I Could Not Have Done Otherwise--So What? Author(S): Daniel C

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

I Could Not Have Done Otherwise--So What? Author(S): Daniel C Journal of Philosophy, Inc. I Could not have Done Otherwise--So What? Author(s): Daniel C. Dennett Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 81, No. 10, Eighty-First Annual Meeting American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division (Oct., 1984), pp. 553-565 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026255 . Accessed: 19/08/2012 01:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM 553 I COULD NOT HAVE DONE OTHERWISE-SO WHAT?* WX T HEREVER progressis stalledon a philosophicalprob- lem, a tactic worth tryingis to find some shared (and hence largelyunexamined) assumption and deny it. The problem of free will is such a problem, and, as Peter van Inwagen notes: ... almostall philosophersagree that a necessarycondition for hold- ing an agentresponsible for an act is believingthat the agent could haverefrained from performing that act.' Perhaps van Inwagen is right;perhaps most philosophers agree on this. If so, this shared assumption, which I will call CDO (for "could have done otherwise"),is a good candidate fordenial, espe- cially since thereturns out to be so littleto be said in support of it, once it is called in question. I will argue that,just like thosepeople who are famous only for being famous, this assumption owes its traditional high regard to nothing more than its traditionalhigh regard.It is almost neverquestioned. And the traditionitself, I will claim, is initiallymotivated by littlemore than inattentiveextrapo- lation fromfamiliar cases. To engage the issue, I assertthat it simply does not matterat all to moral responsibilitywhether the agent in question could have done otherwise in the circumstances.Now how does a friendof CDO set about showing that I am obviously wrong? Not by re- minding meRunnecessarily, of the broad consensus in philosophy in support of the CDO principle, or by repeating it, firmlyand knowingly.The inertia of a traditionis by itselfscant recommen- dation, and if it is claimed that the assumption is not questioned because it is obvious or self-evident,I can at least ask forsome sup- portingillustration of the self-evidenceof the assumption in appli- cation to familiarcases. Can anyone give me an example of some- one withholding a judgment of responsibility until he has determined(to his own satisfaction)whether the agent could have done otherwise? It will perhaps appear that I must be extraordinarilyinattentive to the topics of daily conversationif I can ask that question with a straightface. A prominentfeature of many actual inquiries into the *To be presentedin an APA symposiumon Freedomand Determinism,December 30, 1984. Petervan Inwagen will comment;see this JOURNAL, this issue, 565-567. "'The Incompatibilityof Free Will and Determinism,"Philosophical Studies, xxvii, 3 (March 1975): 185-99,p. 188, reprintedin Gary Watson,ed., Free Will (New York: Oxford,1982): 46-58, p. 50. 0022-362X/84/8110/0553$01.30 C1984The Journalof Philosophy,Inc. 554 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY responsibilityof particular agents is the asking of the question "Could he have done otherwise?"The question is raised in trials, both civil and criminal, and much more frequentlyin the retro- spective discussions between individuals concerning blame or ex- cuse forparticular regretted acts of omission or commission. Beforeturning to a closer examination of those cases, it is worth noting that the question plays almost no role in discussions of praise or rewardfor felicitous, unregretted acts-except in the for- mulaic gracious demurrerof the one singled out for gratitudeor praise: "What else could I do?" ("Anyone else would have done the same." "Shucks; 'twarn'tnothin'.") And in these instances we do not take the agent to be disavowing responsibilityat all, but just declaring that being responsible under those conditions was not difficult. Perhaps one reason we do not ask "Could he have done other- wise?" when tryingto assess responsibilityfor good deeds and tri- umphs is that(thanks to our generosityof spirit)we give agents the benefitof the doubt when theyhave done well by us, ratherthan delving too scrupulouslyinto factsof ultimateauthorship. Such a charitable impulse may play a role, but thereare betterreasons, as we shall see. And we certainlydo ask the question when an act is up forcensure. But when we do, we neveruse the familiarquestion to inaugurate the sort of investigation that would actually shed light on the traditionalphilosophical issue the question has been presumed to raise. Instead we proceed to look around forevidence of what I call a pocket of local fatalism:a particularcircumstance in the relevant portion of the past which ensured that the agent would not have done otherwise(during the stretchof local