with the Sophists (the word is derived from the same Greek root as the words sophia (= ‘wisdom’) and sophós (= ‘wise man’), the first encyclopaedists of the ancient world and the first in the history of philosophy to emerge as paid teachers of wisdom. They became the founders of the art of rhetoric, and they taught the free citizen of the city state to reason, to argue, to refute and prove, in short, to defend his own interests by rhetoric, public speaking, by ‘making the worse reason appear the better’, in order to win votes of the people (the demos), to obtain power by persuading the masses. Protagoras, famous for his humanism (“Man is the measure of all things”), was perhaps the greatest of the Sophists to employ this degenerate form of dialectic, which was called eristic and ridiculed by Plato (for example, in Sophist and Euthydemus). Aristotle also dealt with the Sophists’ deliberate use of invalid argumentation and sophistical tricks in his Sophistical refutations. Unlike Sophists, Socrates used a refined form of the Zenonian paradoxes, called the elenchus (= ‘argument of disproof or refutation’), a prolonged argument that refutes the opponent’s hypothesis by getting him to draw from it, by means of a series of questions and answers, a consequence that contradicts it. The law of logic here is: “if p implies not-p, and not-p is true, then p is false”. Plato (through Socrates) put dialektikê above the Sophists’ rhetorikê. He introduced dialectics in Books VI and VII of the Republic as the power of thought capable of comprehending the highest level in the divided line of knowledge, that is, the intelligible world, the world of Ideas; in this sense, dialectical thinking is reason, which grasps the ultimate reality independent of the senses. He placed dialectics on top of other studies like a coping-stone, above which no other study could rightly be put. Aristotle argued that the innovations that might justly be ascribed to Socrates were epagogic arguments and universal definition, as elenchus had already belonged to Zeno. In the logic of Aristotle, ‘induction’, (a move from particulars to the universal) is opposed to argument by syllogism, a logical argument in which one proposition (the conclusion) results of necessity from two assumptions (each called the premise). Note the core notion of ‘resulting of necessity’, which corresponds to a modern notion of logical consequence: R results of necessity from P and Q if it would be impossible for R to be false when P and Q are true. Aristotle considered dialectics in Organon, the standard collection of his six works: 5 Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Topics, and Sophistical Refutations, where formal logic emerged out of the dialectical logic of Plato. With Aristotle, dialectics suffered a devaluation again, falling into the proximity of sophistry, from which Socrates (Plato) had earlier rescued it. Aristotle (in Metaphysics) tried to explain Plato’s ontology through his method; Plato (according to Aristotle) introduced the notion of the Ideas on account of his preoccupation with dialectics. In Aristotelian logic, dialectics, on the other hand, was essentially a téchnê of persuasion, based on probable premises, in contrast to the apodictic scientific character of philosophy. Thus in the Topics, he defined a dialectical deduction as one in which its conclusion results of necessity from its premises, which are generally accepted. He often contrasted dialectics with demonstration, ‘a deduction that produces knowledge’, or ‘scientific deduction’, based on ‘true and primary’ premises. The Posterior Analytics contains his account (epistemology) of demonstrations and their role in knowledge.
