Philo of Alexandria Vs. Descartes 13

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philo of Alexandria Vs. Descartes 13 Carlos Lévy Philo of Alexandria vs.Descartes: An Ignored JewishPremonitoryCritic of the Cogito The starting-point of this paper is adouble statement of fact.First,inthe transmis- sion of the sorts of tablets of the sceptic lawthat are the tropes of Aenesidemus, our initial witness is neither aphilosopher in the narrow sense, nor adoxographer,nor an encyclopaedist,but someone who was and remains an atypical character in the world of philosophy: aJew born in Alexandria, raised in the paideia,who never abandoned the principles of his faith. Philo thoughtthat there could exist akind of complex compatibility between the Jewish Torahand Greek philosophy. Nowa- days,scholars generallydismiss the Philonian version of the tropes.¹ In my opin- ion—but it seems that Iamalmostthe onlyone to think so currently—it is an error,since Philo was, from achronological, geographical, historical, and linguistic point of view,the closest to Aenesidemus. H. vonArnim expressedthe same opinion at the beginning of the twentieth century that was, but it was shaken by Janáček’s(to my mind) unconvincing criticism, whose authority playedanimportant role in de- valuing Philo’sversion of the tropes.² Certainlytherewould be much to sayabout this question, but the main fact is thatPhilo, who livedinacity brimming with phi- losophers, quicklyidentified Aenesidemus’stropes as something very important to his own reflections on Jewish law. On this matter,thereisasharp contrast between the attitudes of Ciceroand Philo. Cicerowas himself adisciple of the sceptic Academyand agood friend of Tu- bero, to whom Aenesidemus dedicated his Pyrrhonian books, yetCiceronever men- tions Aenesidemus.³ In his opinion the tradition of doubt was represented by the AcademyofArcesilaus and Carneades. Scepticism, aterm that had no precise equiv- alent in his vocabulary,was for Ciceroessentiallyanaspect of Platonism. UnlikeAe- On this question, see Carlos Lévy, “Philon d’Alexandrie est-il inutilisable pour connaître Éné- sidème? Étude méthodologique,” Philosophie antique 15 (2015): 7‒26. Hans vonArnim, Quellenstudien zu Philo von Alexandria (Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1889); KarelJanáček, “Philon vonAlexandreia und skeptische Tropen,” Eirene (1982):83‒97. Photius says that Aenesidemus’sbook was dedicated to Lucius Tubero, who was his sunairesiōtēs (“classmate”)inthe Academy. This Tuberoiscommonlyidentified with Lucius Aelius Tubero, who was alegateofQuintus Cicero duringhis pro-consulate in Asiafrom63to58BCE. On Tubero, see John Glucker, Antiochus and the Late Academy (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck &Ruprecht,1978), 118. On the debateabout the Academic identity of Aenesidemus,see the contradictory positions of Fernanda DeclevaCaizzi, “Aenesidemus and the Academy,” Classical Quarterly 42 (1992):176‒89,who denies that Aenesidemus was astudent in the Academy, and Jaap Mansfeld, “Aenesidemus and the Academ- ics,” in Thepassionate intellect. Essaysonthe transformation of Classical Literature, ed. Lewis Ayres (New Brunswick-London: Transactions, 1996), 235‒48, whoaffirmsthat he was. OpenAccess. ©2019 Carlos Lévy,published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110591040-002 6 Carlos Lévy nesidemus, he never intended to removescepticism from the familyofthe Socratic doctrines. Forhim Pyrrho was adogmatic indifferentist.⁴ Further in this paper,inacomparative perspective,weshall deal with Augus- tine’sintellectual and spiritual itinerary.Itiswell-known that,after avery long and complex evolution, he had an illumination in the garden of Milan, in July 386.Itwas acrucial moment for his conversion.