1 the Background 1. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A21/B35

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 the Background 1. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A21/B35 170 Notes Notes 1 The Background 1. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A21/B35--6. I have followed the usual practice of referring to pages in the two editions of the Critique of Pure Reason by using A to denote the first edition and B to denote the second. In what follows, I shall refer to the Critique of Pure Reason by noting only the relevant pagination. 2. A50/B74. 3. Recent work on Kant's epistemology suggests that the faculty should be treated distinctly from the concepts it informs. Previously, Jonathan Bennett among others had argued that judgement plays an idle role in explanations of how we make assertions by applying concepts. See, for example, Hubert Schwyzer, The Unity of Under­ standing. A Study in Kantian Problems (1990), Chapters 1-3. 4. Bl31. 5. The use of 'I think' is not intended to lessen its certainty as if we were now falling short of asserting X and had to be satisfied with saying that 'I think that X' in the sense that 'It is my opinion (only) that X'. Rather, the claim is only that I can talk about what I am thinking of. 6. This and the above arguments are culled from Kant's Critique of Pure Reason and from Kant's Transcendental Idealism, by H. E. Allison. The latter seems to me to contain the most plausible recent account of Kant's central arguments. 7. Cf. Graham Bird, Kant's Theory of Knowledge, (1962) and Gerd Buch­ dahl, Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science (1968), both of whom develop accounts of the difference between transcendental and em­ pirical necessities. 8. Bxiii. 9. Ibid. 10. Sections 383, A. G . Baumgarten, Metaphysica (Hildesheim, 1963). 11. Ibid., Section 462. 12. G. W. Leibniz, New Essays Concerning Human Understanding, Section 11. 13. Vernunftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt, und der Seele des Menschen (1720), (Abbreviated as VGG), Section 276. 14. Wolff also proposes a distinction between figurative and intuitive knowledge (VGG, Section 316) by which to refine Leibniz's account of perfect and imperfect knowledge. In spite of their differences, both provide degrees of knowledge. 15. Section 123, A. G. Baumgarten, Aesthetica (Hildesheim, 1970). 16. Aesthetica, Section 619. 17. Aesthetica, Section 22. 18. Aesthetica, Section 2. Notes 171 19. Reflections on Poetry, Section 13. 20. Ibid., Section 13. 21. Sections 14 and 15. 22. Section 19. 23. Section 38. 24. Section 40. 25. Aesthetica, Section 177. 26. Aesthetica, Section 181. 27. Kant's a priori justifications of validity deny the power of inductive generalizations about our actual behaviour, such as Hume and Burke propose, to justify the validity of aesthetic response. I have not developed the contrast between Kant's theory and empiricist explana­ tions of aesthetics because a great deal of work is already available in English on this subject. The relation between Kant and the rationalists is less studied, and I thought it would be more useful to develop some details of the theories here. Paul Crowther discusses some aspects of the relation between Kant, Burke, and Addison in Part I of The Kantian Sublime. From Morality to Art (1989). 28. Kant wrote this book under the influence of Burke's Philosophical Enquiry into the Origins of our Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful, and entertained pronouncements on how ideas of beauty varied between countries, cultures, and races. 2 The 'Analytic of the Beautiful' 1. Though they associated it with perfection. 2. They are also aesthetic in the first sense, of course, but that claim does not need argument because it only says that judgements of taste are judgements of taste. In the second sense it says that judgements of taste have to do with our feelings and sensations. 3. Immanuel Kant, Critique of judgement, ~ection 1, 204. See also Section 25, 228, where Kant notes that the aesthetic judgement gives us no knowledge, not even confused knowledge, of an object. I have usually used the translation of the Critique of Judgement by Werner Pluhar, published by Hackett (1987). Page numbers refer to the Academy Edition of Kant's works, which Pluhar cites in the margins. In some instances I have used the translation of the Critique of Judgement by James Creed Meredith because of the felicity of its phrasing. In what follows, I have abbreviated the Critique of Judgement as KDU. 4. B171. 