Aristotle on Genus and Differentia in the Topics and Categories

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aristotle on Genus and Differentia in the Topics and Categories Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 8-1983 Aristotle on Genus and Differentia in the Topics and Categories Herbert Granger University of Texas at Austin, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Granger, Herbert, "Aristotle on Genus and Differentia in the Topics and Categories" (1983). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 106. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/106 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Herbert Granger University of Texas at Austin A ristotle on Genus and Differentia in the Topics and Categories Each of A ristotle's early works, the Topics and the Categories»'*' provides important evidence for A ristotle's holding two accounts of the nature of the genus and differentia. In one account genus and differentia are rad­ ically distinct in nature. In the other they are much the same. In this paper I shall make a case for A ristotle's holding each account, sug­ gest why he adopts them, and consider which of the two is the earlier one. I I shall often refer to A ristotle's categorical distinction between sub­ stances (or secondary substances) and non-substances. I take it to dis­ tinguish between the kinds A ristotle deems ontologically significant and the characteristics of the instances of those kinds. The distinction between kinds and characteristics arises from the syntactical distinc­ tion between nouns and adjectives: nouns express kinds; adjectives ex­ press characteristics. The ontologically significant kinds have for their instances the basic entities in A ristotle's ontology. These kinds reveal what kinds of things the basic entities are with respect to their essential nature. For this reason, according to Aristotle, the ontolog­ ically significant kinds are the genera and species of the basic enti— 2 ties. I shall refer to these kinds as "substantial kinds." A species is a complex of its genus ahd differentia (or differen— 3 tiae): for example, the species man is a complex of the genus animal and the differentia two-footed.^ Accordingly, genus and differentia de- 5 fine the species, and they belong necessarily to the species· Because 1 genus and differentia make up the definition of the species» they pro­ vide the account of its basic nature or essence, its ti In einai (Top. 1 .5 .101b 38). In the definition the genus divides the species from things in general, and the differentia distinguishes it from the other things falling under its genus (Top. VI.3.l40a27-29). This brief description, which I derive primarily from the Topics, of genus, differentia and spe­ cies holds for the two accounts of genus and differentia that I discuss. II The Topics and Categories indicate that at one point Aristotle believes that a radical distinction holds between the genus and differentia of substances. This distinction is the categorical distinction between kind and characteristic, which Aristotle marks by holding that the genus alone shows the ti esti, the Mwhat-it-is," of the definiendum and that the differentia shows only a poion t i , a "certain quality," of the defin­ iendum. In Topics 1.5, when Aristotle first introduces the predicables, he defines the genus in these terms: The genus is what is predicated in the ti esti ("what—it—is") of many things differing in species (l.5.102a31-33) Elsewhere it is evident that at least at one point in his thought the genus alone of the elements in the definition represents the ti esti; for Aristotle holds that it is an error not to place the ti esti first in the definition and that this is why the genus is properly placed first, since it is meant to indicate the ti esti (Top. VI.5.142b22-29). The differentia, in contrast with the genus, does not concern the ti esti and is clearly distinct from the genusj a "bad mistake" then is made, accord- 2 ing to Aristotle, if one renders the differentia as the genus: ...for the differentia is the genus of nothing. That this is true is evident; for no differentia signifies the ti esti, hut rather a poion ti (”certain quality”), such as footed and two-footed (Top. IV.2.122bl5-17» cf. VI.6.l44al5-19). These views concerning the roles of genus and differentia are surely A ristotle’s, since in expressing them he does not qualify them hy holding that each ’’seems” to he the case, as he often does when presenting a par­ ticular position in the Topics: moreover, his holding that a ”bad mis­ take” is made when one renders the differentia as a