Spinoza on Emotion and Akrasia

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Spinoza on Emotion and Akrasia Christiaan Remmelzwaal SPINOZA ON EMOTION AND AKRASIA Doctoral dissertation defended on the 2nd of November 2015 at the University of Neuchâtel (Faculté des Lettres et Sciences Humaines, Institut de Philosophie) and accepted by the dissertation committee Prof. Richard Glauser (dissertation director) Prof. Daniel Garber Prof. Olli Koistinen Dr. Mogens Lærke Prof. Michael LeBuffe 2 3 4 5 6 Summary The objective of this doctoral dissertation is to interpret the explanation of akrasia that the Dutch philosopher Benedictus Spinoza (1632-1677) gives in his work The Ethics. One is said to act acratically when one intentionally performs an action that one judges to be worse than another action which one believes one might perform instead. In order to interpret Spinoza’s explanation of akrasia, a large part of this dissertation investigates Spinoza’s theory of emotion. The first chapter is introductory and outlines Spinoza’s categorisation of mental states and his conception of the relation between the mind and the body. The second chapter deals with Spinoza’s epistemology and the relation between cognitive mental states and states of the brain. The third chapter argues that Spinoza holds that emotions are non-cognitive mental states that are caused by cognitive mental states. The fourth chapter interprets Spinoza’s discussion of the emotions of Joy and Sadness insofar as they are mental states. The fifth chapter suggests that when Spinoza says that the power of our body is increased or decreased when we are joyful or sad, he means that when we are joyful or sad then, at the same time, our heart and perhaps the organs of our digestive system are affected in such a way that our bodily health is increased or decreased. The sixth chapter points to three problems that concern Spinoza’s definitions of the psychophysical states of pleasure, pain, cheerfulness and melancholy, and offers slightly altered definitions of these states. The seventh chapter interprets the various aspects of Spinoza’s conception of the emotion of Desire, both insofar as it is a state of the mind and insofar it is a state of the body, as well as the relation between the emotion of Desire and man’s striving for self-preservation. The eighth chapter discusses what Spinoza writes on the strength of emotions and the way in which we make value judgments in order to finally interpret why it is, according to Spinoza, that ‘we so often see the better for ourselves but follow the worse’. Key words: Spinoza, Emotion, Akrasia (l’Acrasie) 7 8 Contents Abbreviations and translations ............................................................................................. 13 Introduction ............................................................................................................................ 15 Chapter 1: The categories of mental states and the mind-body union .............................. 19 Section 1: The categories of mental states ............................................................................ 19 Section 2: The relation between the mind and the body ....................................................... 24 Chapter 2: Cognition ............................................................................................................. 33 Section 1: Inadequate ideas .................................................................................................. 33 Subsection 1: Sense perception .................................................................................... 34 Subsection 2: Recollection of sense perception ............................................................ 39 Subsection 3: Opinion .................................................................................................. 47 Section 2: Adequate ideas ..................................................................................................... 49 Subsection 1: Reason and intuitive knowledge ............................................................ 49 Subsection 2: Do our adequate ideas correspond to states of our body? .................... 54 Section 3: Judgements .......................................................................................................... 67 Chapter 3: The mental cause of emotion ............................................................................. 85 Section 1: Rejection of the cognitivist interpretation ........................................................... 85 Section 2: Bennett on cognition as the cause of emotion ..................................................... 96 Section 3: The distinction between ideas and emotions ....................................................... 98 Section 4: Emotions are caused by our ideas of things ...................................................... 102 Section 5: Why does Spinoza sometimes call passions mental images? ............................ 109 9 Chapter 4: The mental nature of Joy and Sadness ........................................................... 113 Section 1: Joy, Sadness and Desire are the only primary emotions ................................... 114 Section 2: Joy and Sadness are caused by our ideas of present, past, and future things. ... 116 Section 3: Love & Hate, Gladness & Regret, and Hope & Fear ........................................ 117 Section 4: Accidental causes of Joy and Sadness ............................................................... 131 Section 5: Indirect causes of Joy and Sadness .................................................................... 