5. These ways, we know, depend on the twelve categories. Kant classi­ fies those twelve categories under four major headings of Quantity, Quality, Relation, and Modality. Thus, causality, substance, and reci­ procity belong under the rubric of Relation, while possibility, necess­ ity, and existence belong with Modality. Any sentence, thought, or judgement must use at least one categorv from each of the four rubrics. We cannot assert at the same time that the same thing is possible and necessary or existent, but it must be one of those. Similarly, that item must constitute a causal relation or one ot 172 Notes substance and its accidents, and so on. Cf. B106, for the list of categories. 6. A133/B172. 7. Ibid. 8. A134/B173-4. 9. My attempt to separate out an act of judging from the particular application of a concept may seem problematic, especially given the criticisms familiar in analytic philosophy against such a distinction. Jonathan Bennett, for example, argues that Kant's distinction is fraught with difficulties and makes an unnecessary complication out of the schematism. More recently, this position has been questioned, I think effectively, by Stuart Bell, 'The Art of Judgement and the Judgement of Art', Mind, 1987, and The Unity of Understanding, A Study in Kantian Problems by Hubert Schwyzer (1990). My account of judge­ ment owes considerably to these two publications. 10. Cf. the Introductions to the Critique of Judgement. 11. But also, because we gain this appreciation of order in judgement, it involves the faculty which is distinctively Kantian. If Kant can associ­ ate taste with the activity of this faculty, he will avoid many of the problems afflicting earlier aesthetic theories, which fell victim to a number of problems because they did not make good use of a concept of judgement and associated taste with mere sense, and sensate knowledge with perfection. 12. KDU, 169. lt may be as well to emphasize here that for Kant judge­ ment shows itself in the beauty of both art and nature. Such an emphasis should go to counter the tendency, prevalent for too long in secondary literature, on Kant's aesthetic theory, to claim that his concern is with natural beauty principally. Rather, given his interest in the spontaneous and creative activity of judgement, Kant is unlikely to be satisfied by its exhibition in natural beauty alone, for fine art best embodies the creative power of judgement, of the activity of discover­ ing order, in which the creative power is at its most exemplary in making us conscious of the fact of grasping a richly novel and valuable material produced by our genius, where genius shares in the sponta­ neity native to judgement. 13. KDU, 169. 14. KDU, 194. 15. KDU. 215. Italics added. 16. KDU, 203 nl. 17. See KDU Section 59 for the claims about realism. The issues appear also in S. Kemal, Kant and Fine Art, 131-4. 18. KDU, Section 43. 19. We should make clear that most claims about the Critique of Judgement are controversial. Although the text has gained serious attention from Kantians only in recent years, in this short span it has generated debate over precisely what its issues are. For example, even if we are agreed that intersubjective validity is a crucial issue, the role it plays and its scope are still open to discussion. In this situation any thesis may be found controversial, and although it is not possible for us to enter into discussion with everyone about everything, in this intro- Notes 173 ductory book we will usually indicate in the end-notes what disagree­ ments there are and what diverse positions authors have identified or developed. 20. KDU, 211. 21. KDU, 219. 22. KDU, 236. 23. KDU. 240. 24. KDU, n 203. 25. KDU, 204. See the interesting papers by Rudolph Makkreel, in which he develops Kant's talk of a 'feeling of life' by reference to Dilthey's work, to show that aesthetic judgements have a wider role to play in our practical lives. The formal properties of aesthetic judgements, therefore, must be put in the context of Kant's more general philo­ sophical concerns. Makkreel identifies a hermeneutical issue in the Analytic and later sections, where by displaying the role and nature of the 'productive imagination' Kant's work can be seen as a contribution to the debate between explanation and understanding. R. Makkreel, 'The Feeling of Life: Some Kantian Sources of Life-Philosophy', Dilthey-Jahrbuch fUr Philosophie und Geschichte der Geisteswissenschaften, Band 3, 1985, 83-104; 'The Role of Synthesis in Kant's Critique of Judgement', Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress, 1985, (1990). The results of these papers are presented in R. Makkreel, Understanding and Imagination in Kant. The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgement (1990). 26. KDU, 203. 27. Of course, it is also the case that thinkers at various times have accepted that some role is played by pleasure, but have denied it the centrality which Kant accords to it. 28. In any case, Kant does provide something of a more basic defence of his association of pleasure and beauty, for he sees pleasure as distinc­ tively subjective, and so is able to use it to explain the nature of the activity of judging.