⁵ One could think that,atthis time of his life, he would have isolated himself in order to write some fresh theolog- ical meditation. But it was not the case. He retired with his mother and some friends in Cassiciacum, in order to tackle agreat number of philosophicalthemes, the first of which was the refutation of the New Academy.Thisseems even stranger as in Con- fessions 5.25,⁶ when he speaks about his own sceptical crisis (in 384‒85), he seems to consider it as aminor episode, in the context of his liberation from along-lasting Manichaean influence. In the case of Augustine, as in thatofPhilo, dealingwith scepticism seems to have been more thananintellectual challenge, but an actual kind of emergency. Hereagain, the contrast with Ciceroistelling. Cicerowrote his Academica when he was sixty,anage roughlyequivalent to today’seighty,given differences in life ex- pectancy.One would perhaps object that the link between Philo and Augustine is mere coincidence. But the paradoxical relation between faith and scepticism is a line which runs through the history of Western thought.The namesofMontaigne and Pascal can be mentioned here, among so many others, as carefullystudied by Charles Schmitt.⁷ The presenceofthis relation, however,does not meanthat it would be unidimensional. By exploring the cases of Philo and Augustine, we will try to determine what,ifanything,they have in common. In principle, thingslook quite simple; Philo adopts and adapts the tropes of Ae- nesidemus, while Augustine wants to triumph over the scepticism of the New Acad- emy. In fact,this contrast between the former,who seems to feel some attraction to- wards scepticism, and the latter,who treats it as an adversary,isfallacious. In both See Carlos Lévy, “Un problème doxographique chez Cicéron, les indifférentistes,” Revue des Études Latines 58 (1980): 238‒51. On the Augustinian intellectual and spiritual itinerary,see Peter Brown, Augustine of Hippo:ABi- ography,rev.ed. (Berkeley:University of CaliforniaPress,2000). Augustine, Confessions 5.25: “Accordingly,after the manner of the Academics,aspopularlyunder- stood, Idoubted everything, and in the fluctuatingstateoftotal suspense of judgement Idecided I must leave the Manichees, thinkingatthat period of my scepticism that Ishould not remainamem- ber of asect to which Iwas now preferringcertain philosophers. But to these philosophers, whowere without Christ’ssavingname, Ialtogether refused to entrust the healingofmysoul’ssickness” (ita- que Academicorum more, sicut existimantur,dubitans de omnibus atque inter omnia fluctuans, mani- chaeos quidem relinquendos esse decrevi, non arbitrans eo ipso temporedubitationis meae in illa secta mihi permanendum esse cui iam nonnullos philosophos praeponebam. quibus tamen philosophis,quod sine salutari nomine Christi essent, curationem languoris animae meae committereomnino recusabam). Henry Chadwick, trans., Saint Augustine: Confessions (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press, 1991). Charles B. Schmitt, Cicero Scepticus (Leiden: Brill, 1972). Philo of Alexandria vs.Descartes 7 cases, thingsare far morecomplex. In the background of both cases is aquestion to which Descartesgaveananswer he considered to be definitive:isthere something that Ican know with absolute certainty?Iwill try to demonstrate that Philo had fore- seen and refuted the Cartesian solution, while Augustine in acertain sense anticipat- ed it. 1Prolegomena Before dealing with Philo, Iwillsay something about the pagan attitude towards re- ligion, and more specificallythat of the Hellenistic schools. In the Pyrrhonian tradi- tion, passive observance of the religious tradition of the city is recommended in order to avoid the disturbance of religious dissension.⁸ We find something quiteopposite to this indifferentism in Cicero’streatise On the Natureofthe Gods (De naturadeorum). The main purpose of this treatise, in the tradition of the New Academy,istodemon- strate that the dogmatic explanations of the natureofthe gods offered by Stoics and Epicureans weredisappointingand contradictory.Ishall not insist on the arguments used by Cotta against his dogmatic adversaries, since they have been explored at length.⁹ HereIprefer to evoke apassageofthe third book, rarelyanalysed in com- mentariesonthis treatise.Atsections 11‒12 of the third book, Cotta, the exponent of the Academic refutation of Stoicism, refuses to grant that gods or dead heroes could appear among mortals and be seen in some exceptional occasions,let us sayinmiracles. He adds that he prefers to believesomething more probable, namely that the souls of the great men are divine and immortal.