Pragmatism and the Dao: Laozi Versus Zhuangzi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pragmatism and the Dao: Laozi Versus Zhuangzi Who is the more Pragmatic Daoist – Laozi or Zhuangzi? In recent years, a philosophical position that was introduced in the late nineteenth century – known as pragmatism – has again become the vogue. In the world of academic philosophy, thinkers such as Richard Bernstein, James Conant, Hilary Putnam and Richard Rorty have brought it back into the mainstream of American thought. In the popular media, the word has been used with increasing frequency, especially in reference to President Barack Obama (albeit in a sense at which many professional philosophers might balk). Simply put, pragmatism has become a buzz word, and this rise in its popularity may help explain yet another increase – viz. in the number of philosophers outside of the United States, and from disparate schools of thought, who are being labeled “pragmatic” in recent scholarship. The area of philosophy which focuses on east-west comparison has seen such an increase, as well. Respected professionals like Roger Ames, Richard Shusterman, and Chad Hansen (among others) have given well researched and reasonable accounts of how various Chinese philosophies resonate with pragmatic themes. Interestingly, much of this work tends to focus on the Confucian tradition more than the school of thought known as Daoism. In what follows, I should like to offer a heuristic for this type of (admittedly anachronistic) consideration within the philosophies of the two most prominent daoist sages – Laozi and Zhuangzi. When applying the term pragmatism to thinkers who, like Laozi and Zhuangzi, are far removed from it in time and space, it is vitally important to make clear what is meant by ‘pragmatism.’ Like any “-ism,” pragmatism has been so overused that it has been rendered nearly vacuous in contemporary discourse. Pragmatism has traversed a 1 rougher road than most, though, as it has been used, on occasion, to identify seemingly contradictory positions.1 Moreover, in public consciousness, pragmatism has taken on a separate, non-technical meaning that is almost completely antithetical to its technical uses. Clearly, pragmatism seems to resist attempts at succinct definition, however, one angle of attack might be a delineation of the features that set pragmatism apart from other schools of thought. Thus, before turning our attention to which Daoist should be considered more pragmatic, some clean-up work is in order. Pragmatism grew up in a tumultuous time in American history, when thinkers were grasping at theoretical straws, hoping to find a way to make sense of the political and intellectual turmoil. It is often referred to as the only school of thought native to American soil. The commonly told story names Cambridge as its birthplace, where a group of young Harvard intellectuals (including C.S. Peirce, Oliver Wendell Holmes, and William James) met to discuss philosophy and science. Peirce is credited with coining the term pragmatism, Holmes with applying it to the law, James with popularizing its philosophical tenets and John Dewey – a student of Peirce and correspondent of James – with correcting many of its initial shortcomings. But, this account is simplistic and somewhat inaccurate, as pragmatism did not arise ex nihilo (springing up out of the ground) but instead brought together aspects of many other schools of thought, many of them just as “American” in origin. Hilary Putnam, for one, has argued that pragmatism can be distinguished by four basic theses: 1) antiskepticism, 2) fallibilism, 3) distrust of the fact/value distinction, and 1 Cf. the uses of pragmatism by contemporary thinkers like Richard Rorty and Susan Haack, or A.O. Lovejoy’s famous polemic of “The Thirteen Pragmatisms” 2 4) an assertion that “practice is primary in philosophy.”2 Yet, it should be noted that pragmatism shares an emphasis on philosophical practicality with one of its precursors, transcendentalism, which came into its own with Emerson’s 1836 essay “Nature.” This fact has sometimes been overlooked in the literature but is significant nonetheless because transcendentalism laid the groundwork for pragmatism in several ways. With the appearance of Emerson’s Phi Beta Kappa Address entitled “The American Scholar,” transcendentalism made the first declaration of American intellectual independence. Many of the transcendentalists – most notably Thoreau and Margaret Fuller – published tracts on social and political issues of the day in addition to their philosophical offerings. Perhaps most importantly, the transcendentalists had a strong influence on the childhood of both Peirce and James, whose fathers were active in the social circles of the transcendentalist movement. Pragmatism also shares its antiskepticism and mistrust of the fact/value distinction with another American movement known as naturalism. While many pragmatists adopted some