fatal- ism) no matterwhat he had tried,or wanted, to do. A standardex- ample of local fatalismis being locked in a room.2 If the agent was locked in a room (or in some other way had his will renderedimpotent), then independentlyof the truthor falsity of determinismand no matterwhat sortof causation reignswithin the agent's brain (or Cartesian soul, for that matter),we agree that "he could not have done otherwise."The readilydeterminable em- pirical fact that an agent was a victim of local fatalismterminates the inquiry into causation. (It does not always settlethe issue of re- sponsibility, however, as Harry Frankfurtshows3; under special 2The misuse of this standard example-e.g., in the extrapolation to the theme that,if determinismis true,the whole world's a prison-is describedin my Elbow Room: The Varietiesof Free Will Worth Wanting (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford/ MIT Press, 1984), fromwhich portionsof the presentargument are drawn. 3"Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility,"this JOUJRNAL, LXV, 23 (Dec. 4, 1969): 829-833. FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM 555 circumstancesan agent may still be held responsible.) And if our investigationfails to uncover any evidence of such local fatalism, this also terminatesthe inquiry. We consider the mattersettled: the agent was responsible afterall; "he could have done otherwise." Proving a negative existentialis not generallyregarded as a prob- lem here. We can typicallycount on the agent himselfto draw our attentionto any evidence of local fatalismhe is aware of (for if he can show that "his hands were tied" this will tend to exculpate him), so his failures to come forwardwith any such evidence is takento be a reliable (but not foolproof)sign thatthe case is closed. The firstpoint I wish to make is that if the friendsof CDO look to everydaypractice for evidence for the contention that ordinary people "agree that a necessarycondition for holding an agent re- sponsible foran act is believing thatthe agent could have refrained fromperforming that act," theyin factwill find no such support. When the act in question is up forpraise, people manifestlyignore the question and would seem bizarreif theydidn't. And when as- sessing an act forblame, although people do indeed ask "Could he have done otherwise?", they show no interestin pursuing that question beyond the point where theyhave satisfiedtheir curiosity about the existence or absence of local fatalism-a phenomenon thatis entirelyneutral between determinism or indeterminism.For instance, people never withhold judgment about responsibility until after they have consulted physicists (or metaphysiciansor neuroscientists)for their opinions about the ultimate status-de- terministicor indeterministic-ofthe neural or mental eventsthat governedthe agent's behavior. And so faras I know, no defenseat- torneyhas ever gone into court to mount a defensebased on an ef- fortto establish, by expert testimony,that the accused was deter- mined to make the decision that led to the dreadfulact, and hence could not have done otherwise,and hence ("obviously") is not to be held responsiblefor it. So the CDO principle is not something"everybody knows" even if most philosophersagree on it. The principle requiressupporting argument.My second point is that any such supportingargument must challenge an abundance of utterlyfamiliar evidence suggest- ing that often,when we seem to be interestedin the question of whetherthe agent could have done otherwise,it is because we wish to draw the opposite conclusion about responsibilityfrom that which the philosophical traditionendorses. "Here I stand," Luther said. "I can do no other." Luther claimed that he could do no other,that his conscience made it impossible for him to recant. He might,of course, have been wrong, or have been deliberatelyoverstating the truth,but even if he was-perhaps 556 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY especially if he was-his declarationis testimonyto the factthat we simply do not exempt someone fromblame or praise foran act be- cause we thinkhe could do no other. WhateverLuther was doing, he was not tryingto duck responsibility. There are cases where the claim "I can do no other" is an avowal of frailty:suppose what I ought to do is get on the plane and flyto safety,but I stand rooted on the ground and confess I can do no other-because of my irrationaland debilitatingfear of flying.In such a case I can do no other,I claim, because my rational control facultyis impaired. This is indeed an excusing condition. But in othercases, like Luther's, when I say I cannot do otherwiseI mean that I cannot because I see so clearly what the situation is and be- cause my rational control facultyis not impaired. It is too obvious what to do; reason dictatesit; I would have to be mad to do other- wise, and, since I happen not to be mad, I cannot do otherwise.