genus strongly sug­ gests that he offers his own view. These distinct roles for genus and differentia obtain not only for substances hut for non-substances as well: for instance, state, the genus of the non-substance virtue, indi­ cates the ti esti of virtue, whereas good, its differentia, does not in— 7 dicate the ti esti but rather a poion ti. The Categories maintains that the genus and species of primary sub­ stances are the only predicates that are substances because they reveal the ti esti of primary substances (5.2b29-33). The Categories also notes that the differentia is not a substance (5.3a21-22). The genus and spe­ cies, like their specimens, are thus found in the category of substance; the differentia is not. The Topics reflects these doctrines: it holds that the genus is in the same category as its species (lV.1.120b3ó-121a 9); it remains silent about whether the differentia is in the same cate­ gory as its subjects; it maintains that the differentia can never signi- 8 fy a "this,” a tode, which on A ristotle’s térros represents a substance. Clearly, as one would expect, A ristotle’s distinction between genus 3 ajad differentia in terms of ti esti sind poion t i » "what-it-is" and "cer­ tain quality»" amounts to a categorical distinction in the case of sub­ stances. The genus as the ti esti of a substantial definiendum is a sub­ stance or substantial kind; the differentia as a poion ti is a non-sub- stance or characteristic in the category of quality. Aristotle simply recognizes explicitly what he finds in the definition» a kind and a char­ acteristic» and marks their categorical difference plainly by his use of ti esti and poion ti. A ristotle’s few remarks in the Topics» which concern the meaning of ti esti» support the interpretation that a predicate in the ti esti of a substance must be a substance or substantial kind. In Topics 1.5» where Aristotle gives his account of the genus as a predicate in the ti esti» he explains that such a predicate is given in response to the question» "what is the object before you?" By way of illustration» he says that if one is presented with a man» one says what it is by saying that it is an "animal" (l02a32-35). Thus a predicate in the ti esti signifies what kind of thing the object is. Indeed» it is hard to see how ti esti could signify anything else. Greek, as well as English, will not allow any­ thing else in response to a question about what something is except a noun and thus a kind expressed by the noun. Moreover, in the case of substances a predicate in the ti esti signifies the object’s kind with respect to its nature, its substantial kind, not just any kind it hap- 9 pens to fall under. This interpretation is supported by Aristotle’s examples of these predicates here in Topics 1.5 and in the important discussion of the categories in 1.9» the only other place in which he indicates the meaning of predicates in the ti esti; for Aristotle limits 4 his examples to the species and genera of the substances and non-sub­ stances used in illustration and at no point offers a differentia as a predicate in the ti esti. (Besides» substantial kinds seem to be the only kinds for substances Aristotle recognizes as kinds; for, when he considers some other kinds a substance might belong to, for example, "boxer” and "runner" in the Categories, he seems to treat them as char­ acteristics (8.10a27—bll)·) It is evident then why the differentia is not a predicate in the ti esti of a substance. Por the differentia, in­ sofar as it is a characteristic, is not a kind and a fortiori not one of A ristotle's substantial kinds. Hence, when it applies to a substantial definiendum, it cannot indicate the latter's ti esti. Aristotle says as much about characteristics in general, when in Topics I.9 he maintains that predicates in the non-substantial categories, when predicates of things outside their categories, namely substances, do not signify a ti esti but only a quality or a quantity or some other non-substantial item (103b35-39)· Besides the important distinctions already noted between genus and differentia. Other perhaps less important differences, but certainly rel­ evant to my discussion, hold between them. As I noted, the genus is properly the first term in the definition because it is the ti esti; it is also the more familiar or knowable term and prior in intelligibility to the differentia.*^ These latter two points of difference, which may in fact come to the same thing, also perhaps reflect the categorical dis­ tinction between genus and differentia; for Aristotle believes that sub­ stances are prior in knowledge to non-substances (Met.
