Undisguised Influences’

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Undisguised Influences’ Notes Introduction: An ‘Untimely’ Political Thought for Serious Times 1. Deleuze 2005, p. 3. 2. HTH, II, Preface, 1. 1. The Twentieth-Century Politics of Contempt 1. ‘Le Pari de notre génération’, Interview in Demain (24–30 October 1957), English translation ‘The Wager of Our Generation’ (Camus 1961, pp. 169–75). 2. Dismissed ‘as an early modern polemical weapon for symbolically annihilat- ing cultural opponents’ (Woolfolk 1990, p. 105), sociologists have recently attempted to sketch a viable theory of ‘nihilism’, distinguishing two theo- retical approaches to this much contested notion: the first defines nihilism as the denial of ultimate transcendent foundations; the second approach, originating from Nietzsche’s work, traces nihilism in the Platonic–Christian dichotomy of sensory and supra-sensory Being (God, Truth), of immanence and transcendence, and in the devaluation of the immanent sphere of the phenomena as appearance and illusion. 3. Arendt refers to the three Marxian sentences ‘The philosophers have only interpreted the world differently; the point is, however, to change it’; ‘Labor created man’; ‘Violence is the midwife of every old society pregnant with a new one’ (Arendt 1993, p. 21). 4. See I, p. xix; Garfitt 2007, p. 27; Garfitt 1983, pp. 103–11. 5. Grenier published the essay ‘Le Nihilisme Européen et les Appels de l’Orient’ in two parts under the pseudonym of Jean Caves in Philosophies between March and May 1924 (Garfitt 2007, p. 34). 2. ‘Undisguised influences’ 1. ‘Rencontres avec André Gide’, in Hommage à André Gide (November 1951) in III, 881–5. 2. See Viggiani 1968; Arnold 1984, p. 123. 3. ‘La Philosophie du siècle’, Sud, n. 7 (June 1932), p. 144, in I, 543–5. 4. ‘Sur la musique’, Sud, n. 7 (June 1932), pp. 125–30, in I, 522–40. 5. Between 1931 and 1932, the NRF devotes a series of articles to Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, Dostoyevsky and Bergson; to Andler’s Nietzsche sa vie et sa pensée. VI. La Dernière philosophie de Nietzsche and Podach E.F. (1931) L’effondrement de Nietzsche (Paris: Gallimard) – both texts are listed in Camus’s private library (see Favre 2004, pp. 204–5) – and to Stefan Zweig’s Nietzsche. 6. According to Roger Grenier, in 1932 Camus paraphrases La Naissance de la tragédie, in particular the opposition of the Apollonian and the Dionysian’ 148 Notes 149 (in Le Ridier 1999, p. 143), but textual analysis confirms that the source of Camus’s commentary of the 1872 work is Nietzsche’s 1886 preface, which roots the desire for beauty in pain and the creation of the ‘God-artist’ in a liberation from pain through illusion, namely, in a ‘symbolised ecstasy’ that is opposed to reason’s moral interpretation of existence (‘Essay of self-criticism’, 4–5). The fact that Camus bases the Apollonian in the Dionysian is not due to an error on the part of the young student (Arnold 1984, pp. 126–7), but to the reading of the ‘Essay of Self-Criticism’, and, more precisely, to the inspiration he gets from the pages Nietzsche writes on the opposition between the pes- simism of the ‘Dionysian Greek’, creator of symbolic forms, and the optimism of (Socratic) withering logic; see Vattimo 2000, p. 158. 7. See Vattimo 2000, pp. 143–83. 8. Preface to the re-edition of Grenier’s Les Îles (1959). 9. As Deleuze notes, ‘Nietzsche was first introduced in France not by the ‘right’ but by Charles Andler and Henri Albert, who represented a whole socialist tradition with anarchical colourings’ (Deleuze 2004, p. 129.) The language and style of Albert’s translations especially contributed to Nietzsche’s success in French literary circles, confirming the image, dear to Gide and Valéry, of a writer and thinker that was opposed to the ‘professional philosopher’ (Le Ridier 1999, p. 61). In 1932, Gide is one of the ‘undisguised influences’ of Camus’s early writings and his favourite literary example (see Camus and Grenier 1981, p. 11). 10. A copy of the 1930 edition of Aurore, translated by Henri Albert (Paris: Mercure de France), that was underlined and annotated by Camus, is part of his private library collection (Favre 2004, p. 203). According to his friend and poet, Blanche Balaine, in the mid-1930s, Aurore was Camus’s favourite book by Nietzsche (Balaine 1999, p. 104). 11. A copy of the 1932 French edition of Lou Andréas-Salomé’s Nietzsche (Paris: Grasset) was listed in the catalogues of Camus’s private library until 1971 (Favre 2004, p. 204). 12. I respect the order proposed in the first volume of the new Pléiade edition of the complete works (Camus 2006), which differs from that proposed by Viallaneix (CAC2; Camus 1980). 