Spinoza on Intentionality, Materialism, and Mind-Body Relations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Spinoza on Intentionality, Materialism, and Mind-Body Relations volume 19, no. 43 1. Introduction1 october 2019 Much has been written already about two aspects of Spinoza’s account of the mind-body relation — namely, about his prohibition on causal relations between minds and bodies, and about the identity of certain pairs of minds and bodies. What has been less studied by compari- son is the intentional (‘of’ or ‘about’) relation that, according to Spinoza, Spinoza on Intentionality, every human mind essentially has to some existing human body.2 A prospective investigator might not be encouraged by the fact that Mar- garet Wilson deemed this part of Spinoza’s system “mysterious”, and Jonathan Bennett thought it grounded on “deep” assumptions that Spi- Materialism, and noza “does not discuss” but which simply “cannot be true”.3 The basic aim of this paper is to clarify how Spinoza understands this intentional aspect of the mind-body relation. Mind-Body Relations One of Spinoza’s basic theses is that every durationally existing hu- man mind is essentially an idea of some existing body. So understand- ing the intentional aspect of the mind-body relation will allow us to understand how a human mind comes into durational existence: what is necessary and sufficient for the constitution of a human mind.4 1. For invaluable comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I’m grateful to John Carriero, Olli Koistinen, John Morrison, and Justin Steinberg; to the audiences at UCLA, Yonsei University, and Ghent University; and to the students of the Collegium Spinozanum at the University of Groningen, and of Justin Steinberg’s graduate seminar at CUNY. I rely on the following abbreviations for Spinoza’s works: E=Ethics, Ep=Letters, KV=Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-being, NS=De Nagelate Schriften van B. D. S. (a 1677 Dutch edition of Spinoza’s writings), TIE=Treatise Karolina Hübner on the Emendation of the Intellect. In citing from Ethics I use the follow- University of Toronto ing abbreviations: app=appendix, ax=axiom, c=corollary, def=definition, d=demonstration, pref=preface, p=proposition, s=scholium. 2. Though see Garrett 2008, 2013, 2016; Koistinen 2016. Spinoza himself talks in terms of ideas being “of”, “affirming” or “express- ing” something. An idea “affirms” and “expresses” what it is “of” (cf. Garrett 2009:288). I will sometimes use ‘represent’ as a synonym for Spinoza’s “be an idea of”. Throughout I will also use “concept”, “idea”, and “thought” in- terchangeably. (Throughout I use double quotations marks for citations © 2019 Karolina Hübner from Spinoza and other primary texts; I reserve single quotes for my own This work is licensed under a Creative Commons terminology.) Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License. 3. Wilson 1999:156, Bennett 1984:§37.3. <www.philosophersimprint.org/019043/> 4. In this paper I will not attempt to offer an account of Spinozistic ideas and karolina hübner Spinoza on Intentionality, Materialism, and Mind-Body Relations Prima facie, Spinoza’s view seems to be that human minds exist be- What Spinoza says … is asymmetrical, with the body having primacy.”9 cause their essential intentional objects — human bodies — do. So one In a similar vein, Nadler concludes, of the tasks of the paper will be to determine whether the existence Spinoza does have materialist tendencies insofar as the of an essential intentional relation between human minds and bodies nature of the human mind and its functions are grounded indeed commits Spinoza to an ontological and explanatory dependence in the nature of the human body. Perhaps we can call it an of human minds on bodies,5 and thus to a version of materialism about explanatory materialism, without thereby implying that the human mind.6 Several commentators have drawn precisely this mental phenomena or events are causally explained by conclusion.7 This is how Curley, for example, opens a chapter entitled physical phenomena or events.10 “Spinoza’s Materialism”: Finally, here is Koistinen: it is the essence of the human mind to be related to some- thing else …. Its essence is to be an idea of that exist- that thinking does not produce objects of its own is a ing body. If we conceive of it as being capable of exist- fundamental feature in Spinoza’s philosophy of mind. … ing apart, we must be conceiving of it inadequately. … To Any idea of an object of an attribute X is ontologically de- understand the mind we must understand the body. … In pendent on the attribute of X. … [I]deas are individuated spite of all the parallelistic talk, the order of understand- through their other-attribute objects.11 ing never proceeds from mind to body.8 So understood, Spinoza fundamentally disagrees with Descartes that Likewise, Bennett notes that what Spinoza endorses is not a “mere par- we can conceive of ourselves as thinking things without also, and in- allelism, a