Recommended publications
  • Aquinas on Attributes
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by MedievaleCommons@Cornell Philosophy and Theology 11 (2003), 1–41. Printed in the United States of America. Copyright C 2004 Cambridge University Press 1057-0608 DOI: 10.1017/S105706080300001X Aquinas on Attributes BRIAN LEFTOW Oriel College, Oxford Aquinas’ theory of attributes is one of the most obscure, controversial parts of his thought. There is no agreement even on so basic a matter as where he falls in the standard scheme of classifying such theories: to Copleston, he is a resemblance-nominalist1; to Armstrong, a “concept nominalist”2; to Edwards and Spade, “almost as strong a realist as Duns Scotus”3; to Gracia, Pannier, and Sullivan, neither realist nor nominalist4; to Hamlyn, the Middle Ages’ “prime exponent of realism,” although his theory adds elements of nominalism and “conceptualism”5; to Wolterstorff, just inconsistent.6 I now set out Aquinas’ view and try to answer the vexed question of how to classify it. Part of the confusion here is terminological. As emerges below, Thomas believed in “tropes” of “lowest” (infima) species of accidents and (I argue) substances.7 Many now class trope theories as a form of nominalism,8 while 1. F. C. Copleston, Aquinas (Baltimore, MD: Penguin Books, 1955), P. 94. 2. D. M. Armstrong, Nominalism and Realism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 25, 83, 87. Armstrong is tentative about this. 3. Sandra Edwards, “The Realism of Aquinas,” The New Scholasticism 59 (1985): 79; Paul Vincent Spade, “Degrees of Being, Degrees of Goodness,” in Aquinas’ Moral Theory, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • The Univocity of Substance and the Formal Distinction of Attributes: the Role of Duns Scotus in Deleuze's Reading of Spinoza Nathan Widder
    parrhesia 33 · 2020 · 150-176 the univocity of substance and the formal distinction of attributes: the role of duns scotus in deleuze's reading of spinoza nathan widder This paper examines the role played by medieval theologian John Duns Scotus in Gilles Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza’s philosophy of expressive substance; more generally, it elaborates a crucial moment in the development of Deleuze’s philosophy of sense and difference. Deleuze contends that Spinoza adapts and extends Duns Scotus’s two most influential theses, the univocity of being and formal distinction, despite neither appearing explicitly in Spinoza’s writings. “It takes nothing away from Spinoza’s originality,” Deleuze declares, “to place him in a perspective that may already be found in Duns Scotus” (Deleuze, 1992, 49).1 Nevertheless, the historiographic evidence is clearly lacking, leaving Deleuze to admit that “it is hardly likely that” Spinoza had even read Duns Scotus (359n28). Indeed, the only support he musters for his speculation is Spinoza’s obvious in- terests in scholastic metaphysical and logical treatises, the “probable influence” of the Scotist-informed Franciscan priest Juan de Prado on his thought, and the fact that the problems Duns Scotus addresses need not be confined to Christian thought (359–360n28). The paucity of evidence supporting this “use and abuse” of history, however, does not necessarily defeat the thesis. Like other lineages Deleuze proposes, the one he traces from Duns Scotus to Spinoza, and subsequently to Nietzsche, turns not on establishing intentional references by one thinker to his predecessor, but instead on showing how the borrowings and adaptations asserted to create the connec- tion make sense of the way the second philosopher surmounts blockages he faces while responding to issues left unaddressed by the first.
    [Show full text]
  • John Duns Scotus's Metaphysics of Goodness
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 11-16-2015 John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13th-Century Metaethics Jeffrey W. Steele University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Medieval History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Steele, Jeffrey W., "John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13th-Century Metaethics" (2015). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/6029 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13 th -Century Metaethics by Jeffrey Steele A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Colin Heydt, Ph.D. Joanne Waugh, Ph.D Date of Approval: November 12, 2015 Keywords: Medieval Philosophy, Transcendentals, Being, Aquinas Copyright © 2015, Jeffrey Steele DEDICATION To the wife of my youth, who with patience and long-suffering endured much so that I might gain a little knowledge. And to God, fons de bonitatis . She encouraged me; he sustained me. Both have blessed me. “O taste and see that the LORD is good; How blessed is the man who takes refuge in Him!!” --Psalm 34:8 “You are the boundless good, communicating your rays of goodness so generously, and as the most lovable being of all, every single being in its own way returns to you as its ultimate end.” –John Duns Scotus, De Primo Principio Soli Deo Gloria .