Recommended publications
  • Through the Brook of Fire: Marx'sconceptofspecies- Being Andhisbreakwith Feuerbach
    1 WALKER THROUGH THE BROOK OF FIRE: MARX’S CONCEPT OF SPECIES- BEING AND HIS BREAK WITH FEUERBACH Grayson Shade Walker Supervised by Dr. Gabriel Gottlieb 30 April 2021 2 WALKER 1 | INTRODUCTION Once upon a time a valiant fellow had the idea that men were drowned in water only because they were possessed with the idea of gravity. If they were to knock this notion out of their heads, say by stating it to be a superstition, a religious concept, they would be sublimely proof against any danger from water. His whole life long he fought against the illusion of gravity, of whose harmful results all statistic brought him new and manifold evidence. This valiant fellow was the type of the new revolutionary philosophers in Germany.1 -- Karl Marx The task of this paper is to re-visit a concept that has long escaped proper clarification: Gattungswesen, or species-being. Many scholars have often assumed that the concept has no bearing on Marx’s later developments, or that it invariably bears the baggage of idealistic humanism not yet shorn by the younger Marx.2 While there may be traces of an incipient idealism in the early Marx—a product of his own post-Hegelian milieu—this paper will show how Marx inherits Feuerbach’s concept of species-being and, by overcoming its limitations, arrives at a new concept of humanity. I will show how Feuerbach fails to materialistically inverse Hegel, and how this failure leads him to a concept of man that is ultimately ahistorical—as it fixes a human essence beyond human history—and is idealist, to the extent that it begins from abstractions from the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Network Map of Knowledge And
    Humphry Davy George Grosz Patrick Galvin August Wilhelm von Hofmann Mervyn Gotsman Peter Blake Willa Cather Norman Vincent Peale Hans Holbein the Elder David Bomberg Hans Lewy Mark Ryden Juan Gris Ian Stevenson Charles Coleman (English painter) Mauritz de Haas David Drake Donald E. Westlake John Morton Blum Yehuda Amichai Stephen Smale Bernd and Hilla Becher Vitsentzos Kornaros Maxfield Parrish L. Sprague de Camp Derek Jarman Baron Carl von Rokitansky John LaFarge Richard Francis Burton Jamie Hewlett George Sterling Sergei Winogradsky Federico Halbherr Jean-Léon Gérôme William M. Bass Roy Lichtenstein Jacob Isaakszoon van Ruisdael Tony Cliff Julia Margaret Cameron Arnold Sommerfeld Adrian Willaert Olga Arsenievna Oleinik LeMoine Fitzgerald Christian Krohg Wilfred Thesiger Jean-Joseph Benjamin-Constant Eva Hesse `Abd Allah ibn `Abbas Him Mark Lai Clark Ashton Smith Clint Eastwood Therkel Mathiassen Bettie Page Frank DuMond Peter Whittle Salvador Espriu Gaetano Fichera William Cubley Jean Tinguely Amado Nervo Sarat Chandra Chattopadhyay Ferdinand Hodler Françoise Sagan Dave Meltzer Anton Julius Carlson Bela Cikoš Sesija John Cleese Kan Nyunt Charlotte Lamb Benjamin Silliman Howard Hendricks Jim Russell (cartoonist) Kate Chopin Gary Becker Harvey Kurtzman Michel Tapié John C. Maxwell Stan Pitt Henry Lawson Gustave Boulanger Wayne Shorter Irshad Kamil Joseph Greenberg Dungeons & Dragons Serbian epic poetry Adrian Ludwig Richter Eliseu Visconti Albert Maignan Syed Nazeer Husain Hakushu Kitahara Lim Cheng Hoe David Brin Bernard Ogilvie Dodge Star Wars Karel Capek Hudson River School Alfred Hitchcock Vladimir Colin Robert Kroetsch Shah Abdul Latif Bhittai Stephen Sondheim Robert Ludlum Frank Frazetta Walter Tevis Sax Rohmer Rafael Sabatini Ralph Nader Manon Gropius Aristide Maillol Ed Roth Jonathan Dordick Abdur Razzaq (Professor) John W.
    [Show full text]
  • Embracing the Flux of Academic Librarianship to Co-Author Meaningful Change
    Document Every thing determines everything Embracing the flux of academic librarianship to co-author meaningful change By Stephen Bales [Keynote address delivered at the 1st Annual Canadian Association of Professional Academic Librarians, Brock University, Saint Catharines, Ontario, May 26, 2014. The version herein has been modified from the original delivered at Brock University, and it also includes additional documentation and notes to further benefit the reader]. Introduction 137 I would like to thank the CAPAL Programme Committee for inviting me to speak today. I am honored to have this opportunity to share my ideas about academic librarianship with the members of the Canadian Association of Professional Academic Librarians. Today I want to discuss dialectical materialism as an alternative way of thinking about the academic library. It seems an appropriate topic for this conference, with its theme being the shifting landscapes of academic librarianship. Every one of us knows that the only true constant in the academic library is change. When I started library school in 2002, I think we were still at Web 1.0. Who knows what version we are on now? It’s a different world than it was just moments ago. Dialectical materialism has been around for nearly two Stephen Bales is Humanities and Social Sciences Librarian at Texas A&M University where he is subject librarian for communication & journalism, philosophy, religion, and anthropology. His research interests include the history and philosophy of libraries and librarianship and the professional identity of LIS workers. KEYWORDS: Philosophy of Library and Information Science; Professional Identity; Librarianship and Critical and Cultural Studies; Academic libraries; Dialectical materialism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Marxist Vol