Recommended publications
  • Science, Subjectivity & Reality
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Science and Religion Dialogue Prints Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research| April 2016 | Volume 7 | Issue 4 | pp. 333-336 333 Pereira, C. & Reddy, J. S. K., On Science & Phenomenology in Consciousness Studies Perspective Science, Subjectivity & Reality * Contzen Pereira & J. S. K. Reddy Abstract In this paper, we argue on the ability of science to capture the true subjective experience of life, blinded within the limits of its reductionist approaches. With this approach, even though science can explain well the physics behind the objective phenomenon, it fails fundamentally in understanding the various aspects associated with the biological entities. In this sense, we are skeptical to the present approach of science and calls out for a more fundamental theory of life that considers not only the objectivity aspect of a biological entity but also the subjective experience as well. It raises questions as to what does it takes to develop a new science from a subjective standpoint. Key Words: Science, subjectivity, reality, cosmos, peripersonal space. Modern science is based on the principle “Give us one free miracle and we’ll explain the rest.” The one free miracle is the appearance of all the matter and energy in the universe and all the laws that govern it from nothing, in a single instant - Terrence McKenna The Cosmos showers the experience of life graced by an enigmatic subject grounded in an objective fabric (or biological structure). The extent of the subjective experience is in a way bounded by the limitations of an objective fabric.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Habitus and the Power of the Embodied Self: Reflections on the Insights Gained from the Fakirs in Bangladesh
    23 Bangladesh e-Journal of Sociology. Volume 17, Number 2. July 2020. Aristotelian Habitus and the Power of the Embodied Self: Reflections on the Insights Gained from the Fakirs in Bangladesh Mohammad Golam Nabi Mozumder1, Abstract: This article traces back classical Greek and Medieval meanings of habitus to show that Bourdieu’s redefinition of habitus discarded a seminal feature of Aristotelian habitus—the power of radically transforming the self at will. I elaborate how the practices of purposefully training the embodied self remains marginalized in Pierre Bourdieu’s re-conceptualization of habitus. Examining Aristotle’s habitus, this paper brings back the focus on the long-neglected insight of the power of deliberately (re)training the self in constructing a heterodox but ethical way of being and socializing. As an example, I refer to the Fakirs in current Bangladesh, who cultivate antinomian life-practices. The main argument of the paper is that habitus in Bourdieu’s formulations is less suitable than Aristotle’s in analysing the praxis of the Fakirs. I suggest that instead of sticking to a universal conceptualization of habitus, sociologists should consider with equal importance both models of habitus articulated by Aristotle and Bourdieu. Doing that could benefit contemporary sociology in two ways: First, Aristotle’s conceptualization of habitus is an important tool in identifying the sociological importance of the praxis of marginalized groups, e.g., Fakirs in Bangladesh; and second, extending the focus of a key sociological concept, i.e., habitus, addresses the apparent disconnect between the wisdom of heterodox practitioners in the Global South and dominant social theories built upon the analyses of European and American social traditions.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel and Aristotle
    HEGEL AND ARISTOTLE ALFREDO FERRARIN Boston University published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, vic 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Alfredo Ferrarin 2001 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2001 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Baskerville 10.25/13 pt. System QuarkXPress™ 4.04 [AG] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Ferrarin, Alfredo, 1960– Hegel and Aristotle / Alfredo Ferrarin. p. cm.–(Modern European philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 0-521-78314-3 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770–1831. 2. Aristotle – Influence. I. Title. II. Series. B2948 .F425 2000 193–dc21 00-029779 ISBN 0 521 78314 3 hardback CONTENTS Acknowledgments page xiii List of Abbreviations xv Introduction 1 § 1. Preliminary Notes 1 § 2. On the Object and Method of This Book 7 § 3. Can Energeia Be Understood as Subjectivity? 15 part i the history of philosophy and its place within the system 1. The Idea of a History of Philosophy 31 § 1. The Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Editions and Sources 31 § 2.