form of naturalist sentiments, the two lines of thought remain distinguishable. Naturalism, as the term was used during that time, was primarily an ontological view, whereas pragmatism was seen as more of an epistemological position. Historically, there have been self-identified naturalists who were not pragmatists (George Santayana) just as there have been pragmatists who did not subscribe to naturalism (Josiah Royce). Thus, the only one of Putnam’s four theses that might be unique to pragmatism is its fallibilism, and though it certainly is a feature of other philosophies, pragmatism offers perhaps the only systematic treatment of the idea – viz. Peirce’s notion of inquiry, which 2 Putnam, Hilary. “Pragmatism and Moral Objectivity.” In Words and Life. Ed. by J. Conant (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994) pg. 152 3 was later expounded upon by Dewey. In a nutshell, their view drew heavily upon philosophical realizations about the scientific method. As Peirce put it, “In sciences in which men come to agreement, when a theory has been broached it is considered to be on probation until this agreement is reached.”3 Dewey echoed this sentiment, years later, with his instrumentalist view, which called for philosophers to give up their hopeless “quest for certainty.”4 On their view, the search for knowledge was a ceaseless endeavor, and, as such, those who took it up were required to continuously revise and adjust their beliefs. It would seem that while Putnam’s four theses are necessary conditions in calling a particular view pragmatic, a robust fallibilism might be the only one that is sufficient as well. In the very least it seems to be the deciding factor for determining if any particular thinker can properly be called pragmatic. Therefore, using Putnam’s work as a heuristic device, we might better discern which daoist sage offered the more pragmatic vision. I will begin my analysis of pragmatism and the dào with Laozi, who is traditionally believed to be Zhuangzi’s predecessor.5 According to legend, when Laozi was asked to put his ideas on paper by a border official in exchange for passage, he penned the Dàodéjīng [道德經]. A collection of 81 chapters in verse form, the Dàodéjīng (or “Classic of the Way and Virtue”) is considered the most important text in the Daoist canon. The main topics of the text are the metaphysics of dào [道], or “the way,” and how these notions can be applied in moral life to attain “virtue,” i.e. dé [德]. Commentators have disagreed about which of these two components is the main focus of the text. Those 3 Peirce, C.S. “The Rules of Philosophy,” from Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1934) pgs 156-158 4 cf. Dewey, John. The Quest for Certainty – The Collected Works of John Dewey, 1882-1953. 37 volumes. (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967-1987) LW 4 5 Although the accuracy of this claim has been called into question more recently, my objective is to analyze the philosophical notions only, and therefore I will follow the canonical account throughout the remainder of this essay. 4 who give primacy to the former, typically interpret the Dàodéjīng as a mystical document, whereas their opponents usually view it as a moral treatise. Evidence of this debate can be found in the various translations of the first line of the text, which reads (in the Hanyu Pinyin romanization) dào kě dào fēi cháng dào6, which is most often translated along the lines of, “The way that can be spoken of is not the constant Way.”7 This may be seen as a declaration of the ineffability of dào, and ipso facto, evidence for a mystical reading. However, another way to read this first line might be, “The path worth following is not an unchanging one.” This would render the text not as an endorsement of ineffability, but rather as advancing a normative principle intended to show that the best course (or dào) of action is one that is open to revision, which would seem to be the epitome of fallibilism. For now, I will leave this issue aside in order to focus on other passages from the text that seem to relate to pragmatist precepts. The most obvious feature that the Dàodéjīng shares in common with pragmatism is the dissolution of the fact/value distinction, i.e. the separation of descriptive from prescriptive claims. Chinese philosophy, in general, tends to be far less dualistic than its Western counterpart, and Daoism is perhaps the most holistic of all the major Chinese schools of thought. The theme permeates the Dàodéjīng. For example, in chapter 42, we are told that living organisms are the embodiment of nature’s generative forces (yīn and yáng) and thus doing violence against them inevitably leads to an unnatural end. However, the passage that is most indicative of Laozi’s aversion to an “is-ought” dichotomy is found in Chapter 51, which reads, “the way is revered and virtue honored 6 Literally: “Way worthy of Way, not unchanging Way.” 7 Laozi, Tao Te Ching.