¹⁰ In the case of Cotta, the See Carlos Lévy, “La question du pouvoir dans le pyrrhonisme,” in Fondements et crises du pouvoir, eds.Sylvie Franchet d’Esperey,Valérie Fromentin, Sophie Gotteland, and Jean-Michel Roddaz (Bor- deaux: Ausonius,2003), 47‒56;RichardBett, Pyrrho:his Antecedents and his Legacy (Oxford: Oxford University Press,2000), esp. chap. 2; Emidio Spinelli, “Sextus Empiricus,l’expérience sceptique et l’horizon de l’éthique,” Cahiers philosophiques 115,no. 3(2008): 29‒45. See Daniel Babut, La religion des philosophes grecs,2nd ed. (Paris:Les Belles Lettres,2019); Jean- Louis Girard, “Probabilisme, théologie et religion: le cataloguedes dieux homonymes dans le De na- turadeorum de Cicéron (3,42et53‒60),” in Hommages àR.Schilling,eds.Hubert Zehnacker and Gus- tave Hentz (Paris:Les Belles Lettres,1983), 117‒26;JaapMansfeld, “Aspects of Epicurean Theology,” Mnemosyne 46 (1993): 172‒210; JordiPia, “De la Naturedes dieux de Cicéron àl’abrégédeCornutus: une nouvelle représentation des élites dans la réflexion théologique,” Camenae 10 (February 2012), http://saprat.ephe.sorbonne.fr/media/282f1da6517e2ba6025880dd887c8682/camenae-10-varia-jordi- pia-derniere.pdf. Cicero, De Naturadeorum 3.12: “Would younot prefer to believethe perfectlycredible
Recommended publications
  • Plato, Philo, and the Author of Hebrews
    Plato, Philo, and the Author of Hebrews BY JAMES H. BURTNESS INCE the first centuries of the Christian church, there have been serious ques­ S tions concerning the origin of the Epistle to the Hebrews. It is primarily to the modern period, however, that we owe the view that the author of this epistle was deeply influenced by Platone idealism and by the philosophy of the Alexandrian School, particularly the writings of Philo. Hugo Grotius was perhaps the first, in 1644, to point out the close connection between Philo and Hebrews 4:10. In 1750, Carpzov published a volume of Sacrae Exercitationes in S. Paulli Epistolam ad Hebraeos ex Philone Alexandrine. J. J. Wettstein, in his Novum Testamentum Graecum of 1752, also pointed out these parallels. The rationalistic critics of the nineteenth century saw Alexandrianism written all over the epistle. Baur regarded it as a Judeo-Christian product inter­ mixed with Paulinism and spiritualized by an Alexandrian mentality. Ménégoz, in his La Theologie de L'Epitre aux Hébreux of 1894, concluded that the author was a Philonian converted to Christianity. At the end of the last century the de­ pendence of the epistle upon the religious philosophy of Philo was considered to be a secured result of literary criticism. Typical of this period are the following statements by Pfleiderer and von Soden: The Hellenistic basis of the Epistle to the Hebrews, its dependence in thought and word upon the Book of Wisdom, and especially upon Philo, is so obvious that there is not the smallest room for doubt upon the matter.1 It marks the definite entrance of Alexandrianism into the sphere of Christianity.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Supreme Principle of Morality'? in the Preface to His Best
    The Supreme Principle of Morality Allen W. Wood 1. What is ‘The Supreme Principle of Morality’? In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle of morality, which is the intended outcome of the search. It will consider this formulation in light of Kant’s conception of the historical antecedents of his attempt. Our first task, however, must be to say a little about the meaning of the term ‘supreme principle of morality’. For it is not nearly as evident to many as it was to Kant that there is such a thing at all. And it is extremely common for people, whatever position they may take on this issue, to misunderstand what a ‘supreme principle of morality’ is, what it is for, and what role it is supposed to play in moral theorizing and moral reasoning. Kant never directly presents any argument that there must be such a principle, but he does articulate several considerations that would seem to justify supposing that there is. Kant holds that moral questions are to be decided by reason. Reason, according to Kant, always seeks unity under principles, and ultimately, systematic unity under the fewest possible number of principles (Pure Reason A298-302/B355-359, A645- 650/B673-678).