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary
    CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary Augustine Aurelius Augustinus Hipponensis (henceforth Augustine) was born in 354 A.D. in the municipium of Thagaste (modern day Souk Ahras, Algeria, close to the border with Tunisia). He died in 430, as the Arian1 Vandals besieged the city of Hippo where he was bishop, marking another stage in the demise of the Roman Empire. Rome had already been sacked in 410 by Alaric the Visigoth, but the slow decline of Roman grandeur took place over a period of about 320 years which culminated in 476 when Romulus Augustus, the last Emperor of the Western Roman Empire, was deposed by Odoacer, a Germanic chieftain. Augustine thus lived at a time which heralded the death knell of the ancient world and the beginnings of mediaeval western European Christendom.2 Augustine‘s great legacy to western civilization is that intellectually he united both worlds in drawing from the ancient thought of Greece and Rome and providing a Christian understanding of the intellectual achievements of the ancients. His new synthesis is a remarkable achievement even today and for those of us, who remain Christians in the West, our debates, agreements and disagreements are still pursued in Augustine‘s shadow.3 1 Arianism was a schismatic sect of Christianity that held the view that the Second Person of the Trinity, Christ, is created and thus does not exist eternally with the Father. 2 See J. M. Rist‘s magnificent Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2003. Rist notes that, ‗Despite his lack of resources he managed to sit in judgment on ancient philosophy and ancient culture.‘ p.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel on the Conceivability of Self-Determination
    The Concept as Self-Determination: Hegel on the Conceivability of Self- Determination Herein I investigate how four dogmas underpinning the traditional concepts of universality, the genus, class, and abstract universal, generate four paradoxes of self- reference. The four dogmas are the following: (1) that contradiction entails the total absence of determinacy, (2) the necessary finitude of the concept, (3) the separation of principles of universality and particularity, and (4) the necessity of appealing to foundations. In section III I show how these dogmas underpin the paradoxes of self-reference, and how one cannot make progress on these paradoxes as long as these four dogmas are in place. Corresponding to the abovementioned dogmas are the four paradoxes of self-reference: (1a) the problem of the differentia, (1b) the problem of psychologism, (3c) the problem of participation, and (4d) the problem of onto-theology. Section I enumerates the three traditional concepts of the concept and some of the basic limitations to which they are subject. Section II elucidates the four dogmas shared by these concepts. Finally, Section III shows how four paradoxes of self-reference follow from the dogmas elucidated in Section II. Though philosophers have been struggling with these problems for centuries, philosophers have never systematically connected each of these problems nor have philosophers derived them all from a single principle. It is my contention that the four paradoxes of self-reference are systematically connected insofar as they all follow from a single principle.1 This principle is formal universality. Though I do not provide a solution to these paradoxes, in Section III I suggest that the history of Western philosophy has already provided us with the only two viable ways to eschew these paradoxes.
