Introduction 1 What Motivated Hegel's Philosophical Project?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction 1 What Motivated Hegel's Philosophical Project? Notes Introduction 1 . PH 472. 1 What Motivated Hegel’s Philosophical Project? 1 . In recent decades, several important attempts have been made to fill this lacuna – the absence of a post-Kantian schema – the most salient of which has been that of Henrich (1982, 1991, 2003), who revisits the story of the genesis of German Idealism. See too Horstmann (1991). 2 . The English-speaking world has of late experienced a resurgence of interest in German Idealism, especially Hegel, attested to by the numerous books and articles on the subject published over the past decade. Although these studies are far from monolithic, we can safely say, without fear of over-simplification, that the interpretations offered tend to see Hegel’s philosophy as the culmi- nation of Kant’s epistemological project. See Pippin (1997, 6); Pinkard (1994, 230). 3 . Let me pre-empt a possible misunderstanding. The rupture thesis does not, of course, seek to claim that German Idealism is altogether free of Kantian influ- ence, which would be absurd. The rupture thesis can also be formulated as follows: Kant is the source of the problem of Kantian dualism, and its solution requires total rejection of his philosophy, which must be supplanted by a new philosophical program. 4 . For a thorough defense of the philosophical importance of this question, see Düsing (1983); Pippin (1989); Henrich (1991); Horstmann (1991). 5 . This route is also chosen both by those who seek to show that German Idealism provides insight only into highly speculative epistemological or ontological questions, a claim that is patently indefensible, and by those who seek to show how Idealism sheds profound light on the flaws of the philosophy of subjectivity, and on how accepting the suggested remedy will render the theo- retical position espoused by German Idealism less vulnerable to critique. 6 . For the time being, I will accept the premise that the transition from Kant to Hegel was accompanied by a substantive change in the philosophic enterprise. This claim will be argued for below, when I describe the genesis of Hegel’s philosophy and the main problems it addresses. 7 . Although “German Idealism” is sometimes used very broadly as referring to post-Kantian philosophy in general, I use it here as shorthand for the philo- sophical activity of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. 8 . It is impossible to discuss German Idealism without using what is now consid- ered to be sexist language, as the pertinent texts are replete with gendered concepts, which were taken for granted in the language of the era. Readers must keep in mind, however, that despite the sexist language of the day, the 227 228 Notes authors in question did not take notions such as Menschheit to apply to males alone, but rather intended them to refer to all human beings. 9 . Taylor provides the best description of the genesis of this movement as part of the story of the emergence of Hegel’s philosophy; see Taylor (1975, 1979). Taylor suggests that Hegel’s thought should be seen as an attempt to systematically confront the foundational principles of the Enlightenment, on the one hand, and Romanticism, on the other, movements that espoused competing views of man. The Romantic principle of “expressivism” saw man as embedded in an organic natural and cultural context, within which he expresses his goals and desires. By contrast, the Enlightenment view of man, especially as formulated by Kant, sought to liberate man from this dual context of nature and culture, and see him as a rational individual. On this picture of man, the rational individual manifests radical self-determination that demands freedom from any external restrictions on him or his reason. Taylor understands Hegel as seeking to reconcile, as it were, these two incom- patible guiding principles, to connect the idea of man as embedded in a specific natural and cultural context with that of the individual demanding freedom. According to Taylor, Hegel saw no need to completely relinquish either of these pictures. 10 . See Berlin (1990, 1999). Berlin’s description of the origins of Hegelianism is the classic example of such a primarily historical and ideological reading. 11 . As noted, the number of studies that explore the systematic development of Hegel’s thought is prodigious. Even without surveying all of them, it is obvious that no one today disputes the claim that Hölderlin’s contribution was decisive. For a clear exposition of this thesis, see Jamme (1984, 15). 12 . For detailed discussion, see Henrich (1971, 1992); Harris (1983); Jamme and Schneider (1990). 