Recommended publications
  • Teaching for Apostasy: How Educational Methods and Philosophies Work Against the Church
    The Lutheran Clarion – July 2018 (Volume 10, Issue 6) Teaching for Apostasy: How Educational Methods and Philosophies Work Against the Church Dr. Thomas Korcok gave the presentation below at the 2018 Lutheran Concerns Association conference in Fort Wayne, IN, in January 2018. Since that time it has been slightly revised. Currently in colleges of education across America, almost all future teachers learn from a standard canon of educational thinkers whose work forms the basis for the goals, methods, and structure of the modern American classroom. When students are introduced to these educationists, there is rarely, if ever, any consideration given to what they taught, believed, or confessed in their personal lives. Furthermore, their theories are presented as though they were all based purely on unbiased scientific research. Such an approach should be of concern for the Christian because it is radically different from how the church has traditionally measured teachers. In the history of Western education until the 20th century, (which has always been inseparably linked with Christian education), theology has been the measuring stick for all areas of knowledge, including education. A teacher’s confession of faith was always considered to be the first criterion in judging whether or not his or her teaching was acceptable. In the 16th century, the influential Lutheran educator, Valentin Trotzendorf, insisted that “Those who belong to our school, let the same also be members of our Church and those who agree with our faith, which is most sure and true; because of perhaps one godless person out of the whole body, some evil happens.” 1 In this day and age, we are to believe that the contrary teaching is true: that what a researcher teaches, believes, and confesses has little or nothing to do with the methods he advocates.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Norms and Social Influence Mcdonald and Crandall 149
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Social norms and social influence Rachel I McDonald and Christian S Crandall Psychology has a long history of demonstrating the power and and their imitation is not enough to implicate social reach of social norms; they can hardly be overestimated. To norms. Imitation is common enough in many forms of demonstrate their enduring influence on a broad range of social life — what creates the foundation for culture and society phenomena, we describe two fields where research continues is not the imitation, but the expectation of others for when to highlight the power of social norms: prejudice and energy imitation is appropriate, and when it is not. use. The prejudices that people report map almost perfectly onto what is socially appropriate, likewise, people adjust their A social norm is an expectation about appropriate behav- energy use to be more in line with their neighbors. We review ior that occurs in a group context. Sherif and Sherif [8] say new approaches examining the effects of norms stemming that social norms are ‘formed in group situations and from multiple groups, and utilizing normative referents to shift subsequently serve as standards for the individual’s per- behaviors in social networks. Though the focus of less research ception and judgment when he [sic] is not in the group in recent years, our review highlights the fundamental influence situation. The individual’s major social attitudes are of social norms on social behavior. formed in relation to group norms (pp. 202–203).’ Social norms, or group norms, are ‘regularities in attitudes and Address behavior that characterize a social group and differentiate Department of Psychology, University of Kansas, Lawrence, KS 66045, it from other social groups’ [9 ] (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    1 Introduction Reading Democracy and Education DAVID T. HANSEN What is John Dewey’s Democracy and Education? In a literal sense, it is a study of education and its relation to the individual and society. More- over, Dewey tells us, it is a philosophical rather than historical, sociologi- cal, or political inquiry. His original title for the work was An Introduction to the Philosophy of Education. That was the heading he had in view when he signed a contract to undertake the project on July 21, 1911, with the Macmillan Company of New York (MW.9.377). However, his publishers convinced him to change the title in light of pressing political issues triggered by the cataclysm of World War I. Dewey completed the text in August 1915, and it came out the following year with his original title converted into a subtitle. The book constitutes Dewey’s philosophical response to the rapid social, economic, political, cultural, and technologi- cal change he was witness to over the course of his long life. Born in 1859, when the United States was largely an agrarian society, by the time Dewey pens his educational treatise the country had become an indus- trial, urban world undergoing endless and often jarring transformations, a process that continues unabated through the present. Dewey sought to articulate and justify the education he believed people needed to com- prehend and shape creatively and humanely these unstoppable changes. At the same time, Dewey endeavored in the book to respond to what many critics regard as the two most influential educational works ever written prior to the twentieth century: Plato’s Republic (fourth 1 © 2006 State University of New York Press, Albany 2 John Dewey and Our Educational Prospect century B.C.E.) and Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s Emile (published in 1762).