matching of facts about the body with facts about the mind. deed more fundamentally, conceiving of something extended.12 Call such readings of Spinoza’s account of the human mind ‘Materialist Readings’. As we shall see in what follows, prima facie at least, Materialist intentionality in general, but restrict myself to what is essential to a human Readings find plenty of quite straightforward textual support. One mind. may of course also have independent reasons for cheering on Spino- 5. By ‘explain’ I will mean throughout ‘provide adequate (veridical) cognition’. I will use the locutions ‘minds depend on bodies’ and ‘mental properties za’s apparent recognition that there can be no human mind without a depend on physical properties’ interchangeably, since, in Spinoza’s ontology, brain. Nonetheless, what I want to show in what follows is that once minds are also properties (of substance). 6. Spinoza has been characterized as a “materialist” also for other reasons; 9. Bennett 1984:§30. here I’m interested in this assessment only insofar as it hinges on a mind’s intentional relation to a body. 10. Nadler 2008:597, italics in the original. Nadler is discussing E2p13s and E5p39s but interprets the dependence expressed therein as grounded in 7. See e.g. Ayers 2007:76; Barker 1938:159; Bennett 1984:§30.2; Curley 1988:74– “parallelism” (586). However, both passages describe the mind’s intentional 5, 78; Koistinen 2009:168–9, 182; Malinowski-Charles 2010:126; Matson relation to a body (in E2p14, which grounds E539s via E4p338, it is a question 1971:577; Nadler 2008:597; Rice (Spinoza endorses a “representational de- of what the mind “perceives”). pendence” of minds on bodies; “The content of an idea is a relation which it has to noncognitive entities” [1999:41–2]); D. Steinberg 2000:35–6. 11. Koistinen 2016:§1. 8. Curley 1988:74–5, 78. 12. Cf. Ayers 2007:76. philosophers’ imprint – 2 – vol. 19, no. 43 (october 2019) karolina hübner Spinoza on Intentionality, Materialism, and Mind-Body Relations we take a more comprehensive view of Spinoza’s philosophy, Materi- is that, pace Materialism, such appeals should not be understood as alist Readings begin to lose their plausibility. This is because they vio- references to a non-mental reality.14 Instead, they should be under- late several fundamental commitments of Spinoza’s metaphysics and stood as references to the body as represented, the immanent essential epistemology. In particular, such readings violate two basic constraints intentional object of the human mind (or, to use Spinoza’s Scholastic Spinoza places on all possible cognition:13 one, that cognition be of a terminology, the body as “objectively real”). So understood, Spinoza’s thing’s causes, and two, that only like things can explain — give cogni- account of the human mind does not commit him to an explanatory tion of — one another, such that only ideas can explain ideas, only bod- or ontological dependence of minds on some extra-mental reality, and ies can explain bodies, etc. By suggesting that human minds depend thus also does not undermine his larger epistemological and meta- for their existence and explanation on bodies, Materialist Readings physical commitments. violate both of these commitments. As this suggests, what is at stake in investigating the essential in- 2. Spinoza on human minds tentionality of human minds is thus not merely the details of Spinoza’s In this section I want to lay out the background material necessary for understanding of mind-body relations, but also the internal consisten- us to properly understand Spinoza’s account of the essential constitu- cy of his philosophical system: arguably the most natural and preva- tion of the human mind. There are five doctrines especially salient to lent interpretation of his account of the essential constitution of the such an inquiry. Some of these are general metaphysical and episte- human mind sits uneasily with his larger philosophical commitments. mological principles; others are claims specifically about the human This is despite the fact that “cognition of the human mind” is a stated mind. There exists a rough scholarly consensus about all these doc- goal of Spinoza’s entire undertaking in the Ethics (E2pref). trines, and for the purposes of this paper I will for the most part simply Let me say a few words about how this paper is organized. I begin assume them as given, without offering any justification for them or with a brief review of the most relevant background commitments of entering into detailed discussion.15 Spinoza’s philosophy of mind (§2). Next, I examine arguments in fa- Here is the first doctrine: vor of Materialist Readings of Spinoza’s position (§3). I conclude that, (1) Reduction: Minds are just more or less complex ideas.16 despite their prima facie plausibility, such readings must ultimately be rejected, on the grounds of their incompatibility with Spinoza’s basic In other words, there is nothing more to a Spinozistic “mind” than epistemological and metaphysical commitments (§4).