Recommended publications
  • Daniel Dennett's Science of the Soul
    Daniel Dennett’s Science of the Soul - The New Yorker 3/20/17, 9:38 AM P!FI"S MARCH 27, 2017 I#UE DANIEL DENNE$’S SCIENCE OF THE SOUL A philosopher’s lifelong quest to understand the making of the mind. By Joshua Rothman Daniel Dennett’s naturalistic account of consciousness draws some people in and puts others off. “There ain’t no magic here,” he says. “Just stage magic.” PHOTOGRAPH BY IRINA ROZOVSKY FOR THE NEW YORKER our billion years ago, Earth was a lifeless place. Nothing struggled, F thought, or wanted. Slowly, that changed. Seawater leached chemicals from rocks; near thermal vents, those chemicals jostled and combined. Some hit upon the trick of making copies of themselves that, in turn, made more copies. The replicating chains were caught in oily bubbles, which protected them and made replication easier; eventually, they began to venture out into the open sea. A new level of order had been achieved on Earth. Life had begun. The tree of life grew, its branches stretching toward complexity. Organisms developed systems, subsystems, and sub-subsystems, layered in ever-deepening regression. They used these systems to anticipate their future and to change it. When they looked within, some found that they had selves—constellations of memories, ideas, and purposes that emerged from the systems inside. They experienced being alive and had thoughts about that experience. They developed language and used it to know themselves; they began to ask how they had been made. This, to a !rst approximation, is the secular story of our creation.
    [Show full text]
  • A Naturalistic Perspective on Intentionality. Interview with Daniel Dennett
    Mind & Society, 6, 2002, Vol. 3, pp. 1-12 2002, Rosenberg & Sellier, Fondazione Rosselli A naturalistic perspective on intentionality. Interview with Daniel Dennett by Marco Mirolli Marco Mirolli You describe yourself as a philosopher of mind and you reject the exhortations to get more involved in the abstract problems of ontology and of philosophy of science in general, even if the problems of the philosophy of mind and those of philosophy of science are deeply mutually dependent. I think this is an important issue because, while you say that your philosophy presupposes only the standard scientific ontology and epistemology 1, it seems to me that what you really presuppose is rather a Quinean view of ontology and epistemology, which is not so standard, even if it may well be the one we should accept. Daniel Dennett Well, maybe so, let's see. Certainly I have seen almost no reason to adopt any other ontology than Quine's; and when I look at the work in the phi- losophy of science and more particularly at the work in science, I do not find any ground yet for abandoning a Quinean view of ontology for something fancier. It could happen, but I haven't seen any reason for doing this; so if you want to say that I am vulnerable on this, that's really true. I have stated that I don't see any of the complexities of science or philosophy of mind raising ontological issues that are more sophisticated than those a Quinean ontology could handle; but I may be wrong.