    The Marxist Vol. XII, No. 4, October-December 1996 On the occasion of Lenin’s 125th Birth Anniversary Marxism Of The Era Of Imperialism E M S Namboodiripad The theoretical doctrines and revolutionary practices of Vladymir Illyich Lenin (whose 125th birth anniversary was recently observed by the Marxist-Leninists throughout the world), have well been called “Marxism of the Era of imperialism.” For, not only was Lenin a loyal disciple of Marx and Engels applying in practice their theory in his own homeland, but he also further developed the theory and practices of the two founders of Marxism. EARLY THEORETICAL BATTLES Born in Tsarist Russia which was seeped in its feudal environment, he noticed that capitalism was slowly developing in his country. He fought the Narodniks who advocated the doctrine of the irrelevance and no-applicability of Marxism to Russian conditions. His first major theoretical work was the Development of Capitalism in Russia where he proved that, though in feudal environment, capitalism was rapidly developing in Russia. He thus established the truth of Marxist theory of the working class being the major political force in the development of society. Further, an alliance of peasantry under working class leadership will form the core of the revolutionary forces in the conditions of backward feudal Russia. Having thus defeated the Narodniks, he proceeded to demolish the theory of “legal Marxists” according to whom Marxism was to be applies in perfectly legal battles against capitalism. He asserted the truth that the preparation for the social transformation in Russia should be based on the sharpening class struggle culminating in the proletarian revolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Anton Pannekoek: Ways of Viewing Science and Society
    STUDIES IN THE HISTORY OF KNOWLEDGE Tai, Van der Steen & Van Dongen (eds) Dongen & Van Steen der Van Tai, Edited by Chaokang Tai, Bart van der Steen, and Jeroen van Dongen Anton Pannekoek: Ways of Viewing Science and Society Ways of Viewing ScienceWays and Society Anton Pannekoek: Anton Pannekoek: Ways of Viewing Science and Society Studies in the History of Knowledge This book series publishes leading volumes that study the history of knowledge in its cultural context. It aspires to offer accounts that cut across disciplinary and geographical boundaries, while being sensitive to how institutional circumstances and different scales of time shape the making of knowledge. Series Editors Klaas van Berkel, University of Groningen Jeroen van Dongen, University of Amsterdam Anton Pannekoek: Ways of Viewing Science and Society Edited by Chaokang Tai, Bart van der Steen, and Jeroen van Dongen Amsterdam University Press Cover illustration: (Background) Fisheye lens photo of the Zeiss Planetarium Projector of Artis Amsterdam Royal Zoo in action. (Foreground) Fisheye lens photo of a portrait of Anton Pannekoek displayed in the common room of the Anton Pannekoek Institute for Astronomy. Source: Jeronimo Voss Cover design: Coördesign, Leiden Lay-out: Crius Group, Hulshout isbn 978 94 6298 434 9 e-isbn 978 90 4853 500 2 (pdf) doi 10.5117/9789462984349 nur 686 Creative Commons License CC BY NC ND (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0) The authors / Amsterdam University Press B.V., Amsterdam 2019 Some rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, any part of this book may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise).
    [Show full text]
  • University of Groningen De Dialectisch-Materialistische Filosofie Van
    University of Groningen De dialectisch-materialistische filosofie van Joseph Dietzgen Schaaf, Jasper Willem IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 1993 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Schaaf, J. W. (1993). De dialectisch-materialistische filosofie van Joseph Dietzgen. Kok/Agora. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 23-09-2021 SUMMARY Joseph Dietzgen (1828-1888) Joseph Dietzgen was a philosopher and a tanner. At the congress for the 'our International in The Hague in 1872, Marx called him philosopher', the philosopher of proletarian social democracy; he also said once that Dietzgen was one of the most brilliant workers he knew. Dietzgen was a self-educatedphilo- sopher. On the political scene, he played a part in the notorious'Haymarket' affair in Chicago in 1886; one of the events which led to the introduction of annual First of May celebrations of the international labour movement.