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Pragmatism and Scientific Realism Author(S): Cleo H
    Notes on Pragmatism and Scientific Realism Author(s): Cleo H. Cherryholmes Source: Educational Researcher, Vol. 21, No. 6, (Aug. - Sep., 1992), pp. 13-17 Published by: American Educational Research Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1176502 Accessed: 02/05/2008 14:02 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aera. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Notes on Pragmatismand Scientific Realism CLEOH. CHERRYHOLMES Ernest R. House's article "Realism in plicit declarationof pragmatism. Here is his 1905 statement ProfessorResearch" (1991) is informative for the overview it of it: of scientificrealism.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Magic That Can Set You Free': the Ideology of Folk and the Myth of the Rock Community
    The magic that can set you free': the ideology of folk and the myth of the rock community by SIMON FRITH Rock, the saying goes, is 'the folk music of our time'. Not from a sociological point of view. If 'folk' describes pre-capitalist modes of music production, rock is, without a doubt, a mass-produced, mass- consumed, commodity. The rock-folk argument, indeed, is not about how music is made, but about how it works: rock is taken to express (or reflect) a way of life; rock is used by its listeners as a folk music - it articulates communal values, comments on shared social problems. The argument, in other words, is about subcultures rather than music- making; the question of how music comes to represent its listeners is begged. (I develop these arguments further in Frith 1978, pp. 191-202, and, with particular reference to punk rock, in Frith 1980.) In this article I am not going to answer this question either. My concern is not whether rock is or is not a folk music, but is with the effects of a particular account of popular culture - the ideology of folk - on rock's interpretation of itself. For the rock ideologues of the 1960s - musicians, critics and fans alike - rock 'n' roll's status as a folk music was what differentiated it from routine pop; it was as a folk music that rock could claim a distinctive political and artistic edge. The argument was made, for example, by Jon Landau in his influential role as reviews editor and house theorist of Rolling Stone.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Foundations CEEF6301 New Orleans Baptist Theological Seminary Christian Education Division Spring 2017 Online
    Philosophical Foundations CEEF6301 New Orleans Baptist Theological Seminary Christian Education Division Spring 2017 Online Emily Dean, Ph.D. Adjunct Professor, Christian Education Coordinator of Women’s Programs Office: (504) 282-4455 ext.8053 Email: [email protected] Mission Statement The mission of New Orleans Baptist Theological Seminary is to equip leaders to fulfill the Great Commission and the Great Commandments through the local church and its ministries. Core Value Focus The seminary has five core values. 1. Doctrinal Integrity: Knowing that the Bible is the Word of God, we believe it, teach it, proclaim it, and submit to it. This course addresses Doctrinal Integrity specifically by preparing students to grow in understanding and interpreting of the Bible. 2. Spiritual Vitality: We are a worshiping community emphasizing both personal spirituality and gathering together as a Seminary family for the praise and adoration of God and instruction in His Word. Spiritual Vitality is addressed by reminding students that a dynamic relationship with God is vital for effective ministry. 3. Mission Focus: We are not here merely to get an education or to give one. We are here to change the world by fulfilling the Great Commission and the Great Commandments through the local church and its ministries. This course addresses Mission Focus by helping students understand the biblical foundations for fulfilling the Great Commission and the Great Commandments. 4. Characteristic Excellence: What we do, we do to the utmost of our abilities and resources as a testimony to the glory of our Lord and Savior Jesus Christ. Characteristic Excellence is addressed by preparing students to excel in their ability to interpret Scripture, which is foundational to effective ministry.