132 Section 6: Joy and Sadness caused by our ideas of persons ............................................... 134 Section 7: Several important secondary emotions that are kinds of Joy or Sadness .......... 140 Chapter 5: The bodily cause and nature of Joy and Sadness ........................................... 151 Section 1: The bodily nature of Joy and Sadness ............................................................... 152 Section 2: The fixed proportion of motion and rest ............................................................ 157 Section 3: The bodily cause of Joy and Sadness ................................................................ 158 Section 4: The mind’s perfection and power of thinking ................................................... 162 Chapter 6: Pleasure, Pain, Cheerfulness and Melancholy ............................................... 165 Section 1: A first problem concerning Spinoza’s definitions ............................................. 166 Section 2: A second problem concerning Spinoza’s definitions ........................................ 175 Section 3: A third problem concerning Spinoza’s definitions ............................................ 176 Section 4: Slightly altered definitions ................................................................................ 177 Section 5: These altered definitions work well within Spinoza’s moral theory ................. 178 Section 6: The importance of Health to a life in pursuit of knowledge .............................. 183 10 Chapter 7: The mental and bodily nature of Desire ......................................................... 189 Section 1: The mental cause and the mental nature of Desire ............................................ 190 Section 2: Bennett on teleological action ........................................................................... 204 Section 3: Desire qua bodily state ...................................................................................... 207 Section 4: Della Rocca and LeBuffe on the relation between Desire and the Conatus ...... 211 Section 5: The relation between Desire and the striving for self-preservation .................. 226 Subsection 5.1: We desire to imagine things our ideas of which affect us with Joy, and when we imagine something our idea of which affects us with Joy, then our bodily health increases. ......................................................................................................... 226 Subsection 5.2: Our desire to imagine the presence of a thing corresponds to our bodily action that has as goal that this thing will exist. Our desire to imagine the absence of a thing corresponds to our bodily action that has as goal that this thing will not exist. ...................................................................................................................... 231 Subsection 5.3: This emotional mechanism normally contributes to our self- preservation because it results in pleasure-seeking and pain-avoiding behaviour. .. 236 Section 6: The relation between the desire to act in such a way that the thing we love continues to exist and the desire to make the person we love joyful. ................................. 238 Chapter 8: Akrasia ............................................................................................................... 247 Section 1: Existing interpretations of Spinoza’s theory of akratic action .......................... 248 Section 2: The strength of Desire (Step 1) ......................................................................... 257 Section 3: Desire and action (Step 2) ................................................................................. 266 Section 4: Desire, value judgement and practical judgement (Step 3) ............................... 269 Section 5: Acting intentionally against our practical judgement ........................................ 275 Section 6: Acting intentionally against our rational practical judgement..........................
Recommended publications
  • Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (Ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016)
    Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016) Leibniz’s metaphysical views were not known to most of his correspondents, let alone to the larger public, until 1695 when he published an article in Journal des savants, titled in English “A New System of the Nature and Communication of Substances, and of the Union of the Soul and Body” (henceforth New System).1 The article raised quite a stir. Perhaps the most interesting and cunning critique of Leibniz’s views was provided by a French refugee in Rotterdam, Pierre Bayle (1647−1706) who is most famous for his Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (1697). The fascinating controversy on Leibniz’s idea of pre-established harmony and a number of other topics lasted for five years and ended only when Bayle died. In this paper I will give an overview of the communication, discuss in detail a central topic concerning spontaneity or a sudden change in the soul, and compare the views presented in the communication to Leibniz’s reflections in his partly concurrent New Essays on Human Understanding (1704) (henceforth NE). I will also reflect on whether the controversy could have ended in agreement if it would have continued longer. The New System Let us begin with the article that started the controversy, the New System. The article starts with Leibniz’s objection to the Cartesian doctrine of extension as a basic way of explaining motion. Instead, one should adopt a doctrine of force which belongs to the sphere of metaphysics (GP IV 478).