13. According to the biographer, Nietzsche’s philosophical experience rejects all abstract systems and culminates in the ‘mystical apotheosis’ of the thinker (Andréas-Salomé 2002, p. 287). Camus’s emphasis on his mystical soul’s ‘fervour’ and ‘desire for superhuman communions’ (I, p. 941) suggests that he understands mysticism from the perspective of the Nietzschean theory of knowledge, in other words, as a liberation from rationalism. 14. The figure of the absurd comedian in Le Mythe de Sisyphe evokes the Nietzschean thinker portrayed by Andréas-Salomé (see Andréas-Salomé 2002, pp. 35, 39). 15. The striking affinity between the two figures in ‘Incertitudes’, the one who commands and the one who obeys, and the philosophical experience evo- ked in Andréas-Salomé’s biography of Nietzsche suggests that Camus uses this text to reflect his personal investigation (‘reveries’) in the thinker’s ‘tragic split’ that ‘transfigures’ the individual and allows him to conquer health through illness (Andréas-Salomé 2002, pp. 44–5). 16. The vigorous discipline of his ‘anarchy of instincts’ is the thinker’s way to ‘greatness’ (‘grandeur’) (in Andréas-Salomé 2002, p. 38). Exhortation to 150 Notes (self-)control was also spoken of by Jean Grenier to Camus (see Garfitt 2007, pp. 29–30). 17. In Ecce Homo, Nietzsche insists on the crucial role that illness plays in the gen- esis of his thought, which allows for ‘liberation’ and a ‘return to himself’ (EH, ‘Pourquoi j’écris de si bond livres’, ‘Humain, trop humain’, 4). In similar terms, Camus evokes tuberculosis as a ‘fortunate illness’, which marked the transition from the ‘happy barbarity’ (IV, p. 621) of his youth, which was absorbed by the sensual pleasures of the Algerian beaches, to the artist’s creative period, which was rooted in suffering and the tragic confrontation with a precocious death. 18. The image of the labyrinth recurs in Nietzsche’s Aurore (III, p. 169), also quoted in Andréas-Salomé 2002, p. 40. 19. Anticipating Le Mythe de Sisyphe, Camus renounces the accessibility of Truth without relinquishing his unquenchable desire for the ideal and the infinite (I, pp. 950–1). 20. Andler employs the notion of ‘intuitions sentimentales (sentimental intui- tions)’ to address the different phases of Nietzsche’s philosophy, whose criti- cism of rationalism is said to stem from a primitive ‘éclairage émotionnel’ (‘emotional light’) (Andler 1958b, pp. 14–15). Although it is not cited in the bibliography of ‘Sur la musique’, we cannot exclude that, in 1932, Camus read this book that devotes an extensive analysis to Nietzsche’s philosophy of tragedy. A copy of the 1921 edition of Le pessimisme esthétique de Nietzsche figures in the inventories of Camus’s private library, along with the other five volumes of Charles Andler’s Nietzsche, sa vie et sa pensée (Paris: Gallimard) (see Favre 2004, p. 204). 21. Camus’s pages on the anthropomorphic character of thinking in Le Mythe de Sisyphe are reminiscent of Andler’s emphasis on the schemes or value judge- ments by means of which men impress their seal of order and reason upon reality. 22. It is not possible to say whether Camus read Nietzsche’s Zarathustra in 1932 or not; the book does not figure in Arnold’s inventory (1979), while Favre (2004) refers to a copy of the 1942 French edition of Ainsi parlait Zarathoustra translated by M. Betz (Paris: Gallimard). Nonetheless, there are reasons to believe that even in the early 1930s Camus was acquainted with the text of Zarathustra through his teacher, Jean Grenier. The island is also a recurring theme in the writings of Grenier, whose ‘Îles Kerguélen’ (‘The Kerguelen Islands’) was published in NRF in May 1931. At the time Camus was completing his ‘reveries’, Grenier was working on ‘Les Îles Fortunées’ (‘The Fortunate Isles’), then on ‘L’Île de Pâques’ (‘The Easter Island’). In 1933, Grenier published Les Îles (Islands), which was to have a great influence on Camus (IV, pp. 621–24). As Garfitt observes, ‘for Grenier, the island is a place of inevitable confrontation with the self, in the absence of all other distrac- tions, and is therefore in its essence metaphysical. One is confronted with the truest image of oneself, and it is that experience that can then release one’s inner song [...]. There is a genuine desire to understand (on the part of Camus), a sense of almost surprised recognition, and at the same time a fair amount of resistance to Grenier’s line of thought, which is strongly influenced by Indian philosophy and is constantly pulling away from the human, relegating it to the periphery. Camus is struggling with Grenier’s essentially metaphysical and potentially antisocial approach, and wanting Notes 151 to assert the possibility of a definitive commitment to the values of the here-and-now’ (Garfitt 2007, pp. 31–2). I suggest that Nietzsche provided the arguments for the assertion of such commitment in Camus’s early writings. 23. EH, ‘Pourquoi j’écris de si bons livres’ – ‘La Naissance de la tragédie’, 2.