    [Show full text]
  • GALGAN, Gerald J., God and Subjectivity Roy Martinez
    Document generated on 09/30/2021 1:58 a.m. Laval théologique et philosophique GALGAN, Gerald J., God and Subjectivity Roy Martinez Volume 49, Number 1, février 1993 URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/400749ar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/400749ar See table of contents Publisher(s) Faculté de philosophie, Université Laval ISSN 0023-9054 (print) 1703-8804 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this review Martinez, R. (1993). Review of [GALGAN, Gerald J., God and Subjectivity]. Laval théologique et philosophique, 49(1), 166–167. https://doi.org/10.7202/400749ar Tous droits réservés © Laval théologique et philosophique, Université Laval, This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit 1993 (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ COMPTES RENDUS observed. At the foundation of this study, and present This disparity between the existence of the "this" like a shadow throughout it, is the Platonic-Christian and the cognizing agent posed no problem for first view of time as an image of eternity, and of ourselves philosophy since 'the other", or object of cognition, as redeemed from time, and able in part to compre• was simply given, there for apprehension or obser• hend it, through being in the image of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes for Our Seminar: Objectivity and Subjectivity
    Notes for our seminar: Objectivity and Subjectivity B.M. December 14, 2019 Contents I A preview and overview of the topics we may cover 2 1 The nature of our seminar-course 3 II Readings and Notes for the sessions of Sept 11, Oct 2, Oct 30, and part of Dec 4 13 2 Readings for the September 11 session 13 2.1 Excerpt from [9] . 14 3 Some notes for Sep 11: Subjectivity, Universal Subjectivity, Objectivity 15 3.1 Objective . 16 4 Readings for October 2: 25 5 Notes for Oct 21 session: Objectivity and Subjectivity in Mathematics 36 5.1 What is the number `A thousand and one'?....................... 37 5.2 Plato ............................................ 38 5.3 `Tower Pound' definition ................................ 39 1 5.4 J.S. Mill .......................................... 39 5.5 Georg Cantor: ...................................... 40 5.6 Gottlob Frege (∼ 1900) ................................ 41 5.7 Foundations::: or Constitutions ............................. 43 5.8 David Hilbert ....................................... 43 5.9 L.E.J. Brouwer ...................................... 46 5.10 The simple phrase \and so on::: "............................ 48 6 Readings for October 30, 2019: (Shades of Objectivity and Subjectivity in Epistemology, Probability, and Physics) 50 7 Notes for October 30, 2019:(Shades of Objectivity and Subjectivity in Epistemology, Probability, and Physics) 51 8 Subjectivity and Objectivity in Statistics: `Educating your beliefs' versus `Test- ing your Hypotheses' 55 8.1 Predesignation versus the self-corrective nature of inductive reasoning . 57 8.2 Priors as `Meta-probabilities' . 59 8.3 Back to our three steps . 61 8.4 A numerical example and a question . 62 9 Issues of Subjectivity and Objectivity in Physics 63 10 Consequentialism of Meaning|notes for part of session of December 4 65 11 Dealing with nonexistent objects 69 2 Part I A preview and overview of the topics we may cover 1 The nature of our seminar-course Phil273O (Objectivity and Subjectivity) will be the fourth seminar- course I've taught with Amartya Sen and Eric Maskin.
    [Show full text]
  • Subjectivity and Objectivity Intentional Inexistence and the Independence of the Mind Michael Oliva Córdoba University of Hamburg Version: Wednesday, 4 July 2018
    Subjectivity and objectivity Intentional inexistence and the independence of the mind Michael Oliva Córdoba University of Hamburg Version: Wednesday, 4 July 2018 Introduction Few distinctions in philosophy are as pervasive as the distinction between the subjective and the objective. Apparently, this distinction has less often been submitted to thorough examination than one would expect. Perhaps this is due to its diffcult nature. It might also be due to the uneasiness with which the subjective-objective distinction is brought to harmony with the received scientifc perspective on the world. Yet so deep entrenched in our conceptual scheme is this distinction that to cast light on it is a worthwhile undertaking even if that did not lead to a complete, convenient, or coherent conception. But there is no need for pessimism. A clear and viable reformulation of that venerable distinction seems possible. It would bring out its essence and at the same time it would exceed mere historical interest. This paper aims at such a reformulation. In what follows, I offer an explanation of the central idea of independence in terms of non-inference and causal non-determination. Also, I point to the essential intentionality of the subjective and stress the central feature of intentional inexistence. In the course of this I shall use the most limited means only. Thus I hope to lay bare what the subjective-objective distinction comes down to, and I hope to do so in a manner acceptable on all sides. I close with some indications as to what such a reformulation may have a bearing on.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Seminar Spring 2019, Andy Egan Theories of Subjectivity Or: What Kind of Relativism Is Right for You? Course Descrip