Recommended publications
  • Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin
    Journal of Undergraduate Research at Minnesota State University, Mankato Volume 6 Article 5 2006 Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin Ryan Feldbrugge Minnesota State University, Mankato Follow this and additional works at: https://cornerstone.lib.mnsu.edu/jur Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Feldbrugge, Ryan (2006) "Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin," Journal of Undergraduate Research at Minnesota State University, Mankato: Vol. 6 , Article 5. Available at: https://cornerstone.lib.mnsu.edu/jur/vol6/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate Research Center at Cornerstone: A Collection of Scholarly and Creative Works for Minnesota State University, Mankato. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Undergraduate Research at Minnesota State University, Mankato by an authorized editor of Cornerstone: A Collection of Scholarly and Creative Works for Minnesota State University, Mankato. Feldbrugge: Intentionality in Kant and Wittgensetin INTENTIONALITY IN KANT AND WITTGENSTEIN Ryan Feldbrugge (Philosophy) Dr. Richard Liebendorfer, Faculty Mentor, Philosophy How is thought about and experience of a world possible? This has been the framing question of the present work and it is generally understood as the problem of intentionality. The more specific problem dealt with has been whether or not intentionality has an internal structure that can be made explicit through science, particularly cognitive science. In his Critique of Pure Reason, Immanuel Kant outlines an internal, mental structure that, when imposed on our sensory data, makes thought about and experience of a world possible, which can be viewed as highly anticipatory of modern cognitive science. On the other hand, there are a number of philosophers who have it that the structure of intentionality cannot be made explicit nor can it be understood within science, notably Ludwig Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza's Ethics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza’s Ethics STEVEN NADLER I Descartes famously prided himself on the felicitous consequences of his philoso- phy for religion. In particular, he believed that by so separating the mind from the corruptible body, his radical substance dualism offered the best possible defense of and explanation for the immortality of the soul. “Our natural knowledge tells us that the mind is distinct from the body, and that it is a substance...And this entitles us to conclude that the mind, insofar as it can be known by natural phi- losophy, is immortal.”1 Though he cannot with certainty rule out the possibility that God has miraculously endowed the soul with “such a nature that its duration will come to an end simultaneously with the end of the body,” nonetheless, because the soul (unlike the human body, which is merely a collection of material parts) is a substance in its own right, and is not subject to the kind of decomposition to which the body is subject, it is by its nature immortal. When the body dies, the soul—which was only temporarily united with it—is to enjoy a separate existence. By contrast, Spinoza’s views on the immortality of the soul—like his views on many issues—are, at least in the eyes of most readers, notoriously difficult to fathom. One prominent scholar, in what seems to be a cry of frustration after having wrestled with the relevant propositions in Part Five of Ethics,claims that this part of the work is an “unmitigated and seemingly unmotivated disaster..
    [Show full text]
  • Identity, Personal Continuity, and Psychological Connectedness Across Time and Over
    1 Identity, Personal Continuity, and Psychological Connectedness across Time and over Transformation Oleg Urminskyi, University of Chicago University of Chicago, Booth School of Business Daniel Bartels, University of Chicago University of Chicago, Booth School of Business Forthcoming, Handbook of Research on Identity Theory in Marketing 2 ABSTRACT: How do people think about whether the person they’ll be in the future is substantially the same person they’ll be today or a substantially different, and how does this affect consumer decisions and behavior? In this chapter, we discuss several perspectives about which changes over time matter for these judgments and downstream behaviors, including the identity verification principle (Reed et al. 2012) — people’s willful change in the direction of an identity that they hope to fulfill. Our read of the literature on the self-concept suggests that what defines a person (to themselves) is multi-faceted and in almost constant flux, but that understanding how personal changes relate to one’s own perceptions of personal continuity, including understanding the distinction between changes that are consistent or inconsistent with people’s expectations for their own development, can help us to understand people’s subjective sense of self and the decisions and behaviors that follow from it. 3 A person’s sense of their own identity (i.e., the person’s self-concept) plays a central role in how the person thinks and acts. Research on identity, particularly in social psychology and consumer behavior, often views a person’s self-concept as a set of multiple (social) identities, sometimes characterized in terms of the category labels that the person believes apply to themselves, like “male” or “high school athlete” (Markus and Wurf 1987).