Recommended publications
  • A Critical Assessment of the Political Doctrines of Michael Oakeshott
    David Richard Hexter Thesis Title: A Critical Assessment of the Political Doctrines of Michael Oakeshott. Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. 1 Statement of Originality I, David Richard Hexter, confirm that the research included within this thesis is my own work or that where it has been carried out in collaboration with, or supported by others, that this is duly acknowledged and my contribution indicated. I attest that I have exercised reasonable care to ensure that the work is original, and does not to the best of my knowledge break any UK law, infringe any third party’s copyright or other Intellectual Property Right, or contain any confidential material. I accept that the college has the right to use plagiarism detection software to check the electronic version of the thesis. I confirm that this thesis has not been previously submitted for the award of a degree by this or any other university. The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without the prior written consent of the author. David R Hexter 12/01/2016 2 Abstract Author: David Hexter, PhD candidate Title of thesis: A Critical Assessment of the Political Doctrines of Michael Oakeshott Description The thesis consists of an Introduction, four Chapters and a Conclusion. In the Introduction some of the interpretations that have been offered of Oakeshott’s political writings are discussed. The key issue of interpretation is whether Oakeshott is best considered as a disinterested philosopher, as he claimed, or as promoting an ideology or doctrine, albeit elliptically.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Camus' Dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected]
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2014 Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Illing, Sean Derek, "Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky" (2014). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 1393. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/1393 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. BETWEEN NIHILISM AND TRANSCENDENCE: ALBERT CAMUS’ DIALOGUE WITH NIETZSCHE AND DOSTOEVSKY A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Sean D. Illing B.A., Louisiana State University, 2007 M.A., University of West Florida, 2009 May 2014 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation is the product of many supportive individuals. I am especially grateful for Dr. Cecil Eubank’s guidance. As a teacher, one can do no better than Professor Eubanks. Although his Socratic glare can be terrifying, there is always love and wisdom in his instruction. It is no exaggeration to say that this work would not exist without his support. At every step, he helped me along as I struggled to articulate my thoughts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hegemony of Reason and the Assimilation of Comic Folly
    In Praise of Folly: The Hegemony of Reason and the Assimilation of Comic Folly James Mark Shields ©1990 (revised 2007) ABSTRACT According to Michel Foucault, one aspect of discourse control is the principle of “exclusion,” which may take the form of what Foucault calls “division and rejection”—where discourses are categorized so as to reduce the significance of some categories. As an example, Foucault produces the opposition of reason and folly, a division investigated in greater detail in his Madness and Civilization. In this latter work, however, Foucault speaks primarily of the Fool as a socially categorized individual; one who, through the course of history and changing discursive habits, has become the Madman. The Fool/Madman character and the issue of insanity are not by any means exhaustive of the broad and often convoluted concept of folly. To take a strict denotative approach, folly has various meanings, all of which focus to some degree on “unreason” or “anti-reason.” Cultural limits have been established, and these limits can be investigated through an analysis of one particular form of folly, that which I will call comic folly—that side of folly dealing with mirth, humor, laughter, and the joke. In this essay, the following matters are explored: the concept of folly, its various facets and history; comic folly as a branch of unreason; the hegemony, power, and limits of reason in modern Western culture; the comic folly of the so-called rational/sane person; and the strengths and limits of comic folly within our Rational Western world. Must unreason, as Webster’s seems to suggest, always end in disaster? I am uneasy to think I approve of one object, and disapprove The danger lurks precisely because there are limits to of another; call one thing beautiful, and another deform’d; folly, and these limits have been systematically engrained decide concerning truth and falsehood, reason and folly, within modern “rational discourse.” The hegemony of Reason without knowing upon which principles I proceed.