    [Show full text]
  • Proof for the Existence of God Developed by Saint Augustine
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1948 The "Psychological" Proof For the Existence of God Developed By Saint Augustine Patrick J. Kremer Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Kremer, Patrick J., "The "Psychological" Proof For the Existence of God Developed By Saint Augustine" (1948). Master's Theses. 250. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/250 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1948 Patrick J. Kremer THE 11 PSYCHOLOGI CAL" PROOF FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD DEVELOPED BY SAINT AUGUSTINE BY PATRICK J. KREMER, S.J. • A THESIS SUmiTTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQ.UIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE 01<' MASTER OF ARTS IN LOYOLA UNIVERSITY DEC:D.1BER 1948 VITA AUCTORIS Patrick J. Kremer, S.J., was born in Detroit, Michigan, June 25, 1919. He attended Visitation Grammar School, and in June, 1935, was graduated from Visitation High School, Detroit, Michigan. In September, 1935, he entered the University of Detroit, from which he received the degree of Bachelor of Arts in June, 1939. He entered the Milford Novitiate of the Society of Jesus in September, 1939, and spent three years there. He studied at West Baden College Branch of Loyola University from 1942 to 1944, and has been enrolled in the Loyola University Graduate School since September, 1942.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind, Body, Motion, Matter Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives Edited by Mary Helen Mcmurran and Alison Conway MIND, BODY, MOTION, MATTER
    Mind, Body, Motion, Matter Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives edited by Mary Helen McMurran and Alison Conway MIND, BODY, MOTION, MATTER Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives Mind, Body, Motion, Matter Eighteenth-Century British and French Literary Perspectives EDITED BY MARY HELEN MCMURRAN AND ALISON CONWAY UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO PRESS Toronto Buffalo London © University of Toronto Press 2016 Toronto Buffalo London www.utppublishing.com Printed in the U.S.A. ISBN 978-1-4426-5011-4 (cloth) Printed on acid-free, 100% post-consumer recycled paper with vegetable-based inks. ___________________________________________________________________ Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication Mind, body, motion, matter : eighteenth-century British and French literary perspectives / edited by Mary Helen McMurran and Alison Conway. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-4426-5011-4 (cloth) 1. English literature – 18th century – History and criticism. 2. French literature – 18th century – History and criticism. 3. Philosophy in literature. 4. Materialism in literature. 5. Vitalism in literature. 6. Aesthetics in literature. I. Conway, Alison Margaret, editor II. McMurran, Mary Helen, 1962–, author, editor PR448.P5M55 2016 820.9'384 C2015-908168-8 ___________________________________________________________________ CC-BY-NC-ND This work is published subject to a Creative Commons Attribution Non-commercial No Derivative License. For permission to publish commercial versions please
    [Show full text]
  • The Mind–Body Problem: an Overview
    The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Chapter 1 The Mind–Body Problem: An Overview Kirk Ludwig I have said that the soul is not more than the body, And I have said that the body is not more than the soul, And nothing, not God, is greater to one than one’s self is. Walt Whitman 1.1 Introduction Understanding the place of thought and feeling in the natural world is central to that general comprehension of nature, as well as that special self-understanding, which are the primary goals of science and philosophy. The general form of the project, which has exercised scientists and philosophers since the ancient world, is given by the question, ‘What is the relation, in general, between mental and physical phenomena?’ There is no settled agreement on the correct answer. This is the single most important gap in our understanding of the natural world. The trouble is that the question presents us with a problem: each possible answer to it has consequences that appear unacceptable. This problem has traditionally gone under the heading ‘The Mind–Body Problem.’1 My primary aim in this chapter is to explain in what this traditional mind–body problem consists, what its possible solutions are, and what obstacles lie in the way of a resolution. The discussion will develop in two phases. The first phase, sections 1.2–1.4, will be concerned to get clearer about the import of our initial question as a precondition of developing an account of possible responses to it. The second phase, sections 1.5–1.6, explains how a problem arises in our attempts to answer the question we have characterized, and surveys the various solutions that can be and have been offered.