    [Show full text]
  • The Critique of Real Abstraction: from the Critical Theory of Society to the Critique of Political Economy and Back Again
    The Critique of Real Abstraction: from the Critical Theory of Society to the Critique of Political Economy and Back Again Chris O’Kane John Jay, CUNY [email protected] There has been a renewed engagement with the idea of real abstraction in recent years. Scholars associated with the New Reading of Marx, such as Moishe Postone, Chris Arthur, Michael Heinrich, Patrick Murray, Riccardo Bellofiore and others,1 have employed the idea in their important reconstructions of Marx’s critique of political economy. Alberto Toscano, Endnotes, Jason W. Moore and others have utilized and extended these theorizations to concieve of race, gender, and nature as real abstractions. Both the New Reading and these new theories of real abstraction have provided invaluable work; the former in systematizing Marx’s inconsistent and unfinished theory of value as a theory of the abstract social domination of capital accumulation and reproduction; the latter in supplementing such a theory. Yet their exclusive focus on real abstraction in relation to the critique of political economy means that the critical marxian theories of real abstraction -- developed by Alfred Sohn- Rethel, Theodor W. Adorno and Henri Lefebvre -- have been mostly bypassed by the latter and have largely served as the object of trenchant criticism for their insufficient grasp of Marx’s theory of value by the former. Consequently these new readings and new theories of real abstraction elide important aspects of Sohn-Rethel, Adorno and Lefebvre’s critiques of real abstraction; which sought to develop Marx’s critique of political economy into objective-subjective critical theories of the reproduction of capitalist society.2 However, two recent works by 1 Moishe Postone’s interpretation of real abstraction will be discussed below.
    [Show full text]
  • Marxist Philosophy and Organization Studies: Marxist Contributions to the Understanding of Some Important Organizational Forms by Paul S
    1 Marxist philosophy and organization studies: Marxist contributions to the understanding of some important organizational forms by Paul S. Adler Dept. of Management and Organization Marshall School of Business University of Southern California Los Angeles 90089-0808 Draft chapter for: Research in the Sociology of Organizations, Special Volume on Philosophy and Organization Theory, 2010, Guest editors: Haridimos Tsoukas and Robert Chia Version date: Feb 2, 2010 Author bio: Paul S. Adler is currently Harold Quinton Chair in Business Policy at the Marshall School of Business, University of Southern California.. He received his PhD in economics and management at the University of Picardie, France. His research and teaching focus on organization design, with a particular focus on technical, professional, and manufacturing operations. Acknowledgments Earlier drafts benefited from research assistance from Jade Lo and from comments by Michael Burawoy, Richard Delbridge, Steve Jaros, Martin Kenney, David Levy, Richard Marens, Mark Mizruchi, Craig Prichard, Mick Rowlinson, Paul Thompson, and Matt Vidal, even if there is much with which they still disagree. 2 Marxist philosophy and organization studies: Marxist contributions to the understanding of some important organizational forms Abstract This essay aims to how Marx’s ideas and subsequent Marxist-inspired scholarship have contributed to the analysis of the various forms of work organization. It summarizes Marx’s basic philosophy, theory of history, and critique of political economy; it distinguishes more critical and more optimistic variants of Marxist theory; and it then shows how these ideas have been used in the analysis of key organizational forms, contrasting Marxist versus non-Marxist approaches and critical versus optimistic versions of Marxism.
    [Show full text]
  • Xerox University Microfilms 300 North Zoeb Road Ann Arbor
    INFORMATION TO USERS This material was produced from a microfilm copy of the original document. While the most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this document have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the original submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you understand markings or patterns which may appear on this reproduction. 1.The sign or "target" for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is "Missing Page(s)". If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) dr section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting thru an image and duplicating adjacent pages to insure you complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a large round black mark, it is an indication that the photographer suspected that the copy may have moved during exposure and thus cause a blurred image. You will find a good image of the page in the adjacent frame. 3. When a map, drawing or chart, etc., was part of the material being photographed the photographer followed a definite method in "sectioning" the material. It is customary to begin photoing at the upper left hand corner of a large sheet and to continue photoing from left to right in equal sections with a small overlap. If necessary, sectioning is continued again - beginning below the first row and continuing on until complete. 4. The majority of users indicate that the textual content is of greatest value, however, a somewhat higher quality reproduction could be made from "photographs" if essential to the understanding of the dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • Engels, Trotsky and the Natural Sciences: a Case Study in Cosmology