    Metaphysics seminar Spring 2019, Andy Egan Theories of Subjectivity or: What Kind of Relativism is Right for You? Course Description There are a bunch of subject matters about which various people have, at various times, had an inclination to say something like, “Hey, that stuff’s not fully objective. It’s not part of reality as it is in itself. It’s something that we bring to reality, or at least it’s partly something we bring to reality. It’s in the eye of the beholder. It’s subjective!” How to cash out that kind of thought in a careful and precise way is really, really not straightforward. What we’ll be doing in this seminar is looking at a few different domains about which people have sometimes wanted to say such things (color, taste, and ethics), and at the different kinds of theoretical apparatus people have offered to try to cash the thought(s) out (various kinds of contextualism, various kinds of response-dependence, weird metaphysics, various kinds of relativism about mental and/or linguistic content, probably etc.). What I’m hoping to get from the seminar is a clearer picture of how all these different bits of theoretical apparatus relate to each other, what kind of phenomena or theoretical desiderata would properly motivate *some* kind of subjectivist-y thought or other, and what kind of phenomena or theoretical desiderata would properly motivate one, rather than another, theory of subjectivity. (So: how should we go about deciding, faced with some subject matter, whether to try and offer a subjective theory of it, what would
    [Show full text]
  • Concept of Freedom in the Philosophy of Fichte
    ISSN 2411-9563 (Print) European Journal of Social Sciences September-December 2014 ISSN 2312-8429 (Online) Education and Research Volume 1, Issue 2 CONCEPT OF FREEDOM IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF FICHTE Ermela Hoxha University of Elbasan, Faculty of Educational Sciences, Department of Civic Education, E-mail: [email protected], Albania, Tirana Abstract The concept of freedom is the central theme of all philosophy of Fichte. The study aims to determine the meaning of the concept of freedom by Johann Gottlieb Fichte. His fundamental philosophical problematic characterizes as "analysis of the notion of freedom". The methodology of this paper supported in a systematic review of the literature, description, comparison of different concepts and philosophical notions of the nineteenth century on freedom that coming as a result of different research as writings, works and articles. The main issues of the study relates to analysis of the subject as a creative activity, report subject to freedom and concept of freedom as a self-development. Problem that appears has to do with the subject which should be a self conscious that to create his freedom. The whole philosophy of Fichte relates to three main issues: the subject, the activity and freedom. His philosophy is defined as a philosophy of practice and freedom. The basic motive of subjective idealism is search of freedom according to which freedom is a field of opportunities that are offered to us in the world. The meaning of freedom is the form of expression that will, of individual action as something natural. Freedom is not absolute and an empirical given, but it should be a creativity.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Substance and Personalistic Subjectivity
    Aristotelian Substance and Personalistic Subjectivity Mark K. Spencer ABSTRACT: Many personalists have argued that an adequate account of the human person must include an account of subjectivity as irreducible to anything objectively definable. The personalists contend that Aristotle lacks such an account and claim that he fails to meet three criteria that a theory of the human person must fulfill in order to have an account of subjectiv- ity as irreducible. I show first that some later Aristotelians fulfill these criteria, and then that Aristotle himself also does so. He describes four characteristics of human subjectivity that are considered crucial by many personalists. I do this through an interpretation of Aristotle’s accounts of substantial actualities, nous, friendship, and beauty. N A SEMINAL ESSAY, Karol Wojtyła distinguishes two approaches to philo- Isophical anthropology. He calls one approach “objectivistic” and “cosmological.” When using this approach, one explains human beings and our actions using third- person terms, thereby treating us as objects of intentional cognitive acts. He calls the other approach “subjective” and “personalistic.” When using this approach, one explains human beings and our actions in first-person terms, that is, in terms of lived experience or “subjectivity,” thereby treating us as unique conscious subjects, “irreducible” to anything objectively observable or definable.1 In this paper I draw on both Wojtyła and other personalists as well as on some non-personalistic phenomenologists who have dealt with subjectivity in ways similar to the approach favored by the personalists. These thinkers hold that there are four characteristics of the human person that one must meet in order to satisfy the necessary conditions for having human subjectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger's Solution To