    [Show full text]
  • The Commodification of French Intellectual Culture, 1945-1990
    From Ideas to Icons: The Commodification of French Intellectual Culture, 1945-1990 By Hunter K. Martin A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (History) at the UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN-MADISON 2012 Date of final oral examination: August 9, 2012 The dissertation is approved by the following members of the Final Oral Committee: Laird Boswell, Professor, History Mary Louise Roberts, Professor, History Suzanne Desan, Professor, History Jennifer Ratner-Rosenhagen, Professor, History Richard Staley, Professor, History of Science © Copyright by Hunter K. Martin 2012 All Rights Reserved i Table of Contents Abbreviations ii Tables and Illustrations iii Introduction Commodification: A New Concept for the History of Intellectual Culture 1 Part I From Inspiration to Implantation: The Origins of Maisons de la Culture 24 Chapter 1 Local Cultural Centers and the “Great Intellectual Struggle of Our Time” 24 Chapter 2 The Commercialization of Maisons de la Culture in Paris and Grenoble 65 Part II Off the Page and onto the Stage: The Making and Marketing of Intellectual Culture at Maisons de la Culture 106 Chapter 3 A Considerable Track Record: Encounters with Intellectual Culture in Paris and Grenoble 106 Chapter 4 Maisons de la Culture and the Creation of Demand 141 Part III Appropriations and Parallel Evolutions 174 Chapter 5 Out with the Old, in with the Pompidou 174 Chapter 6 A Virtuous Cycle: Intellectual Culture on Television and in Journals 207 Conclusion Intellectual “Engagement”
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Way of Life As Contemporary Moral Ontology
    UDC 111,177,141.5 Вестник СПбГу. Философия и конфликтология. 2017. т. 33. Вып. 3 S. V. Nikonenko1 THE ARISTOTELIAN WAY OF LIFE AS CONTEMPORARY MORAL ONTOLOGY The matter of the article is the study of the concept Aristotelian way of life as the concept of contem- porary moral ontology. Several moral philosophers are considered: A. Flew, B. Williams, A. Macintyre, S. Hampshire, J. L. Mackie, R. M. Hare, etc. According to Flew, moral rationality is only the capacity to act and to be responsible in moral way. Moral rationality does not define the essence of moral acts. Williams treats Aristotle as a moral anti-realist. Macintyre proposes practical rationality, unlike the “theoretical” one, that depends on actions and not only on thoughts. Macintyre thinks that practical rationality is changeable in history. He calls the stage of practical rationality a tradition. S. Hampshire’s criticism of Aristotelian way of life is considered. He thinks that Aristotle is a founder of moral sub- stantialism. The Aristotelian way of life is an ethics of individual perception. Ethical virtues must be conscious, but they are not rational in metaphysical sense. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics is studied in the article. There are three main ideas of Aristotle that have been influenced the analytical moral phi- losophy: 1. The unity of all the virtues; 2. The practical character of morality; 3. The freedom of indi- vidual will. Aristotle taken in the mirror of analytic moral philosophy is an adept of practical thinking, incompatible with moral rationalism and substantialism. There are main characteristic features of the Aristotelian way of life: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • To Download the PDF File
    The Leviathan and the Contours of Conservative Imagination: The Role of Thomas Hobbes in the Works of Schmitt, Strauss and Oakeshott By R. Omur Birler, MA A thesis submitted to The Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy Department of Political Science Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario Canada © by R. Omur Birler, 2007 Library and Bibliotheque et 1*1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A0N4 Ottawa ON K1A0N4 Canada Canada Your file Votre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-36777-3 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-36777-3 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par Nnternet, preter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans loan, distribute and sell theses le monde, a des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, electronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protege cette these. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la these ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent etre imprimes ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Arthur Schopenhauer – Bergsonian Intuitionism Forerunner
    ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER – BERGSONIAN INTUITIONISM FORERUNNER Gabriela Pohoaţă [email protected] Abstract: Our article discusses the kinship of two thinkers of reference in the universal philosophical landscape, who lived in different eras and belonged to emblematic cultures for European philosophy. Both philosophers analyse intuition, but each understands something different by it and relate differently to it, from the perspective of their own systems of thought. Nevertheless, in the view of both thinkers neither reason, nor intelligence is paramount, but intuition - both seeing in it a wonderful process by which we understand our essence, and the essence of the universe. We find this approach particularly interesting and of great significance to contemporary philosophical research, and for the contemporary man obsessed with the intellect, intuition may be a chance of rescue. Keywords: will to live, thing-in-itself, metaphysics, intuition, the vital drive, intuitionism, voluntarism. 1. Among the great modern thinkers who are representative for what was called postkantian "German idealism", but also for the turn towards postmodernism, there is Arthur Schopenhauer. Born in Danzig (Gdansk) on February the 22nd, 1788 and dead on September the 21st, 1860 in Frankfurt a. Main, where he lived after finishing his short teaching activity (carried out, with some interruptions, in Berlin between 1820-1832), Arthur Schopenhauer remains one of the most influential modern philosophers, an active presence not only in philosophical thinking, but also in romantic and postromantic poetic creation. Recognized studies drew a more nuanced attention on Schopenhauer's role and effect of thought: it is essentially "a new realization of the metaphysical intention of productive philosophizing (philosophieren).