    [Show full text]
  • Synthetic Philosophy
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Synthetic Philosophy Schliesser, E. DOI 10.1007/s10539-019-9673-3 Publication date 2019 Document Version Final published version Published in Biology and Philosophy License CC BY Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Schliesser, E. (2019). Synthetic Philosophy. Biology and Philosophy, 34(2), [19]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9673-3 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:25 Sep 2021 Biology & Philosophy (2019) 34:19 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9673-3 REVIEW ESSAY Synthetic philosophy Eric Schliesser1 Received: 4 November 2018 / Accepted: 11 February 2019 © The Author(s) 2019 Abstract In this essay, I discuss Dennett’s From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds (hereafter From Bacteria) and Godfrey Smith’s Other Minds: The Octopus and The Evolution of Intelligent Life (hereafter Other Minds) from a methodologi- cal perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • DANIEL DENNETT and the SCIENCE of RELIGION Richard F
    DANIEL DENNETT AND THE SCIENCE OF RELIGION Richard F. Green Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Minnesota-Duluth Duluth, MN 55812 ABSTRACT Daniel Dennett (2006) recently published a book, “Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon,” which advocates the scientific study of religion. Dennett is a philosopher with wide-ranging interests including evolution and cognitive psychology. This talk is basically a review of Dennett’s religion book, but it will include comments about other work about religion, some mentioned by Dennett and some not. I will begin by describing my personal interest in religion and philosophy, including some recent reading. Then I will comment about the study of religion, including the scientific study of religion. Then I will describe some of Dennett’s ideas about religion. I will conclude by trying outlining the ideas that should be considered in order to understand religion. This talk is mostly about ideas, particularly religious beliefs, but not so much churches, creeds or religious practices. These other aspects of religion are important, and are the subject of study by a number of disciplines. I will mention some of the ways that people have studied religion, mainly to provide context for the particular ideas that I want to emphasize. I share Dennett’s reticence about defining religion. I will offer several definitions of religion, but religion is probably better defined by example than by attempting to specify its essence. A particular example of a religion is Christianity, even more particularly, Roman Catholicism. MOTIVATION My interest in philosophy and religion I. Beginnings I read a few books about religion and philosophy when I was in high school and imagined that college would be full of people arguing about religion and philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • New Atheism and the Scientistic Turn in the Atheism Movement MASSIMO PIGLIUCCI
    bs_bs_banner MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY Midwest Studies In Philosophy, XXXVII (2013) New Atheism and the Scientistic Turn in the Atheism Movement MASSIMO PIGLIUCCI I The so-called “New Atheism” is a relatively well-defined, very recent, still unfold- ing cultural phenomenon with import for public understanding of both science and philosophy.Arguably, the opening salvo of the New Atheists was The End of Faith by Sam Harris, published in 2004, followed in rapid succession by a number of other titles penned by Harris himself, Richard Dawkins, Daniel Dennett, Victor Stenger, and Christopher Hitchens.1 After this initial burst, which was triggered (according to Harris himself) by the terrorist attacks on September 11, 2001, a number of other authors have been associated with the New Atheism, even though their contributions sometimes were in the form of newspapers and magazine articles or blog posts, perhaps most prominent among them evolutionary biologists and bloggers Jerry Coyne and P.Z. Myers. Still others have published and continue to publish books on atheism, some of which have had reasonable success, probably because of the interest generated by the first wave. This second wave, however, often includes authors that explicitly 1. Sam Harris, The End of Faith: Religion, Terror, and the Future of Reason (New York: W.W. Norton, 2004); Sam Harris, Letter to a Christian Nation (New York: Vintage, 2006); Richard Dawkins, The God Delusion (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2006); Daniel C. Dennett, Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon (New York: Viking Press, 2006); Victor J. Stenger, God:The Failed Hypothesis: How Science Shows That God Does Not Exist (Amherst, NY: Prometheus, 2007); Christopher Hitchens, God Is Not Great: How Religion Poisons Everything (New York: Twelve Books, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • A Pragmatic and Empirical Approach to Free Will Andrea Lavazza(Α)