13 . Schiller expounds this critique in three of his key works on aesthetics and ethics: “On Grace and Dignity” (1793); “On the Aesthetic Education of Man in a Series of Letters” (1795); and “On Naïve and Sentimental Poetry” (1795/96). To rectify the flaws in the Kantian approach to ethics, he invokes the aesthetic perspective, which, he contends, is a more appropriate frame- work for ethics, as it is applicable not only to man qua thinking being, but also qua agent and sentient being. 14 . See ELT 137. 15 . StA 6.1, p. 119. 16 . ELT 137. 17 . On the two works’ enormous influence on Hegel and Hölderlin, see Harris (1972, 109–111); Jamme (1983). 18 . AE, letter 27. 19 . Schiller states: “Closer attention to the character of our age will, however, reveal an astonishing contrast between the contemporary form of humanity and earlier ones, especially that of Greece. The reputation for culture and refinement on which we otherwise rightly pride ourselves vis-à-vis humanity in its merely natural state, can avail us nothing against the natural humanity of the Greeks. For they were wedded to all the delights of art and the dignity of wisdom, without however, like us, falling a prey to their seduction. ... This disorganization, which was first started within man by civilization and learning, was made complete and universal by the new spirit of government. Notes 229 It was scarcely to be expected that the simple organization of the early repub- lics should have survived the simplicity of early manners and conditions; but instead of rising to a higher form of organic existence it degenerated into a crude and clumsy mechanism. The polypoid character of the Greek States, in which every individual enjoyed an independent existence but could, when need arose, grow into the whole organism, now made way for an ingenious clock-work, in which, out of the piecing together of innumerable but lifeless parts, a mechanical kind of collective life ensued. State and the Church, laws and customs, were now torn asunder; enjoyment was divorced from labour, the means from the end, the effort from the reward. Everlastingly chained to a single little fragment of the Whole, man himself develops into nothing but a fragment; everlastingly in ear the monotonous sound of the wheel that he turns, he never develops the harmony of his being; and instead of putting the stamp of humanity upon his own nature, he becomes nothing more then the imprint of his occupation or of his specialized knowledge. But even the meagre, fragmentary participation, by which individual members of the State are still linked to the Whole, does not depend upon forms which they spontaneously prescribe for themselves ... it is dictated to them with meticulous exactitude by means of a formulary which inhibits all freedom of thought. The dead letter takes the place of living understanding, and a good memory is a safer guide than imagination and feeling” (AE, letter 6, 35). 20 . See AE, letter 11, 42–43, and see too letter 13, where Schiller asserts: “At the first sight nothing could seem more diametrically opposed than the tendencies of these two drives, the one pressing for change, the other for changelessness. And yet it is these two drives that between them, exhaust our concept of humanity, and make a third fundamental drive that might possibly reconcile the two a completely unthinkable concept.” He proceeds to pose the question that he takes to define the philosophical challenge at hand: “How, then, are we to restore the unity of human nature which seems to be utterly destroyed by this primary and radical opposition?” (AE 89). 21 . See AE, letter 27, last paragraph. 22 . See ELT 33–37. 23 . ELT 33–34. 24 . StA 3, 163. 25 . Hölderlin’s great enthusiasm for Fichte is revealed primarily through his correspondence from that period, especially with his friends from Tübingen, Schelling and Hegel. 26 . What is special about this text, which some scholars consider to be the first part of the version known as “Hyperion’s Youth,” is that Hölderlin attempts to write in verse using the metrical patterns of classical Greek poetry. However, it is unclear whether the metrical section is the first part of “Hyperion’s Youth,” or a separate, self-standing version. On the genesis and various versions of Hyperion , see Beissner’s introductory essay in his edition of Hölderlin’s collected works (StA). 27 . The fact that Hölderlin, and Hegel after him, adduce these lectures, is instruc- tive, as it shows that they viewed these polemical lectures – today we would characterize them as “ideological” – as no different from the lectures that make up the various versions of the Wissenschaftslehre , where the same ideas are formulated philosophically. What we tend to see as a significant 230 Notes difference between Fichte’s polemical-political writings, e.g., the Addresses to the German Nation , and his later theoretical work is, for Hölderlin and Hegel, simply irrelevant. 28 . Some interpretations suggest parallels between figures in the novel and Hölderlin’s contemporaries. Some take the scholar to be Fichte himself, and take Hyperion to be a disciple who seeks to actualize the ideals revealed by the scholar.