    [Show full text]
  • Ideology: the Challenge for Civic Literacy Educators by James A
    Volume 1, Issue 1 http://journals.iupui.edu/index.php/civiclit/index July 2014 Ideology: The Challenge for Civic Literacy Educators By James A. Duplass ABSTRACT: Commitment to open-mindedness, critical thinking, liberty, and social justice are proposed as four pillars of a democratic ideology. The highly charged and polarized discourse between left and right po- litical ideology among the media, politicians, educators, and public has intensified the challenge placed on social studies educators to transmit these goals to their students. A rendition of the philosophical trajectory of the ideas of liberty, social justice, and justice are provided and married with concepts from the philosophical foundations of American education, social studies education goals and strategies, and contemporary human- istic philosophy so as to articulate a new case that transmission of a democratic ideology is at the core of social studies education. The proposition is made that teaching social studies is unique because the development of an ideology requires teachers’ attention to values, virtues formation, and the liberation of the individual. Keywords: Ideology, critical thinking, liberty, social justice, justice The purpose of this essay is to explore the largely unexamined idea of a democratic ideology as an inherent goal of social studies education. The traditional meaning of competency and literacy established by many disciplines including social studies education (Duplass, 2006) do not fully convey the unique mission of social studies education to pass on an ideology - belief system - to successive generations. The formation of values (Apple, 2004; Duplass, 2008; McCarthy, 1994), the use of critical thinking (Dewey, 1890/1969), and July 2014 Ideology: The Challenge for Civic Literacy Educators 1 the goal of passing on democratic traditions (Dewey, 1939/1976; National Council for Social Studies, 2008) serve as an intersection for the formation of a democratic ideology, although such a term is seldom found in the social studies literature.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Spirituality?
    fact sheets What is spirituality? Recognising the difference between spirituality and religion can be a great way to begin to understand what spirituality means to different people. There are many types of spirituality that people sometimes base their beliefs around and also many different reasons people practice spirituality. Spirituality is something that’s often debated and commonly misunderstood. Many people confuse spirituality with religion and so bring pre–existing beliefs about the impact of religion to discussions about spirituality. Though all religions emphasise spirituality as being an important part of faith, it’s possible to be ‘spiritual’ without necessarily being a part of an organised religious community. This might help if... What’s the difference between religion and › You’re looking for spirituality? information on spirituality Spirituality and religion can be hard to tell apart but there are some pretty defined differences between the two. › You want to know Religion is a specific set of organised beliefs and practices, usually shared the difference between by a community or group. spirituality and religion Spirituality is more of an individual practice and has to do with having a › You’d like to become a sense of peace and purpose. It also relates to the process of developing more spiritual person beliefs around the meaning of life and connection with others. One way that might help you to understand the relationship between Take action... spirituality and religion is imagine a game of football. The rules, referees, other players, and field markings help guide you as you play the game in › Learn more about a similar way that religion might guide you to find your spirituality.
    [Show full text]
  • THINKING with MENTAL MODELS 63 and Implementation
    Thinking with CHAPTER 3 mental models When we think, we generally use concepts that we it would be impossible for people to make most deci- have not invented ourselves but that reflect the shared sions in daily life. And without shared mental models, understandings of our community. We tend not to it would be impossible in many cases for people to question views when they reflect an outlook on the develop institutions, solve collective action problems, world that is shared by everyone around us. An impor- feel a sense of belonging and solidarity, or even under- tant example for development pertains to how people stand one another. Although mental models are often view the need to provide cognitive stimulation to shared and arise, in part, from human sociality (chapter children. In many societies, parents take for granted 2), they differ from social norms, which were discussed that their role is to love their children and keep them in the preceding chapter. Mental models, which need safe and healthy, but they do not view young children not be enforced by direct social pressure, often capture as needing extensive cognitive and linguistic stimu- broad ideas about how the world works and one’s place lation. This view is an example of a “mental model.”1 in it. In contrast, social norms tend to focus on particu- In some societies, there are even norms against verbal lar behaviors and to be socially enforced. There is immense variation in mental models across societies, including different perceptions of Mental models help people make sense of the way the world “works.” Individuals can adapt their mental models, updating them when they learn that the world—to interpret their environment outcomes are inconsistent with expectations.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Belief Functions