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 4-12-2006 Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Neste, Berit Van, "Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea" (2006). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/3782 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea by Berit Van Neste A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Religious Studies College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: James F. Strange, Ph.D. Paul G. Schneider, Ph.D. Michael J. Decker, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 12, 2006 Keywords: theology, philosophy, politics, patristic, medieval © Copyright 2006 , Berit Van Neste For Elizabeth and Calista Table of Contents Abstract ii Chapter 1 1 Introduction 1 Cicero’s Influence on Augustine 7 Chapter 2 13 Justice 13 Natural and Temporal Law 19 Commonwealth 34 Chapter 3 49 Just War 49 Chapter 4 60 Conclusion 60 References 64 i Cicero and St.
    [Show full text]
  • On Unitarian Universalist Moral Duties: Looking Forward with Cicero and Kant
    On Unitarian Universalist Moral Duties: Looking Forward with Cicero and Kant Myriam Renaud I. Why Moral Duties? Aren‟t We Done With That Conversation? For the purposes of this paper, I will rely on the following definition of moral duty (or obligation): an action which is required (imperative) and which is guided by certain moral rules and principles. In every day language, we capture the concept of duty or obligation when we say things like, “I should [or „ought‟] to do this because it‟s the right thing to do,” or “I want to do right by so and so.” These ordinary expressions reflect the view that awareness of the rightness of an action may be enough to provide the impetus to carry through that action—namely, that “in acting from a motive attached to a moral principle,”—in acting on what we take to be the right thing to do—“the moral rightness of the action gives the agent reason for action” [Herman, 30]. Admittedly, the word alone—duty—is likely to cause unpleasant shivers to course down the spines of most Unitarian Universalists. It brings to mind something we have to do, something we‟d rather not do, something we‟re made to do, probably at the expense of some activity we would actually enjoy. But, if we push past the unpleasant shiver, we recognize that duty, or obligation, is tied to the moral structure which governs our lives and which we try to impart to our children both at home and in the religious education classes offered in our congregations.
    [Show full text]
  • Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 11-1-2006 Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Studies in the History of Ethics (November 2006). Publisher link. © 2006 HistoryofEthics.org. Used with permission. Studies in the History of Ethics Ciceronian Bu siness Ethics Owen Goldin (Mar quette University) The teaching and practice of business must resist ethical compartmentalization. One engaged in business ought not check moral principles at the door and say “business is business,” for this is to pretend that when one is engaged in business, one is no longer a human being, with the rational nature, emotional constitution, and social bonds that are at the root of our ethical nature. Ethical standards apply to business as they do all aspects of human life. Nonetheless, making money is the goal of business, and more often than not, one is trying to take money from another, at the least possible cost. Such action is necessarily self-centered, if not selfish, and requires acting in a way that we would not want to see people act in all of their dealings with others, especially in regard to family, friends, and others with whom they have special social bonds. Granting that business practices are not compartmentalized against all ethical considerations, the fact that business demands maximization of profit entails that special rules apply. Determining what these are, in what circumstances they are less demanding than the ethical principles of everyday life, and in what circumstances they are more demanding, is the domain of business ethics, as a special domain of ethical philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Origen in the Likeness of Philo: Eusebius of Caesarea's Portrait Of
    SCJR 12, no. 1 (2017): 1-13 Origen in the Likeness of Philo: Eusebius of Caesarea’s Portrait of the Model Scholar JUSTIN M. ROGERS [email protected] Freed-Hardeman University, Henderson, TN 38340 The name of Philo of Alexandria occurs more in the writings of Eusebius of Caesarea than in those of any other ancient author. Philo’s name can be located over 20 times in the surviving literary corpus of Eusebius,1 and there is strong ev- idence that Eusebius’ Caesarean library is the very reason Philo’s works exist today.2 In all probability, the core of this library can be traced to the personal col- lection of Origen when he settled in Caesarea in 232 CE.3 Eusebius’ own teacher Pamphilus expanded the library, and took great pains to copy and preserve Ori- gen’s own works. What we have, then, is a literary union between Philo and Origen, Alexandrians within the same exegetical tradition. But we can go further. Ilaria Ramelli has argued that Eusebius’ accounts of Philo and Origen in the Ecclesiastical History are strikingly similar, picking up Robert Grant’s stress on the similarity between Origen and the Philonic Therapeutae.4 Here, I further Ramelli’s work by noting additional similarities in the Eusebian biographical presentations. I also point to the tension Eusebius felt between Philo Christianus and Philo Judaeus, a tension detectible in his presentation of the Therapeutae, a group about whom Philo reported and whom Eusebius considered to be the first Egyptian Christians.5 The result is that Eusebius recognized Philo to be exegeti- cally closer to Christianity, and religiously closer to Judaism.