    RIVISTA INTERNAZIONALE DI FILOSOFIA E PSICOLOGIA ISSN 2039-4667; E-ISSN 2239-2629 DOI: 10.4453/rifp.2017.0020 Vol. 8 (2017), n. 3, pp. 247-258 STUDI A Pragmatic and Empirical Approach to Free Will Andrea Lavazza(α) Ricevuto: 10 febbraio 2017; accettato: 24 agosto 2017 █ Abstract The long dispute between incompatibilists (namely, the advocates of the contemporary ver- sion of the illusory nature of freedom) and compatibilists is further exemplified in the discussion between Sam Harris and Daniel Dennett. In this article, I try to add to the discussion by outlining a concept of free will linked to five operating conditions and put forward a proposal for its operationalization and quantifi- cation. The idea is to empirically and pragmatically define free will as needed for moral blame and legal liability, while separating this from the debate on global determinism, local determinism, automatisms and priming phenomena on a psychological level. This is made possible by weakening the claims of de- terminisms and psychological automatisms, based on the latest research, and by giving a well-outlined definition of free will as I want to defend it. KEYWORDS: Compatibilism; Daniel Dennett; Free Will Quantification; Global Determinism; Local De- terminism █ Riassunto Un approccio pragmatico ed empirico al libero arbitrio – La lunga disputa tra incompatibilisti (va- le a dire i sostenitori della versione contemporanea dell’illusorietà del libero arbitrio) e compatibilisti trova un’esemplificazione nel dibattito tra Sam Harris e Daniel Dennett. In questo articolo cerco di contribuire alla discussione delineando un concetto di libero arbitrio legato a cinque condizioni operative e proponendo la sua operazionalizzazione e quantificazione.
    [Show full text]
  • The Organism – Reality Or Fiction?
    The organism – reality or fiction? organism CHARLES T WOLFE SCOUTS THE ANSWERS forum/ hat is an “organism”? A state We murder to dissect, or as the famous physicist of matter, or a particular type Niels Bohr warned, we may kill the organism of living being chosen as an with our too-detailed measurements. experimental object, like the Historically, the word “organism” emerged in Wfruit fly or the roundworm c. elegans, which the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centu- 96 are “model organisms”? Organisms are real, in ries, in particular, in the debate between the a trivial sense, since flies and Tasmanian tigers philosopher and polymath Gottfried Wilhelm and Portuguese men-o-war are (or were, in the Leibniz and the chemist and physician Georg- case of the Tasmanian tiger) as real as tables and Ernest Stahl, the author of a 1708 essay On the chairs and planets. But at the same time, they difference between mechanism and organism. are meaningful constructs, as when we describe Both Leibniz and Stahl agree that organisms Hegel or Whitehead as philosophers of organism are not the same as mere mechanisms, but in the sense that they insist on the irreducible they differ on how to account for this differ- properties of wholes – sometimes, living wholes ence. For Leibniz, it is more of a difference in in particular. In addition, the idea of organism complexity (for him, organisms are machines is sometimes appealed to in a polemical way, as which are machines down to their smallest parts), when biologists or philosophers angrily oppose a whereas for Stahl, the organism is a type of whole more “holistic” sense of organism to a seemingly governed by the soul (at all levels of our bodily cold-hearted, analytic and dissective attitude functioning, from the way I blink if an object associated with “mechanism” and “reductionism”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science Studio with Daniel Dennett