    [Show full text]
  • The No-Self Theory: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity Author(S): James Giles Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol
    The No-Self Theory: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity Author(s): James Giles Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol. 43, No. 2 (Apr., 1993), pp. 175-200 Published by: University of Hawai'i Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1399612 . Accessed: 20/08/2012 03:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy East and West. http://www.jstor.org THE NO-SELF THEORY: HUME, BUDDHISM, AND JamesGiles PERSONAL IDENTITY The problem of personal identity is often said to be one of accounting for Lecturerin Philosophy what it is that gives persons their identity over time. However, once the and Psychologyat Folkeuniversitetet problem has been construed in these terms, it is plain that too much has Aalborg,Denmark already been assumed. For what has been assumed is just that persons do have an identity. To the philosophers who approach the problem with this supposition already accepted, the possibility that there may be no such thing as personal identity is scarcely conceived. As a result, the more fundamental question-whether or not personal identity exists in the first place-remains unasked.
    [Show full text]
  • Expressions of Mind/Body Dualism in Thinspiration
    MIND OVER MATTER: EXPRESSIONS OF MIND/BODY DUALISM IN THINSPIRATION Annamarie O’Brien A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2013 Committee: Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Dr. Rebecca Kinney Dr. Jeremy Wallach © 2013 Annamarie O’Brien All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Thinspiration images, meant to inspire weight-loss, proliferate online through platforms that encourage the circulation of user-generated content. Despite numerous alarmist critiques in mass media about thinspiration and various academic studies investigating ‘pro-anorexia’ sites, surprisingly little attention has been given to the processes of creation and the symbolic potential of thinspiration. This thesis analyzes the formal hybridity of thinspiration, and its use as an expressive medium. The particularities of thinspiration (including its visual characteristics, creative processes, and exhibition) may be considered carefully constructed instances of self- representation, hinging on the expression of beliefs regarding the mind and body. While these beliefs are deeply entrenched in popular body management discourse, they also tend to rely on traditional dualist ideologies. Rather than simply emphasizing slenderness or reiterating standard assumptions about beauty, thinspiration often evokes pain and sadness, and employs truisms about the transcendence of flesh and rebellion against social constraints. By harnessing individualist discourse and the values of mind/body dualism, thinspiration becomes a space in which people struggling with disordered eating and body image issues may cast themselves as active agents—contrary to the image of eating disorders proffered by popular and medical discourse. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, I would like to thank my thesis committee chair, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Intentionality and the Mental Volume IV, Number 4 (Winter 1957)
    Paul E. Meehl we have a formula, and a case comes along in which it disagrees with ------APPENDIX------ our heads? Shall we then use our heads? I would say, yes-provided the psychological situation is as clear as a broken leg; otherwise, very, very seldom. EDITORS' NOTE. This article first appeared in the Tournal of Counseling Psychology, Intentionality and the Mental Volume IV, Number 4 (Winter 1957). For the assignment of copyright, we are grateful to the editor, C. Gilbert Wrenn. REFERENCES I. Cronbach, L. J., and P. E. Meehl. "Construct yalidity in Psy.chological Tests," Psychological Bulletin, 52:281-302 (1955). Reprmted m H. Fe1gl and M. Scnv~n Introduction by Wilfrid Sellars (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. I, pp. 174-204. Mm­ The traditional mind-body problem is, as Herbert Feig] has amply demonstrated in neapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1956. his contribution to this volume, a veritable tangle of tangles. At first sight but one of 2. Humphreys, L. G., C. C. McArthur, P. E. Meehl, N. Sanford, ~nd _ J. Zubin. the 'problems of philosophy,' it soon turns out, as one picks at it, to be nothin& more "Clinical versus Actuarial Prediction," Proceedings of the 1955 Invitational Con- nor less than the philosophical enterprise as a whole. Yet if, to the close-up view. of ference on Testing Problems, pp. 91-141. the philosopher at work, it soon becomes a bewildering crisscross of th.r~ds l.eadmg 3. McArthur, C. C. "Analyzing the Clinical Process," Tournal of Counselmg Psy­ in all directions, it is possible to discern, on standing off, a number of d1stmgmshable chology, 1:203-207 (1954).