Recommended publications
  • Mentalism Versus Behaviourism in Economics: a Philosophy-Of-Science
    Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: aphilosophy-of-scienceperspective⇤ Franz Dietrich Christian List CNRS & University of East Anglia London School of Economics 18 November 2012 Abstract Behaviourism is the view that preferences, beliefs, and other mental states in social- scientific theories are nothing but constructs re-describing people’s behavioural dis- positions. Mentalism is the view that they capture real phenomena, no less existent than the unobservable entities and properties in the natural sciences, such as elec- trons and electromagnetic fields. While behaviourism has long gone out of fashion in psychology and linguistics, it remains influential in economics, especially in ‘re- vealed preference’ theory. We aim to (i) clear up some common confusions about the two views, (ii) situate the debate in a historical context, and (iii) defend a men- talist approach to economics. Setting aside normative concerns about behaviourism, we show that mentalism is in line with best scientific practice even if economics is treated as a purely positive science of economic behaviour. We distinguish men- talism from, and reject, the radical neuroeconomic view that behaviour should be explained in terms of people’s brain processes, as distinct from their mental states. 1 Introduction Economic theory seeks to explain the social and economic behaviour of human (and sometimes other) agents.1 It usually does so by (i) ascribing, at least in an ‘as if’ mode, ⇤This paper was presented at the LSE Choice Group workshop on ‘Rationalizability and Choice’, July 2011, the D-TEA workshop, Paris, July 2012, and the EIPE seminar, Rotterdam, September 2012. We are grateful to the participants and especially Nick Baigent, Walter Bossert, Richard Bradley, Mika¨el Cozic, Eddie Dekel, Ido Erev, Itzhak Gilboa, Conrad Heilmann, Johannes Himmelreich, Marco Mariotti, Friederike Mengel, Clemens Puppe, Larry Samuelson, David Schmeidler, Asli Selim, Daniel Stoljar, Kotaro Suzumura, and Peter Wakker for comments and discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Mentalism Versus Behaviourism in Economics: a Philosophy-Of-Science Perspective
    Franz Dietrich & Christian List Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: a philosophy-of-science perspective Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Dietrich, Franz and List, Christian (2016) Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: a philosophy-of-science perspective. Economics and Philosophy, 32 (2). pp. 249-281. ISSN 0266-2671 © 2016 Cambridge University Press This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/62444/ Available in LSE Research Online: August 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: aphilosophy-of-scienceperspective Franz Dietrich & Christian List⇤ First version 1 April 2012, this version 17 May 2015 Abstract Behaviourism is the view that preferences, beliefs, and other mental states in social- scientific theories are nothing but constructs re-describing people’s behaviour. Mentalism is the view that they capture real phenomena, on a par with the unobserv- ables in science, such as electrons and electromagnetic fields.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of the Learning Brain
    A CRITIQUE OF THE LEARNING BRAIN JOAKIM OLSSON Department of Philosophy Master Thesis in Theoretical Philosophy (45 ECTS) Autumn 2020 Supervisor: Sharon Rider Examiner: Pauliina Remes Table of Contents 1. INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................................... 1 1.1 A Brief Overview ............................................................................................................. 1 1.2 Method, Structure and Delimitations ............................................................................... 4 2. BACKGROUND ON THE LEARNING BRAIN ............................................................. 8 2.1 The Learning Brain and Its Philosophical Foundation .................................................... 9 2.2 Cognitivism’s Three Steps: Mentalism, Mind-Brain Identity and Computer Analogy . 14 3. A CRITIQUE OF COGNITIVISM .................................................................................. 24 3.1 A Critique of Mentalism ................................................................................................ 24 3.1.1 The Exteriorization of the Mental ........................................................................... 25 3.1.2 The Intentionality of Mind Seen Through Intentional Action ................................ 32 3.2 A Critique of the Mind-Brain Identity Theory .............................................................. 54 3.3 A Critique of the Computer Analogy ............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 4 C. D. Broad (1887–1971)