    The Science Studio With Daniel Dennett ROGER BINGHAM: My guest today in the Science Studio is Dan Dennett, who is the professor of philosophy and co-director for the Center For Cognitive Studies at Tufts University, co-founder and co-director of the Curricula Software Studio at Tufts, and he helped design museum exhibits on computers for the Smithsonian, the Museum of Science in Boston, and the Computer Museum in Boston. But more importantly he’s known as the author of many books, including most recently Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. So, Dan Dennett, let me just take you back to an interview, because this is Beyond Belief Two: Enlightenment 2.0. You were supposed to have been at the first meeting last year. There’s an interview that you did some time ago with our old friend, Susan Blackmore, where she asked you “I assume you don’t believe in God; do you think anything of the person survives physical death?” You got very close to physical death about a year ago. DANIEL DENNETT: I did, yeah. BINGHAM: Would you like to recount that wonderful experience? DENNETT: I had had a triple bypass in ‘99, but I was fine; I was in good shape. But then I had a so-called aortic dissection. My aorta, the main pipe from the heart up to the rest of the body, sort of blew out. It was held together by the scar tissue from the old operation; that’s what saved my life, first. And so I had that all replaced - I now have a Dacron aorta and a carbon fiber aortic valve, and I’m fine, as you can see.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Lexicon
    THE PHILOSOPHICAL LEXICON DANIEL DENNETT, EDITOR Copies of The Philosophical Lexicon may be obtained from: American Philosophical Association University of Delaware Newark, Delaware 19711 Price, prepaid, postage included: single copy $3.00 twenty-five copies or more $2.50 Checks should be made payable to the American Philosophical Associa­ tion. All royalties to the American Philosophical Association. Copyright © 1987 by Daniel Dennett PREFACE TO THE EIGHTH EDITION The Eighth Edition of The Philosophical Lexicon is only the second to be published. The Seventh Edition was published in 1978. while the earlier editions circulated in mimeograph form. (In 1980. a Serbo­ Croation translation of selections from the Seventh Edition was published in Zagreb. joining the German translation of the Sixth Edition published a few years earlier in Austria.) The Lexicon began one night in September of 1969 when I was writing lecture notes and found myself jotting down as a heading "quining in­ tentions" I saw fit to compose a definition of the verb. In the morning I was ill prepared to lecture, but handed a list of about a dozen definitions together with the Introduction to my colleagues at Irvine. Joe Lambert promptly responded with several more definitions and sent the first batch to Nuel Belnap and Alan Anderson at Pittsburgh. Almost by return mail their first entries arrived, and within a few months we pre­ pared a second edition, and then a third. The editions have been cumula­ tive, but along the way a few entries have either been dropped as sub­ standard or replaced by better definitions of the same term.
    [Show full text]
  • 1301 STUDY GUIDE #2 Spring 2006
    1301 STUDY GUIDE #2 MWF Fall 2010 What is the subject: ‘Epistemology?’ Conditions for knowledge according to the ‘Standard Analysis of Knowledge’: 1. __________________________ condition which involves __________________ and _________________________ 2. _______________________ condition Three truth theories are (list and define-explain): 1) 2) 3) 3. ______________________________ condition Which is a matter of: What characterizes rationalist theories of epistemology? 1) 2) 3) 4) 5) Rene Descartes – explain: his “method of doubt” “cogito ergo sum!” the role of God in his account of knowledge: God is a ____________ being who “must‟ exist! = how he came to trust again in reason as a source of knowledge: = how he came again trust the senses as sources of knowledge: The nature and problem of his standard of certainty for knowledge was: Define – Explain: „Local Skepticism‟ „Global Skepticism‟ What characterizes empiricist theories of epistemology? 1) 2) 3) 4) 5) Explain: tabula rasa = the basis of all our ideas is: primary qualities / properties = secondary qualities / properties = Why did David Hume deny that we have knowledge of causal connections in objective reality? How was Immanuel Kant‟s epistemology a „synthesis‟ account of knowledge? What was Kant‟s view of the mind‟s role in knowing? What were „categories of the understanding‟ according to Kant? Explain what „synthetic apriori‟ judgments / truths are: So what was the status of causal relations according to Kant? Explain the significance of Kant‟s statements: 1) “Concepts without perceptions are empty. / Perceptions without concepts are blind.” 2) „It is true that al knowledge begins with experience. / It is not true that all knowledge arises from experience.” List and explain eleven accounts / perspectives on personal identity.