    [Show full text]
  • University of Groningen Spinoza's Theory of the Human Mind
    University of Groningen Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason Marrama, Oberto IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2019 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Marrama, O. (2019). Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason. University of Groningen. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 27-09-2021 SPINOZA’S THEORY OF THE HUMAN MIND: CONSCIOUSNESS, MEMORY, AND REASON 1A_BW_Marrama .job © Oberto Marrama, 2019. All rights reserved. ISBN 978-94-034-1568-0 (printed version) ISBN 978-94-034-1569-7 (electronic version) 1B_BW_Marrama .job Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason PhD thesis to obtain the degree of PhD at the University of Groningen on the authority of the Rector Magnificus Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research?
    The Qualitative Report Volume 24 Number 4 How To Article 15 4-22-2019 So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research? Katherine E. Soule University of California, Agriculture and Natural Resources Division, [email protected] Melissa Freeman University of Georgia, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://nsuworks.nova.edu/tqr Part of the Educational Assessment, Evaluation, and Research Commons, Quantitative, Qualitative, Comparative, and Historical Methodologies Commons, and the Social Statistics Commons Recommended APA Citation Soule, K. E., & Freeman, M. (2019). So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research?. The Qualitative Report, 24(4), 857-872. https://doi.org/10.46743/2160-3715/2019.3305 This How To Article is brought to you for free and open access by the The Qualitative Report at NSUWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Qualitative Report by an authorized administrator of NSUWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. So You Want to Do Post-Intentional Phenomenological Research? Abstract In this article, phenomenology, both in its philosophical and methodological variants, is introduced in the form of a fictional dialogue between a student justifying her interest in using a post-intentional phenomenological approach in her dissertation to her major professor. The dialogue tackles founding philosophers, notably Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty; contemporary researchers, including A. Giorgi, B. Giorgi, van Manen, and Vagle; several phenomenological concepts, such as intentionality, bracketing, and bridling; and provides examples of three distinct approaches to phenomenological research. Keywords Phenomenology, Post-Intentional Phenomenology, Bridling, Bracketing, Intentionality Creative Commons License This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 4.0 International License.
    [Show full text]
  • Transparency of Mind: the Contributions of Descartes, Leibniz, and Berkeley to the Genesis of the Modern Subject
    Transparency of Mind: The Contributions of Descartes, Leibniz, and Berkeley to the Genesis of the Modern Subject Gary Hat! eld Philosophers often use classical positions as paradigms for de! ning their own views, usually in contrast. In the philosophy of mind, the notion of the Cartesian subject is one such paradigm. This notion is often used to represent tendencies in the conception of the subject that today’s philosophers wish to avoid. John McDowell and Hilary Putnam 1, among others, portray the Cartesian subject – and speci! cally the Cartesian mind – as a step backward from an earlier, preferable Aristotelianism, whose concept of mind might be made serviceable today if adjusted to ! t modern science. Such paradigms, whose use is unavoidable, are typically caricatures, whether slight or gross. The Cartesian mind as standardly portrayed by McDowell, Putnam, and oth- ers 2 is a gross caricature. This would be important enough for its potential to mislead us about the actual historical development of philosophy. But even more crucially for the philosophy of mind, the use of a caricatured picture as a counterparadigm against which one de! nes one’s own, comparatively better position, can lead to a pyrrhic vic- tory that avoids or misrepresents the real problems. If the opponent has been tailored to one’s desired virtues as conquering hero, one may give the impression that one’s own position solves great problems, deeply embedded in the tradition, when in fact one has simply rejected a fairly recent problematic position, which one has perhaps also misun- derstood and misidenti! ed. 3 The Cartesian mental paradigm is frequently de! ned in terms of four factors: con- sciousness as essence, intentionality as exclusively mental, the veil of perception, and the transparency of mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Intentionality *