    4 C. D. Broad (1887–1971) JAMES VAN CLEVE Charlie Dunbar Broad was a leading contributor to analytic philosophy of the twenti- eth century, known not so much for any startlingly original doctrines he propounded as for his formidable powers of distinction, analysis, and argument. Born in London, he was educated at Dulwich College and Cambridge. He entered Cambridge in 1905, first studying physics and chemistry in the natural science tripos and then switching to philosophy in the moral science tripos. The influence of Russell and Moore at Cambridge was then very strong and shows itself in Broad’s work (see RUSSELL and MOORE). He published his dissertation as Perception, Physics, and Reality in 1914. For a period of years beginning in 1911 he served as G. F. Stout’s assistant in St. Andrews, and in 1920 he was appointed professor at the University of Bristol, where he gave the course of lectures in philosophy for natural science students that became Scientific Thought. In 1922 he delivered the Tarner Lectures, subsequently published as The Mind and Its Place in Nature, and was invited to succeed McTaggart as lecturer at Cambridge. After McTaggart’s death in 1925, he oversaw the publication of the second volume of McTaggart’s The Nature of Existence, which served as the stimulus for writing his own monumental Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy. (This is the book of choice for any metaphysician who is sentenced to exile on a desert island.) From 1933 until his retire- ment in 1953 he was Knightbridge Professor of Moral Philosophy at Cambridge.
    [Show full text]
  • Mentalism Versus Behaviourism in Economics: a Philosophy-Of-Science Perspective
    Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: aphilosophy-of-scienceperspective Franz Dietrich & Christian List⇤ First version 1 April 2012, this version 17 May 2015 Abstract Behaviourism is the view that preferences, beliefs, and other mental states in social- scientific theories are nothing but constructs re-describing people’s behaviour. Mentalism is the view that they capture real phenomena, on a par with the unobserv- ables in science, such as electrons and electromagnetic fields. While behaviourism has gone out of fashion in psychology, it remains influential in economics, espe- cially in ‘revealed preference’ theory. We defend mentalism in economics, construed as a positive science, and show that it fits best scientific practice. We distinguish mentalism from, and reject, the radical neuroeconomic view that behaviour should be explained in terms of brain processes, as distinct from mental states. Keywords: Mentalism, behaviourism, revealed preference, decision theory, scientific realism. 1 Introduction Economic theory seeks to explain the social and economic behaviour of individual human agents (and sometimes that of other agents, such as firms). It usually does so by (i) ascribing, at least in an ‘as if’ mode, certain mental states, such as beliefs and preferences, to the agents in question and (ii) showing that, under the assumption that those agents are rational, the ascribed mental states lead us to predict, and thereby to ⇤Contact details: F. Dietrich, Paris School of Economics & CNRS, CES-Centre d’Economie de la Sorbonne, Maison des Sciences Economiques, 106-112 Boulevard de l’Hˆopital, 75647 Paris cedex 13, France; URL: <http://www.franzdietrich.net>. C. List, London School of Economics, Departments of Government and Philosophy, London WC2A 2AE, U.K.; URL: <http://personal.lse.ac.uk/LIST>.
    [Show full text]
  • DICTIONARY of PHILOSOPHY This Page Intentionally Left Blank
    A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY This page intentionally left blank. A Dictionary of Philosophy Third edition A.R.Lacey Department of Philosophy, King’s College, University of London First published in 1976 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Second edition 1986 Third edition 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © A.R.Lacey 1976, 1986, 1996 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Lacey, A.R. A dictionary of philosophy.—3rd edn. 1. Philosophy—Dictionaries I. Title 190′.3′21 B41 ISBN 0-203-19819-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-19822-0 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-13332-7 (Print Edition) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available on request Preface to the first edition This book aims to give the layman or intending student a pocket encyclopaedia of philosophy, one with a bias towards explaining terminology. The latter task is not an easy one since philosophy is regularly concerned with concepts which are unclear.