    [Show full text]
  • CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE Sour
    ( Fall 1995 Vol.15, No.4 HMMM... CONSCIOUSNESS 'THE sour. ABE ARTIFICIAL IIITELLIGENCE Exclusive Interviews with Cognitive Scientists Patricia Smith Churchland and Daniel C. Dennett BERTRAND RUSSELL Also: The Disneyfication of America Situation Ethics in Medicine 74957 Reactionar Black Nationalism FALL 1995, VOL. 15, NO. 4 ISSN 0272-0701 !ee WTI : Contents Editor: Paul Kurtz Executive Editor: Timothy J. Madigan Managing Editor: Andrea Szalanski 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Senior Editors: Vern Bullough, Thomas W. Flynn, R. Joseph Hoffmann, Gerald Larue, Gordon Stein 5 EDITORIALS Contributing Editors: Robert S. Alley, Joe E. Barnhart, David Berman, Notes from the Editor: Pro Ecclesia et Commercia, Paul Kurtz I H. James Birx, Jo Ann Boydston, Bonnie Bullough, Reactionary Black Nationalism: Authoritarianism in the Name of Paul Edwards, Albert Ellis, Roy P. Fairfield, Charles W. Faulkner, Antony Flew, Levi Fragell, Adolf Freedom, Norm R. Allen, Jr. / The Founding Fathers Were Not Grünbaum, Marvin Kohl, Jean Kotkin, Thelma Lavine, Tibor Machan, Ronald A. Lindsay, Michael Christian, Steven Morris I Religious Right to Bolt GOP?, Skipp Martin, Delos B. McKown, Lee Nisbet, John Novak, Porteous I Humanist Potpourri, Warren Allen Smith Skipp Porteous, Howard Radest, Robert Rimmer, Michael Rockier, Svetozar Stojanovic, Thomas Szasz, Roh Tielman 16 NEWS AND VIEWS V. M. Torkunde, Richard Taylor, Associate Editors: Molleen Matsumura, Lois Porter 19 CONSCIOUSNESS REVISITED Editorial Associates: 19 FI Interview: A Conversation with Daniel Dennett Doris Doyle, Thomas Franczyk, Roger Greeley, James Martin-Diaz, Steven L. Mitchell, Warren 22 FI Interview: The Neurophilosophy of Patricia Smith Churchland Allen Smith 25 Neurological Bases of Modern Humanism José Delgado Cartoonist: Don Addis 29 Revisiting 'New Conceptions of the Mind' Noel W Smith CODESH.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Two Realms
    Leibniz’s Two Realms Jonathan Bennett [From D. Rutherford and J. A. Cover (eds), Leibniz: Nature and Freedom (Oxford University Press, 2005), pp. 135–55. 1. Leibniz’s commitment to mechanism Leibniz’s support for ‘mechanism’ may be encouraged Leibniz insists that any bodily event can be explained purely also by his denial that any material event can be explained in terms of ‘mechanism’, meaning impact mechanics. The through a mental one. The Galilean revolution may en- latter’s laws are all quasi-causal (Sleigh’s label) rather than courage that denial, but not to the extent of requiring it. causal; they describe patterns among events that are em- Descartes was a prime revolutionary who firmly rejected the bedded in the universal harmony, and do not imply that any Aristotelian paradigm, yet he held that human behavior body acts on any other. When declaring how things must go requires some input from an immaterial mind. Leibniz in physics, Leibniz does not often remind us that his topic dissents: ‘I attribute to mechanism everything which takes is quasi-causation, not real transeunt causation; but that place in the bodies of plants and animals except their initial is always his view. Similarly, in those contexts he seldom formation’, he writes at NE 139. ‘I do not approve of bringing reminds us that bodies are phenomenal rather than basically in the soul when plant and animal phenomena have to be real; but in the mature years that is always his view too. explained in detail’ (NE 220). This holds for humans too. In his claim for the power of mechanism, Leibniz is refus- Leibniz’s faith in mechanism’s extent draws strength from ing to explain any particular events in terms of Aristotelian his conviction that the value of this world consists partly ‘forms’, e.g.
    [Show full text]