    Ronald McIntyre and David Woodruff Smith, “Theory of Intentionality,” in J. N. Mohanty and William R. McKenna, eds., Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook (Washington, D. C.: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology and University Press of America, 1989), pp. 147-79. Original page numbers are in <>. THEORY OF INTENTIONALITY * by Ronald McIntyre and David Woodruff Smith 1. INTENTIONALITY Intentionality is a central concept in philosophy of mind and in Husserl’s phenom­ enology. Indeed, Husserl calls intentionality the “fundamental property of consciousness” and the “principle theme of phenomenology”. Although ‘intentionality’ is a technical term in philosophy, it stands for something familiar to us all: a characteristic feature of our mental states and experiences, especially evident in what we commonly call being “conscious” or “aware”. As conscious beings, or persons, we are not merely affected by the things in our environment; we are also conscious of these things – of physical objects and events, of our own selves and other persons, of abstract objects such as numbers and propositions, and of anything else we bring before our minds. Many, perhaps most, of the events that make up our mental life – our perceptions, thoughts, beliefs, hopes, fears, and so on – have this characteristic feature of being “of” or “about” something and so giving us a sense of something in our world. When I see a tree, for example, my perception is a perception of a tree; when I think that 3 + 2 = 5, I am thinking of or about certain numbers and a relation among them; when I hope that nuclear war will never take place, my hope is about a possible future state of the world; and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig.Wittgenstein.-.Philosophical.Investigations.Pdf
    PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS By LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN Translated by G. E. M. ANSCOMBE BASIL BLACKWELL TRANSLATOR'S NOTE Copyright © Basil Blackwell Ltd 1958 MY acknowledgments are due to the following, who either checked First published 1953 Second edition 1958 the translation or allowed me to consult them about German and Reprint of English text alone 1963 Austrian usage or read the translation through and helped me to Third edition of English and German text with index 1967 improve the English: Mr. R. Rhees, Professor G. H. von Wright, Reprint of English text with index 1968, 1972, 1974, 1976, 1978, Mr. P. Geach, Mr. G. Kreisel, Miss L. Labowsky, Mr. D. Paul, Miss I. 1981, 1986 Murdoch. Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be NOTE TO SECOND EDITION reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or THE text has been revised for the new edition. A large number of otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. small changes have been made in the English text. The following passages have been significantly altered: Except in the United States of America, this book is sold to the In Part I: §§ 108, 109, 116, 189, 193, 251, 284, 352, 360, 393,418, condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re- 426, 442, 456, 493, 520, 556, 582, 591, 644, 690, 692.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz: Personal Identity and Sameness of Substance
    ROCZNIKI FILOZOFICZNE Tom LXV, numer 2 – 2017 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.18290/rf.2017.65.2-5 PRZEMYSŁAW GUT * LEIBNIZ: PERSONAL IDENTITY AND SAMENESS OF SUBSTANCE Leibniz’s view on personal identity has been the object of numerous dis- cussions and various interpretations.1 Among others, the controversies re- volve around the following questions: (1) What is the relation of Leibniz’s conception to the Cartesian view on personal identity? Is it a completely new idea or some modification of Descartes’? (2) To what extent did Locke’s ideas lay the basis for Leibniz’s conception of personal identity, especially Locke’s distinction between being the same substance, organism, and per- son? (3) What role did psychological continuity play in Leibniz’s conception of personal identity? Did he indeed claim that a person’s identity cannot solely arise out of sameness of substance? (4) Is Leibniz’s solution to the problem of personal identity compatible with his deepest metaphysical com- mitments? Can it be seen as a conclusive solution to the problem? (5) Is Leibniz’s effort to offer an account of personal identity by combining the 2 substance-oriented view with the psychological view a coherent solution? Dr hab. PRZEMYSŁAW GUT, Prof. KUL – Katedra Historii Filozofii Nowożytnej i Współ- czesnej, Wydział Filozofii, Katolicki Uniwersytetu Lubelski Jana Pawła II; adres do korespon- dencji: Al. Racławickie 14, 20-950 Lublin; e-mail: [email protected] 1 The abbreviations I use are: Erdmann = Gottfried Wilhelm LEIBNIZ, Opera philosophica om- nia, ed. Johann Eduard Erdmann (Berlin: Scientia Verlag Aalen, 1840); GP = Die philosophischen Schriften von G.W.
    [Show full text]