    LA ÚLTIMA MORADA DE TROTSKY GABRIELA PÉREZ NORIEGA http://dx.doi.org/10.23925/1982-6672.2020v13i38p19-49 Engels, Trotsky and the natural sciences: a case study in cosmology Alex Steinberg1 https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2842-5687 Abstract: The topic of this essay is Trotsky’s approach to dialectical philosophy and the natural sciences. We will first summarize the tradition whose mantle Trotsky inherited as it was developed by Engels. We will then consider Trotsky’s relationship to the natural sciences. Trotsky, echoing Engels proclamations decades earlier, maintained that a dialectical philosophy is an essential guide to the work of the scientist while at the same time granting the autonomy and 19 freedom of scientists to pursue their research. Trotsky had a lifelong interest in following the developments in the natural sciences. He also had an intuitive grasp of some important developments in the natural sciences that would only come to fruition decades after his death. We will then present a case study of how a dialectical approach to nature can assist in overcoming a crisis that is plaguing contemporary physics. Specifically we will discuss how a dialectical approach to nature can inform cosmology in the 21st century and avoid the philosophical pitfalls and dead–ends that mark the contemporary crisis in physics. Keywords: Human Sciences; Marxism; Social History; Dialectical Materialism; Philosophy of Nature. 1 Alex Steinberg has taught classes on Hegel, Marxist philosophy, the dialectics of nature, and other topics at the Brecht Forum, the New Space and the Marxist Education Project. He has been a presenter and panelist at Socialist Scholars Conference, the Left Forum and Historical Materia- lism.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Thesis
    This electronic thesis or dissertation has been downloaded from the King’s Research Portal at https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/ “From the Theses on Feuerbach to the Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, Gramsci, Philosophy and Politics” Bernstein, Aaron Jacob Awarding institution: King's College London The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without proper acknowledgement. END USER LICENCE AGREEMENT Unless another licence is stated on the immediately following page this work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International licence. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ You are free to copy, distribute and transmit the work Under the following conditions: Attribution: You must attribute the work in the manner specified by the author (but not in any way that suggests that they endorse you or your use of the work). Non Commercial: You may not use this work for commercial purposes. No Derivative Works - You may not alter, transform, or build upon this work. Any of these conditions can be waived if you receive permission from the author. Your fair dealings and other rights are in no way affected by the above. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 23. Sep. 2021 1 From the Theses on Feuerbach to the Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, Gramsci, Philosophy and Politics Aaron Bernstein PhD European Studies 2 Abstract In recent years, there has been a growing literature on Gramsci’s conception of the philosophy of praxis, and specifically the centrality of Marx within it.
    [Show full text]
  • 361-Emerald Sabry-3611505 BIB 277..283
    REFERENCES Abdel Naem, S. (1985). Moslimo Turkistan wa al-ghazw al-Sofyetti min khilal al-tarikh wal adab (Turkistan’s Muslims and the Soviet invasion in history and literature). Cairo: Dar Al- Ta’awan lil Taba’a wal Nashr. Acemoglu, D., & Robinson, J. A. (2006). Economic origins of dictatorship and democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Adam Smith (1776). An Inquiry into the Nation and Cause of the Wealth of Nation. Glasgow Edition, Book IV. Al-Dirawi, O. (1990). Al-Harb Al-A’alamaya Al-Olaa (World War I). Beirut: Dar Al-Aalm lil- Malayien. Atkinson, A. B., & Morelli, S. (2014). Chartbook of economic inequality À Economic inequality over the long run. Retrieved from http://www.chartbookofeconomicinequality.com; internet. Accessed on May 1, 2015. Avineri, S. (1967). Marx and the intellectuals. Journal of the History of Ideas, 28(2), 269À278. (Apr. - Jun.): University of Pennsylvania Press.: Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/ 2708422; internet. Accessed on June 28, 2008. Baier, S., Dwyer, G. P., & Tamura, R. (2006). How important are capital and total factor productiv- ity for economic growth? Economic Inquiry, 44(1), 23À49. Bakunin, M. (1872). “On the International Workingmen’s Association and Karl Marx.” in Sam Dolgoff (1971) (edt.) Bakunin on Anarchy. Retrieved from https://www.marxists.org/refer- ence/archive/bakunin/works/1872/karl-marx.htm; internet. Accessed on August 11, 2016. Bakunin, M. (1873). “Critique of the Marxist theory of the State,” in Sam Dolgoff (1971) (edt.) Bakunin on Anarchy. Retrieved from https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/bakunin/ works/1873/statism-anarchy.htm#s1; internet.
    [Show full text]