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
    The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Brains and Behavior Hilary Putnam
    2 Brains and Behavior Hilary Putnam Once upon a time there was a tough- ism appeared to exhaust the alternatives. minded philosopher who said, 'What is all Compromises were attempted ('double this talk about "minds", "ideas", and "sen- aspect' theories), but they never won sations"? Really-and I mean really in the many converts and practically no one real world-there is nothing to these so- found them intelligible. Then, in the mid- called "mental" events and entities but 1930s, a seeming third possibility was dis- certain processes in our all-too-material covered. This third possibility has been heads.' called logical behaviorism. To state the And once upon a time there was a nature of this third possibility briefly, it is philosopher who retorted, 'What a master- necessary to recall the treatment of the piece of confusion! Even if, say, pain were natural numbers (i.e. zero, one, two, perfectly correlated with any particular three ... ) in modern logic. Numbers are event in my brain (which I doubt) that identified with sets, in various ways, de- event would obviously have certain prop- pending on which authority one follows. erties-say, a certain numerical intensity For instance, Whitehead and Russell iden- measured in volts-which it would be tified zero with the set of all empty sets, senseless to ascribe to the feeling of pain. one with the set of all one-membered sets, Thus, it is two things that are correlated, two with the set of all two-membered not one-and to call two things one thing sets, three with the set of all three-mem- is worse than being mistaken; it is utter bered sets, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Alister Mcgrath's Anti-Mind-Body Dualism: Neuroscientific and Philosophical Quandaries for Christian Physicalism Brandon Rickabaugh* I
    TRINJ40NS (2019) 215-240 ALISTER MCGRATH'S ANTI-MIND-BODY DUALISM: NEUROSCIENTIFIC AND PHILOSOPHICAL QUANDARIES FOR CHRISTIAN PHYSICALISM BRANDON RICKABAUGH* I. INTRODUCTION Here is a staggering truth: the ontology of the human person currently embraced by the most vocal Christian scholars working on this issue is a view that almost no Christians thought plausible only 100 years ago. Until recently, the dominant view among Christian thinkers has been various forms of mind-body dualism (hereafter, dualism), according to which the human person comprises body and soul.1 In stark disagreement, many contemporary Christian scholars vigorously advance antidualism and defend physicalism (reductive or nonreductive), understanding the human person as fundamentally physical.2 These Christian physicalists proffer the strong impression of a uniform rejection of dualism across the neuroscientific, theological, and philosophical communities, as if dualism has been defeated, just as phlogiston was in in the 1770s. Here is another staggering truth: this certain-defeat-of-dualism narrative is demonstrably false. There is, in fact, a growing resurgence of dualism in philosophy. The recent Blackwell Companion Brandon Rickabaugh is a PhD candidate in the Department of Philosophy at Baylor University. This paper won the 2018-2019 Harold O. J. Brown Award for Student Scholarship. aSee Paul Gavarilyuk, "The Incorporeality of the Soul in Patristic Thought," in Christian Physicalism? Philosophical Theological Criticisms, ed. Keith Loftin and Joshua Farris (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2017), 1-26; and Thomas Atkinson, "Christian Physicalism: Against the Medieval Divines," in Loftin and Farris, Christian Physicalism?, 27-42. This isn't to say that dualism was the only view, as there is a tiny minority of Christian physicalists in the history of the church.
    [Show full text]
  • Vasubandhu's) Commentary on His "Twenty Stanzas" with Appended Glossary of Technical Terms
    AN INTRODUCTION AND TRANSLATION OF VINITADEVA'S EXPLANATION OF THE FIRST TEN VERSES OF (VASUBANDHU'S) COMMENTARY ON HIS "TWENTY STANZAS" WITH APPENDED GLOSSARY OF TECHNICAL TERMS Gregory Alexander Hillis Palo Alto, California B.A., University of California, Santa Cruz, 1979 A Thesis Presented to the Graduate Faculty of the University of Virginia in Candidacy for the Degree of Master of Arts Department of Religious Studies University of Virginia May, 1993 ABSTRACT In this thesis I argue that Vasubandhu categorically rejects the position that objects exist external to the mind. To support this interpretation, I engage in a close reading of Vasubandhu's Twenty Stanzas (Vif!lsatika, nyi shu pa), his autocommentary (vif!lsatika- vrtti, nyi shu pa'i 'grel pa), and Vinrtadeva's sub-commentary (prakaraiJa-vif!liaka-f'ika, rab tu byed pa nyi shu pa' i 'grel bshad). I endeavor to show how unambiguous statements in Vasubandhu's root text and autocommentary refuting the existence of external objects are further supported by Vinitadeva's explanantion. I examine two major streams of recent non-traditional scholarship on this topic, one that interprets Vasubandhu to be a realist, and one that interprets him to be an idealist. I argue strenuously against the former position, citing what I consider to be the questionable methodology of reading the thought of later thinkers such as Dignaga and Dharmak:Irti into the works of Vasubandhu, and argue in favor of the latter position with the stipulation that Vasubandhu does accept a plurality of separate minds, and he does not assert the existence of an Absolute Mind.