    [Show full text]
  • Søren Kierkegaard Reflected in Indian Philosophy
    Sincronía ISSN: 1562-384X [email protected] Universidad de Guadalajara México Søren Kierkegaard reflected in Indian philosophy. Hajko, Dalimír Søren Kierkegaard reflected in Indian philosophy. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=513852378037 This work is licensed under Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. PDF generated from XML JATS4R by Redalyc Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Filosofía Søren Kierkegaard reflected in Indian philosophy. Dalimír Hajko [email protected] Constantine the Philosopher University in Nitra, Eslovaquia Abstract: Analysis of the postulates of Kierkegaard in the Indian world. Transcendence and breaking of boundaries are approached from a critical analysis based on the conceptualization of existentialism, knowing their contribution in the context of the Upanishads, Vedantas, Neo-Vedantas, as well as their western influence in a non- Western scenario. Keywords: Kierkegaard, Hindu philosophy, Existentialism. Resumen: Análisis de los postulados de Kierkegaard en el mundo índico. La trascendencia y rompimiento de las fronteras son abordadas desde un análisis crítico partiendo de la conceptualización del existencialismo, conociendo su aportación en el Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 contexto de los Upanishads, Vedantas, Neo-Vedantas, así como su influencia occidental en un escenario no occidental. Universidad de Guadalajara, México Palabras clave: Kierkegaard, Filosofía hindú, Existencialismo. Received:
    [Show full text]
  • (Mars 1959), P. 94. %% This Merely Includes Zazie Dans Le Métro in a List with the Comment "Humour Très Leste Et Écriture Insolite." Anonymous
    Anonymous. "Vous devriez avoir lu." Réalités (Paris), vol. * #158 (mars 1959), p. 94. %% This merely includes Zazie dans le métro in a list with the comment "humour très leste et écriture insolite." Anonymous. "Vous devriez avoir lu." Réalités (Paris), vol. * #159 (avril 1959), p. 98. %% This merely includes Zazie dans le métro in a list with the comment "humour très leste et insolite de Raymond Queneau." Anonymous. "Vous ne verrez peut-être jamais 'Le (sic) Couple' de Raymond Queneau." Paris- presse (Paris), an. * #4924 (9 octobre 1960), p. 11. %% The author explains how "Un Couple" had been subjected to an age limit by the censors but that even then the owners of movie houses were not interested in showing the film. Anonymous. "Les Vrais Représentants de la pensée française demandent le châtiment des écri- vains qui vendirent leur plume à l'ennemi." Front national (Paris), an. 1 #14 (5 septembre 1944), p. 2. %% This is a statement from the CNE with two motions and a list of mem- bers, including Queneau. Anonymous. "Vu, lu, su." L'Express (Paris), vol. * #393 (24 décembre 1958), p. 31. %% This is one of the very earliest announcements of Zazie dans le métro . Anonymous. "Wehmütige Liebe." Die Weltwoche (Zürich), an. 44 #5 (4 février 1976), p. 12. %% This is a review of Ein Winter in Le Havre , Eugen Helmlé's translation of Un Rude Hiver . Anonymous. "Welcome to Le Havre." Times Literary Supplement (London), an. * #3887 (10 september 1976), p. 1114. %% This positive review of Richard Cobb's 1976 Zaharoff lecture, Raymond Queneau , doesn't say anything much.