    [Show full text]
  • 2:00-4:00 Pm Session 1A: Theandrites: Byzantine Philosophy
    Thursday, June 10, 2021 (All times are in the time zone of Athens.) 2:00-4:00 p.m. Session 1a: Theandrites: Byzantine Philosophy and Christian Platonism Frederick Laurtizen <[email protected]> and Sarah Klitenic Wear <[email protected]> Panagiotis Pavlos <[email protected]>, University of Oslo, Platonism and Christian Thought: A System in Phase Transition; An Approach to the Contributions of Vassilios Tatakis and fr. John Romanides” Fernandez Marco Alviz <[email protected]>, National University of Distance Learning, UNED, Madrid, “Χάρισμα and παιδεία in Late Antiquity: From Neoplatonic circles to Christian thought in the 3rd and 4th centuries” Chris Chris Barnard <[email protected]>, Newman University, “The Good and Evil λόγοι Dialectic in Saint Maximus the Confessor” Evi Zacharia <[email protected]>, Radboud University Nijmegen, “Commentary on Alcibiades I: towards an explanation of human perfection through love” Session 1b: Plotinus and Proclus Marcin Podbielski <[email protected]> Paolo Di Leo <[email protected]>, Singapore University of Technology and Design, “Plotinus and Heidegger: A Dialogue Through Parmenides’ R. B3” Marcin Podbielski <[email protected]>, Jesuit University Ignatianum, “Revisiting the Text, Grammar, and Translations of Plotinus’s On Contemplation” Martin Lee Mueller <[email protected]>, University of Oslo, “Deep Ecology and Telling About Nature” Zdenek Lenner, <[email protected]>, École Pratique des Hautes
    [Show full text]
  • Park, Sam-Yel (1999) a Study of the Mind-Body Theory in Spinoza. Phd Thesis. Copyright and Moral R
    Park, Sam-Yel (1999) A study of the mind-body theory in Spinoza. PhD thesis. http://theses.gla.ac.uk/2040/ Copyright and moral rights for this thesis are retained by the author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the Author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the Author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Glasgow Theses Service http://theses.gla.ac.uk/ [email protected] A Study of the Mind-Body Theory in Spinoza Departmentof Philosophy University of Glasgow A Study of Theory in Spinoza the pffindýBody by Sam-Yel Park A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of Arts in Fulfilment of the Requirementsfor the degreeof Doctor of Philosophy June 1999 C Sam-Yel Park 1999 Abstract A Study of the Mind-Body Theory in Spinoza by Sam-Yel Park This thesis investigates Spinoza's mind-body theory starting with the discussion of the diverse interpretations of his mind-body theory such as hylomorphism.,idealism, epiphenomenalism,and materialism. From the critical comments on inadequaciesof these interpretations, it turns out that Spinoza's argumentof the relationshipbetween the mind and the body should be understood as holding that there is a non-causalrelationship between the mind and the body and that they have equal weight.
    [Show full text]
  • New Scholasticism
    VoV VI U No. 1 THE NEW SCHOLASTICISM A QUARTERLY REVIEW OF PHILOSOPHY JANUARY, 1932 I. The " De Differentia Rhetoricae, Ethicae et Politicae " of Aegidius Romanus GERARDO BRUNI II. Plato's Doctrine of Temperance JOHN A. MOURANT III. The Theory of Divine Illumination in St. Bonaventura p. J. McANDREW IV. BOOK REVIEWS D'Arcy, The Nature of Belief, by Martin J. Healy; D'Arcy and Others, A Monument to St. Augustine, by Thomas J. Shahan; 8. Agostino: Pubblicazione Commemorativa del XV Centenario della Sua Morte, by Joseph P. Christopher; Grabmann, Die Werke des hi. Thomas von Aquin and Flatten, Die Philosophie des Wilhelm von Conches, by Gerald B. Phelan; Hirsch, Genius and Creative Intelligence, by J. Edward Rauth; Lehu, La Raison B«gle de la Morality d'apres Saint Thomas, by Virgil Michel; Schmaus, Liber Propugnatorius des Thomas Anglieus und die Lehrunterschiede zwischen Thomas von Aquin und Duns Scotus, by Conrad O'Leary; Farrell, The Natural Law, According to St. Thomas and Suarez; John Dewey, The Man and His Philosophy, and Dewey, Construction and Criticism, by Virgil Michel; Colle, Aristote, Traductions et fitudes, by James Marshall Campbell; Jennings, The Biologi­ cal Basis of Human Nature, by Cornelius J. Connolly. V. CURRENT PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEWS AND BOOK NOTES CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY PRESS PUBLISHERS EUROPEAN REPRESENTATIVE A. LORENT? KURPRINZSTRASSE, 10, LEIPZIG, GERMANY SINGLE COPIES $1.00 PER ANNUM $4-00 APR 18 1932 THE NEW SCHOLASTICISM A QUARTERLY REVIEW OF PHILOSOPHY APRIL, 1932 I. The Starting-Point of Epiatemology JOHN J. TOOHKY n. Snarez: De Anima GEORGE H. HAHOWALD III. Mathematics and Philosophy DANIEL C.
    [Show full text]