    [Show full text]
  • The Manifest Image and the Scientific Image(1)
    (1) The Manifest Image and the Scientific Image Bas C. van Fraassen Princeton University (published: pp. 29-52 in D. Aerts (ed.). Einstein Meets Magritte: The White Book -- An Interdisciplinary Reflection. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999.) PART ONE. WORLDVIEWS IN COLLISION (?) .................................... 2 1. The Clash ........................................................... 2 2. The three main differences between the Images ....................... 3 PART TWO. THE PLAGUE OF IRREMEDIABLE VAGUENESS .......................... 4 3. Deconstructing the Manifest Image ................................... 4 4. Deconstructing the Scientific Image ................................. 5 5. Philosophical choices in response ................................... 7 PART THREE. AN INCOHERENT FICTION ....................................... 8 6. The Images as philosophical miscreants .............................. 8 6.1 What is this thing called the Manifest Image? ................... 8 6.2 And what of that thing called the Scientific Image? ............. 9 6.3 The dialectic that engenders the dichotomy ...................... 9 7. The very idea of images .......................................... 10 PART FOUR. REAL LIFE WITH SCIENCE ..................................... 11 8. A new beginning .................................................... 12 9. The continuity of common sense and science in method ............... 13 10. Perspectival discourse and relativity ............................ 13 11. Value- and function-laden discourse .............................
    [Show full text]
  • The Scientific Evidence for Materialism About Pains Draft 2-4-13
    The Scientific Evidence For Materialism About Pains Draft 2-4-13 ABSTRACT (added 5-5-14) This paper argues in unprecedented empirical and philosophical detail that, given only what science has discovered about pain, we should prefer the materialist hypothesis that pains are purely material over the dualist hypothesis that they are immaterial. The empirical findings cited provide strong evidence for the thesis of empirical supervenience: that to every sort of introspectible change over time in pains, or variation among pains at a time, there corresponds in fact a certain sort of simultaneous neural change over time, or variation at a time. The empirical supervenience of pain on the neural is shown in turn to favor the hypothesis that pains are, in a sense that is made precise, purely material. I Philosophical discussions of the mind-body problem have often taken pain as their leading example of a phenomenally conscious mental state (see, e.g., Kripke 1980). In this paper, I discuss the implications for the mind-body problem of what science has to say about pain—and I aspire to do so in a way that is accessible to interested non-philosophers. 1 Science has clearly taught us much about the etiology of pain. It has taught us that there are several different types of specialized nociceptive neurons, distinct from tactile sensors and proprioceptors, that are sensitive to noxious stimuli of different kinds, e.g., to thermal, mechanical, or chemical stimuli (Price 1999, 76-79). It has taught us that bundles of these neurons run first to the spine, where they synapse with neurons that then run, along several distinct pathways, to various regions of the brain, some of which project further neurons to the cortex (Price 1999, 98-107).
    [Show full text]
  • Reflexive Monism
    Reflexive Monism Max Velmans, Goldsmiths, University of London; email [email protected]; http://www.goldsmiths.ac.uk/psychology/staff/velmans.php Journal of Consciousness Studies (2008), 15(2), 5-50. Abstract. Reflexive monism is, in essence, an ancient view of how consciousness relates to the material world that has, in recent decades, been resurrected in modern form. In this paper I discuss how some of its basic features differ from both dualism and variants of physicalist and functionalist reductionism, focusing on those aspects of the theory that challenge deeply rooted presuppositions in current Western thought. I pay particular attention to the ontological status and seeming “out- thereness” of the phenomenal world and to how the “phenomenal world” relates to the “physical world”, the “world itself”, and processing in the brain. In order to place the theory within the context of current thought and debate, I address questions that have been raised about reflexive monism in recent commentaries and also evaluate competing accounts of the same issues offered by “transparency theory” and by “biological naturalism”. I argue that, of the competing views on offer, reflexive monism most closely follows the contours of ordinary experience, the findings of science, and common sense. Key words: Consciousness, reflexive, monism, dualism, reductionism, physicalism, functionalism, transparency, biological naturalism, phenomenal world, physical world, world itself, universe itself, brain, perceptual projection, phenomenal space, measured space, physical space, space perception, information, virtual reality, hologram, phenomenological internalism, phenomenological externalism, first person, third person, complementary What is Reflexive Monism? Monism is the view that the universe, at the deepest level of analysis, is one thing, or composed of one fundamental kind of stuff.