    [Show full text]
  • A Discussion of the Theological Implications of Free Will in the Biblical Story of the Exodus from Egypt
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Senior Theses and Projects Student Scholarship Spring 2012 A Discussion of the Theological Implications of Free Will In the Biblical Story of the Exodus From Egypt Michelle Okun Trinity College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/theses Part of the Biblical Studies Commons, Jewish Studies Commons, and the Other Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Okun, Michelle, "A Discussion of the Theological Implications of Free Will In the Biblical Story of the Exodus From Egypt". Senior Theses, Trinity College, Hartford, CT 2012. Trinity College Digital Repository, https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/theses/194 A Discussion of the Theological Implications of Free Will In the Biblical Story of the Exodus From Egypt Michelle Okun Jewish Studies Thesis Professor Seth Sanders 12/20/11 Okun 2 Introduction Humans have always been acutely aware of their place in time and space, wondering what control they have over their lives. We ask questions such as: what do I, as an individual, control in my life? To what extent does a supreme being know what I will do? Jews and Jewish philosophers have grappled with these questions for centuries, looking to the Torah for advice and clues. Human intellect greatly influences how we view ourselves and our experiences in the context of our relationship with God. Human intellect and how it is aquired emerges first in the Genesis story, after man and woman have been created. The following passage is
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Automatic Action in Plotinus
    Created on 26 November 2007 at 17.13 hours page 373 AUTOMATIC ACTION IN PLOTINUS JAMES WILBERDING 1. Introduction Plotinus scholars have recently called attention to a kind of action in the sensible world, which one could call ‘spontaneous’ or ‘automatic’ action, that is supposed to result automatically from the contemplation of the intelligible.1 Such action is meant to be opposed to actions that result from reason, calculation, and plan- ning, and has been put to work to provide a way for Plotinus’ sage to act, and in particular to act morally, without compromising his ã James Wilberding 2008 A version of this paper was presented at the Katholieke Universiteit Leuven in 2006, where it received a helpful discussion. For comments and suggestions I am par- ticularly indebted to Peter Adamson, Julie Cassiday, Christoph Helmig, Christoph Horn, Jan Opsomer, David Sedley, and Carlos Steel. I have also profited greatly from a reading group held in autumn 2005 at King’s College London on Ennead 3. 8 with Peter Adamson, Verity Harte, M. M. McCabe, and others. I would like to thank Williams College and the Humboldt-Stiftung for funding the research leave during which this paper was written, and Andreas Speer for welcoming me into the Thomas-Institut for this period. 1 e.g. A. Schniewind, L’Ethique‹ du sage chez Plotin [L’Ethique‹ ] (Paris, 2003), 190 with n. 7: ‘les actions du sage sont l’expression (παρακολοýθηµα) de sa propre con- templation . Plotin evoque‹ deux possibilites:‹ d’une part, les actions par faiblesse (èσθÝνεια) de contemplation, pour ceux qui ne parviennent pas a› l’Un; d’autre part — et c’est la› ce qui correspond au sage — les actions en tant qu’activites‹ secondaires (παρακολοýθηµα), issues de la contemplation’; D.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero and Machiavelli: a Complex Relationship
    Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVI, 2014, 2, pp. 526-532 Realism, ontology, and the concept of reality Riccardo Martinelli Università di Trieste Dipartimento di Studi Umanistici [email protected] ABSTRACT This essay focuses on realism in ontology and on the problem of defining reality. According to the definition given by many realists, reality is independent of our thoughts, conceptual schemes, linguistic practices, etc. Yet, this merely negative definition of reality has some disadvantages: it implies a dualistic view, and it is incompatible with scientific realism. As an alternative, I introduce and discuss the traditional definition of reality as effectiveness, or capability of acting. I then attempt to determine to what extent this definition can be helpful in the debate concerning ontological realism. KEYWORDS Realism, new realism, ontology, effectiveness I. In