    [Show full text]
  • A Criticism of Edmund Burke's Conception of Patriotism*
    A Criticism of Edmund Burke’s Conception of Patriotism* Juan Espíndola Instituto de Investigaciones Sociales, UNAM [email protected] Abstract This paper draws on scholarship examining Edmund Burke’s emotionalism in order to conceptualize his understand- ing of patriotism, and to understand how it hangs together with other dimensions of his political and aesthetic thought. More substantively, the paper takes the further step of engaging with recent accounts of patriotism in order to criticize Burke’s patrio- tism. According to sympathetic views of Burke’s patriotism, and the theory of emotions that underlies it, the latter has resourc- es to ground a cosmopolitanism of a particular kind. The paper contests these views by highlighting the affinities of Burkean patriotism to some objectionable forms of patriotism, such as Alasdair MacIntyre’s version of it, and its incompatibility with less objectionable forms, such as Jürgen Habermas’s. Key words: Edmund Burke, patriotism, emotions, Jürgen Habermas. Resumen Este artículo se apoya en la literatura sobre el papel de las emociones en la filosofía de Edmund Burke para caracterizar su concepción del patriotismo, y para entender cómo se relaciona con otras dimensiones de su pensamiento político y estético. Más importante aún, el artículo rechaza la idea de que el patriotismo Recibido: 26 - 09 - 2013. Aceptado: 05 - 12 - 2013. *Becario del Programa de Becas Posdoctorales en la UNAM, Instituto de Investigaciones Sociales, UNAM. El autor agradece el apoyo de la Coordinación de Humanidades de la Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México. Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía 46 (2014), 121-149 122 Juan Espíndola Burkeano (y su anclaje en una teoría particular de las emociones) sirva como base para articular una visión cosmopolita de la política.
    [Show full text]
  • Shadworth Hodgson and the Psychology of William James: Experience, Teleology and Realism
    University of New Hampshire University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository Doctoral Dissertations Student Scholarship Winter 1978 SHADWORTH HODGSON AND THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WILLIAM JAMES: EXPERIENCE, TELEOLOGY AND REALISM RICHARD PAUL HIGH Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.unh.edu/dissertation Recommended Citation HIGH, RICHARD PAUL, "SHADWORTH HODGSON AND THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WILLIAM JAMES: EXPERIENCE, TELEOLOGY AND REALISM" (1978). Doctoral Dissertations. 1220. https://scholars.unh.edu/dissertation/1220 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This was produced from a copy of a document sent to us for microfilming. While the most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this document have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the material submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you understand markings or notations which may appear on this reproduction. 1.The sign or “target” for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is “Missing Page(s)”. If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting through an image and duplicating adjacent pages to assure you of complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a round black mark it is an indication that the film inspector noticed either blurred copy because of movement during exposure, or duplicate copy.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflections of Kierkegaard in Indian Philosophy an Introduction
    European Journal of Science and Theology, February 2017, Vol.13, No.1, 69-78 _______________________________________________________________________ REFLECTIONS OF KIERKEGAARD IN INDIAN PHILOSOPHY AN INTRODUCTION Dalimír Hajko* University of Žilina in Žilina, Faculty of Humanities, Univerzitná 1, 010 26 Žilina, Slovak Republic (Received 29 September 2016) Abstract The ideas of Søren Kierkegaard have attracted the interest of a broad spectrum of creators of modern Indian culture. In the first place, it was the admirers of existentialism who diligently sought reasons to justify a legitimate place for existential thought in the new context of Indian thinking. They were followed by thinkers who categorically refused existentialism, criticizing it from various points of view. There have also been philosophers, who tried to evaluate the function of existentialism objectively and scientifically in a very sober way, first in connection to the traditional attitudes of Indian philosophers and religious thinkers and secondly in connection to the evident presence of existentialism in the context of Indian philosophy in the 20th century. Keywords: Soren Kierkegaard, existentialism, India, philosophy 1. Introduction Was Kierkegaard uniquely European? Could his philosophical and theological opinions be understood as the views and statements of a genuine citizen of Europe that could not have appeared on the other continents? Does his work contain concepts that are hard to understand or to translate into the languages of other cultures? Can we find the beginning and the end of the intellectual legacy of Søren Kierkegaard only in a European cultural environment? Did his ideas have universal character? Is the spiritual influence of his ideas widely accepted in the sense of the worldwide global perspective influencing the culture in the whole world? Could it be that by emphasizing the absolute European nature of the spiritual legacy of Søren Kierkegaard, one of the Eurocentric myths is supported? Kierkegaard did not deal with oriental culture.
    [Show full text]