    [Show full text]
  • The Curious Case of Baruch Spinoza in Walter Ben­Ja­Min’S “Toward the Critique of Violence”
    The Curious Case of Baruch Spinoza in Walter Ben ja min’s “Toward the Critique of Violence” MASSIMO PALMA abstract Although Baruch Spinoza was im por tant for think ers of his gen er a tion, Walter Ben ja­ min seems to have com pletely ig nored the phi los o pher. Spinoza’s name ap pears just a few times in Ben ja min’s works, and Spinoza’s thought never seems to have been rel e vant to him. The only place where Ben ja min quotes a text of Spinoza’s, al beit be tween the lines, is in “Toward the Critique of Violence” (1921). Still, in this essay Ben ja min is far from enthu si as tic about the au thor of the Ethics. He names Spinoza as a pro po nent of nat u ral law the o ry, which Ben ja min dismisses in his search for a cri te rion with which to judge Gewalt. This ar ti cle seeks to in ves ti gate Ben ja min’s ap par ent hos til ity to Spinoza and to reexamine the re la tion ship be tween the two, from both a the o ret i cal and a po lit i cal per spec tive. keywords Walter Ben ja min, Baruch Spinoza, le gal vi o lence, nat u ral law, mi gra tion The names of Walter Ben ja min and Baruch Spinoza rarely ap pear along side one an other in the lit er a ture on Ben ja min.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatic Model for Integrating Complementary and Alternative
    Jong et al., Primary Health Care 2016, 6:2 ealth y H Ca ar re : DOI: 10.4172/2167-1079.1000224 im O r p P e f n o A l c a c n e r s u s o J Primary Health Care: Open Access ISSN: 2167-1079 Research Article Open Access Pragmatic Model for Integrating Complementary and Alternative Medicine in Primary Care Management of Chronic Musculoskeletal Pain Miek C Jong1-3*, Martine Busch3,4, Lucy PL van de Vijver1, Mats Jong2, Jolanda Fritsma5 and Ruth Seldenrijk6 1Department Nutrition & Health, Louis Bolk Institute, Driebergen, Netherlands 2Department of Nursing Science, Mid Sweden University, Sundsvall, Sweden 3National Information and Knowledge Centre for Integrative Medicine (NIKIM), Netherlands 4Van Praag Institute, Utrecht, Netherlands 5Zorgbelang Groningen, Groningen, Netherlands 6Patiënten Platform Complementaire Gezondheidszorg, Netherlands Abstract Background: Integration of complementary and alternative medicine (CAM) into conventional care is driven by patients’ needs for holistic care. This study aimed to develop a model for integration of CAM into primary healthcare in close collaboration with patients suffering from chronic musculoskeletal pain (CMP). Methods: The study had a qualitative inductive approach following the principles of Grounded Theory, where data were collected and generated via several data sources and steps; individual and focus group interviews and meetings with patients, general practitioners (GPs), CAM practitioners, health insurers and other key informants. Results: Consensus was reached on a model in which shared decision making was introduced to facilitate discussions on CAM between patients and GPs. Guided by evidence and best-practices, GPs refer patients to one of five selected and reimbursed CAM therapies (acupuncture, homeopathy, naturopathy, osteopathy or Tai Chi) and respective practitioner within their integrative network.
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam Has Been One of the Most Influential Philosophers
    Putnam and Computational Functionalism For over half a century, Hilary Putnam has been one of the most influential philosophers. He started his career with several seminal papers in mathematical and philosophical logic. His further contributions, published in his numerous books, collections, and papers, span the philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of mind, psychology and language, metaphysics and epistemology, ethics and moral philosophy, practical philosophy, Jewish philosophy and more. Our focus here is on Putnam’s contributions in the philosophy of mind and psychology (though these are inevitably connected to his work in other domains). In this area, of mind and psychology, Putnam’s major impact relates to functionalism. In the 1960s Putnam promoted a central version of the view, known as computational, or machine, functionalism. The view gained immediate success. One reason why it became so attractive is that functionalism arguably does better as a theory than its two rival views at the time, logical behaviorism and reductive materialism (also known as type- identity theory). Another reason is that computational functionalism aligned with the new science of the mind at the time, namely cognitive science. In the 1980s, however, Putnam became a vocal critic of functionalism; his criticism motivated others to refine and modify the view, or to abandon it altogether. This chapter will focus on Putnam’s arguments for, and then against, functionalism. These arguments will be put in the wider context of the more general discussion about functionalism. We will start with an introduction to functionalism (part 1), then move to computational functionalism (part 2), and after that discuss Putnam’s main argument for the view (part 3).
    [Show full text]
  • The Refutation of Idealism Author(S): G
    Mind Association The Refutation of Idealism Author(s): G. E. Moore Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 12, No. 48 (Oct., 1903), pp. 433-453 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2248251 . Accessed: 30/03/2011 03:28 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind. http://www.jstor.org NEW SERIES. NO. 48.] [OCTOBER, 1903. MIND A QUARTERLY REVIEW OF PSYCHOLOGYAND PHILOSOPHY I.-THE REFUTATION OF IDEALISM.
    [Show full text]