the last decades, philosophers have been involved in an extensive and animated discussion about realism. As it is well known, the word ‘realism’ appears in various philosophical contexts, e.g. in semantics, metaphysics, epistemology, morals, philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of art, political theory, etc.1. Remarkably, in each of these fields, the word ‘realism’ assumes different, heterogeneous meanings. Being a realist in morals, for instance, has little or no influence over one’s attitude towards realism in science, and so on. Accordingly, realism cannot be considered an all-embracing philosophical position2. To a certain extent, some forms of realism might show a certain “family resemblance”, and the various realists possibly use certain specific sets of keywords more frequently than non-realists. But still, different realisms cannot be unified within a single doctrine.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine of Hippo's Philosophy of Time Meets General Relativity
    Augustine of Hippo’s philosophy of time meets general relativity∗ E. Minguzzi† Abstract A cosmological model is proposed which uses a causality argument to solve the homogeneity and entropy problems of cosmology. In this model a chronology violating region of spacetime causally pre- cedes the remainder of the Universe, and a theorem establishes the existence of time functions precisely outside the chronology vio- lating region. This model is shown to nicely reproduce Augustine of Hippo’s thought on time and the beginning of the Universe. In the model the spacelike boundary representing the Big Bang is replaced by a null hypersurface at which the gravitational de- grees of freedom are almost frozen while the matter and radiation content is highly homogeneous and thermalized. 1 Introduction In this work I shall present a cosmological model allowed by general rela- tivity which can be regarded as a mathematical representation of previous ideas by Augustine of Hippo (354 - 430) on time and the creation of the Universe. This model provides also some novel and natural solutions to the homogeneity and entropy problems of cosmology. arXiv:0909.3876v3 [physics.gen-ph] 26 Mar 2014 Instead of introducing the model directly, in order to clarify the cor- respondence with Augustine’s thought, we shall first investigate whether ∗This version includes the proof of Theorem 3.4 which is not included in the version published in Kronoscope 14 (2014) 71-89. Previous title: Can God find a place in physics? St. Augustine’s philosophy meets general relativity. †Dipartimento di Matematica Applicata “G. Sansone”, Universit`adegli Studi di Firenze, Via S.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes on Psychology and the Principles of Metaphysics Richard C
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 10-1-1998 Averroes on Psychology and the Principles of Metaphysics Richard C. Taylor Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 36, No. 4 (October, 1998): 507-523. DOI. Copyright © 1998 Journal of the History of Philosophy, Inc. This article first appeared in Journal of the History of Philosophy 36:4 (1998), 507-523. Reprinted with permission by The oJ hns Hopkins University Press. Averroes on Psychology and the Principles of Metaphysics I RICHARD C. TAYLOR FIRST TRANSLATED FROM Arabic into Latin in the early thirteenth century, the philosophical works of Averroes were initially respected as valuable aids to understanding the true philosophy of Aristotle. William of Auvergne, Bishop of Paris and author of a philosophically astute theological synthesis of Greek and Arabic thought with Christian doctrine, openly expressed his appreciation with praise for Averroes. But by the mid-thirteenth century many of Averroes' teachings were under attack with his conceptions of human nature and separate immaterial intellect the subject of sharply focussed and heated argumentative assaults by Aquinas, Albert and others3 Their arguments were not primarily theological but rather philosophical criticisms which charged that Averroes, Drafts of this paper were presented at a conference sponsored by the International Society for the History of Arabic and Islamic Science and Philosophy at the Smithsonian Institution in Washington, DC, March 28, 1996, and at the annual meeting of the Medieval Academy of America in Toronto, Canada, April 19, 1997. I benefited from discussions of this article with Alfred Ivry, my colleagues, David B.
    [Show full text]