    Introduction to belief functions Thierry Denœux Université de Technologie de Compiègne, France HEUDIASYC (UMR CNRS 7253) https://www.hds.utc.fr/˜tdenoeux Fourth School on Belief Functions and their Applications Xi’An, China, July 5, 2017 Thierry Denœux Introduction to belief functions July 5, 2017 1 / 77 Contents of this lecture 1 Historical perspective, motivations 2 Fundamental concepts: belief, plausibility, commonality, conditioning, basic combination rules 3 Some more advanced concepts: cautious rule, multidimensional belief functions, belief functions in infinite spaces Thierry Denœux Introduction to belief functions July 5, 2017 2 / 77 Uncertain reasoning In science and engineering we always need to reason with partial knowledge and uncertain information (from sensors, experts, models, etc.) Different sources of uncertainty Variability of entities in populations and outcomes of random (repeatable) experiments ! Aleatory uncertainty. Example: drawing a ball from an urn. Cannot be reduced Lack of knowledge ! Epistemic uncertainty. Example: inability to distinguish the color of a ball because of color blindness. Can be reduced Classical ways of representing uncertainty 1 Using probabilities 2 Using set (e.g., interval analysis), or propositional logic Thierry Denœux Introduction to belief functions July 5, 2017 3 / 77 Probability theory Probability theory can be used to represent Aleatory uncertainty: probabilities are considered as objective quantities and interpreted as frequencies or limits of frequencies Epistemic uncertainty:
    [Show full text]
  • Social Norms and the Enforcement of Laws
    SOCIAL NORMS AND THE ENFORCEMENT OF LAWS Daron Acemoglu Matthew O. Jackson Massachusetts Institute of Technology Stanford University, and Santa Fe Institute Abstract We examine the interplay between social norms and the enforcement of laws. Agents choose a behavior (e.g., tax evasion, production of low-quality products, corruption, harassing behavior, substance abuse, etc.) and then are randomly matched with another agent. There are complementarities in behaviors so that an agent’s payoff decreases with the mismatch between her behavior and her partner’s, and with overall negative externalities created by the behavior of others. A law is an upper bound (cap) on behavior. A law-breaker, when detected, pays a fine and has her behavior forced down to the level of the law. Equilibrium law-breaking depends on social norms because detection relies, at least in part, on whistle-blowing. Law-abiding agents have an incentive to whistle-blow on a law-breaking partner because this reduces the mismatch with their partners’ behaviors as well as the negative externalities. When laws are in conflict with norms and many agents are breaking the law, each agent anticipates little whistle-blowing and is more likely to also break the law. Tighter laws (banning more behaviors), greater fines, and better public enforcement, all have counteracting effects, reducing behavior among law-abiding individuals but increasing it among law-breakers. We show that laws that are in strong conflict with prevailing social norms may backfire, whereas gradual tightening of laws can be more effective in influencing social norms and behavior. (JEL: C72, C73, P16, Z1) 1.
    [Show full text]
  • An Exploratory Analysis of John Dewey's Writings: Implications for School Leaders
    An Exploratory Analysis of John Dewey's Writings: Implications for School Leaders Larry J. Moss and Anthony H. Normore Florida International University, USA Abstract: The purpose of this study was to synthesize the operational definition of education through an exploratory analysis of John Dewey’s writings. Dewey’s definition of education changed from 1938 to 1896. Findings suggest that schools promote more social and emotional learning through instructional activities such as service-learning. In 1776, Thomas Jefferson penned the following words, perhaps the most inspiring sentence in American language: "We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all Men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the Pursuit of Happiness” (as cited in Cannon, 2004, p.13). How does education contribute to an understanding of the pursuit of happiness? John Dewey saw many ethical implications among education, democracy, happiness and social service. Dewey wrote in Education and experience (1938/1998): “We always live at the time we live and not at some other time, and only by extracting at each present time the full meaning of each present experience are we prepared for doing the same thing in the future” (p.51). Method Primary writings of John Dewey are highlighted in this historical paper, including The school and society (1896); The child and the curriculum (1902); Democracy and education (1916); and Experience and education (1938/ 1998). Additionally, several anthologies were explored, including The Philosophy of John Dewey, Volume I; The structure of experience, Volume II; The lived experience (McDermott, 1981), and Classic and contemporary readings in the philosophy of education (Cahn, 1997).
    [Show full text]