    SPANNING THE GAP: HEIDEGGER’S SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF TRANSCENDENCE AND HIS CRITIQUE OF MODERN SUBJECTIVITY A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY EMRAH GÜNOK IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY SEPTEMBER 2012 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Prof. Dr. Meliha ALTUNIŞIK Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Prof. Dr. Ahmet İNAM Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Assoc. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman Supervisor Examining Committee Members Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam (METU, PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Elif Çırakman (METU, PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Çetin Türkyılmaz (H. U., PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Ertuğrul R. Turan (A.U., PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, PHIL) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Emrah GÜNOK Signature : iii ABSTRACT SPANNING THE GAP: HEIDEGGER’S SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF TRANSCENDENCE AND HIS CRITIQUE OF MODERN SUBJECTIVITY GÜNOK, Emrah Ph.D., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Assoc. Prof. Dr. Elif ÇIRAKMAN September 2012, 330 pages This study aims at exhibiting the strong correlation between the question of subjectivity and the question of being.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Version: O'brien, LF (1996), 'Solipsism and Self-Reference'
    Final Version: O’Brien, L. F. (1996), ‘Solipsism and Self-Reference’, European Journal of Philosophy 4:175-194. Solipsism and Self-Reference ! I. Introduction In this paper I want to propose that we see solipsism as arising from certain problems we have about identifying ourselves as subjects in an objective world. The discussion will centre on Wittgenstein’s treatment of solipsism in his Tractatus Logico- Philosophicus. In that work Wittgenstein can be seen to express an unusually profound understanding of the problems faced in trying to give an account of how we, who are subjects, identify ourselves as objects in the world. We have in his compressed remarks, the kernels of a number of arguments which all come together to form what can be called the problem of self-identification. I want to argue that the solipsism of the Tractatus arises at least in part as a solution to, or – to put it less optimistically – as a symptom or articulation of this problem. In approaching Wittgenstein’s early discussion of solipsism in this way I will obviously be in disagreement with some other interpretations of the work. For example, there are those who think that there is no ‘solipsism of the Tractatus’.1 In fact, the Tractarian arguments presented below as motivating solipsism have been seen as fulfilling the quite opposite function of refuting it. I do not intend in this piece to engage with alternative interpretations. Let me say a little bit about why I have granted myself the licence not to do so. First, the focus of my concern with solipsism is on how it connects with what I have called the problem of self-identification.
    [Show full text]
  • Existentialism and Phenomenology
    PHIL 3142 EXISTENTIALISM AND PHENOMENOLOGY Class Number 46535 Section TR3 Tues, Thurs 3:40 – 4:55pm Instructor: Moris Stern Email: [email protected] We will take the 20TH Century philosophy of Phenomenology and Existentialism to do all of the following: to analyze, systematically reconstruct, diagnose, critically question and empower the late modern person, in view of that person’s individualistic self-conception. The late modern self understands itself to be subjectivity first, and, objectivity, if at all, second. In the more popular terms - the self is an individual first and everything else second. Existence is divided into the subjective and the objective, and the self identifies with the subjective first. To loosely paraphrase Sartre, modern human being chooses and makes himself to be what he is and empowers himself by in-depth understanding of this and owning up to it. Here are some of the questions the philosophy of Phenomenology and Existentialism raises and that will be of interest to us in our class. What does existence thus divided (subjective and objective) and systematized (subjective is superior to objective) look like? Is this division and hierarchization of existence inevitable? Are we, late moderns, always already engaged in it – even when we prioritize objectivity (by subjectively endowing objectivity with importance, as it were)? What are the unique challenges that this position raises for our relationship to ourselves, others, nature, God, death, love, sex, our daily activities, etc.? How does one emerge strengthened and empowered as a result of facing these challenges? Is there an attempt by such a one-sided subjectivity to balance itself out by objectivity – and what form do such attempts take? Can they be excessive? We will start with short selections from Descartes and Kant to establish the 16th-18th Century roots of the view that subjectivity, or consciousness, in its purity and independence of objectivity of the world, takes precedence in knowledge and ethics.
    [Show full text]