    [Show full text]
  • Antidualism and Antimentalism in Radical Behaviorism*
    Behavior and Philosophy, 43, 1-37 (2015). © 2015 Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies ANTIDUALISM AND ANTIMENTALISM IN RADICAL BEHAVIORISM* José E. Burgos** University of Guadalajara Abstract: Radical behaviorism (RB) is antidualistic and antimentalistic. Antidualism is the rejection of ontological dualism, the partition of reality into physical and nonphysical. Antimentalism is the rejection of the ontological theses that mind is causal, internal, subjective, and nonbehavioral in nature. Radical behaviorists conflate both rejections, based on depictions of mentalism as inherently dualistic. However, such depictions are fallacious. Mental causation and mind as internal are fundamentally incompatible with dualism and hence inherently materialistic. Mind as subjective and nonbehavioral in nature are compatible with dualism, but can be construed materialistically. I exemplify with the mind-brain identity theory. The same arguments apply to functionalism, which is also materialistic and provides a more plausible philosophical interpretation of cognitive psychology as a paradigmatic example of mentalism at work in psychology. I propose that radical behaviorists’ accusations of dualism against mentalism rely on an invalid redefinition of “dualism” in terms other than the physical-nonphysical partition. All of this only weakens RB’s antimentalism. Radical behaviorists are advised to stop making those accusations and adopt a behavioristic ontology of mind, such as mind-behavior identity, to reject alternative nondualistic ontologies. Key words: radical behaviorism; antidualism; antimentalism; mind-brain identity; cognitive psychology; functionalism; mind-behavior identity * A preliminary version of this paper was presented in Pereira, Colombia, September, 2014. ** I thank an anonymous reviewer, Andrew Brook, Sigrid Glenn, Peter Killeen, Sam Leigland, Joseph Mendola, Ted Schoneberger, Eric Schwitzgebel, John Staddon, Warren Tryon, and William Uttal for many valuable comments to previous drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • AECT International Convention Las Vegas, Nevada October 21-25, 2019 Contents
    InspiredProfessional Learning. InspiredLearning Professionals. AECT International Convention Las Vegas, Nevada October 21-25, 2019 Contents Welcome to Las Vegas 2 Convention at-a-Glance 4 Local Information 6 Meet the Candidates 11 What’s New at Convention? 12 Breakfast with Champions 14 Hotel Floor Plan 15 General Convention Information 16 Educational Partners 21 Planning Committee 22 AECT Foundation Members 23 University Reception Participants 24 Addie Kinsinger Leadership Development Program: Meet the Interns 27 AECT Early Career Symposium 28 AECT Board of Directors 30 Inspire! Sessions 32 AECT Division Convention Kickoff 34 The Association for Educational AECT and Divisional Awards 35 Communications and Technology Division & Affiliate Highlights 40 320 W. 8th Street, Suite 101 GSA Sessions & Events 44 Bloomington, IN 47404-3745 IVLA Sessions & Events 46 KSET Sessions & Events 47 NJASL Activities 49 PAECT Sessions & Events 51 Toll Free: 877-677-2328 SICET Sessions & Events 53 Local: 812-335-7675 Governance and Committee Meetings 56 Fax: 812-335-7678 Featured Sessions 58 E-mail: [email protected] Design & Development Showcase 58 Web site: www.aect.org Emerging Technology Showcase 60 AECT 2020 Problem Statement 61 2020 Design & Development Competition 62 2020 Call for Proposals 64 Workshops 67 Schedule by Day: Monday, Oct 21 69 Schedule by Day: Tuesday, Oct 22 72 Schedule by Day: Wednesday, Oct 23 119 Schedule by Day: Thursday, Oct 24 157 Schedule by Day: Friday, Oct 25 213 Divisional and Affiliate Session Index 225 Presenters and Participant Index 243 Convention Notes 250 Las Vegas, Nevada AECT • Inspired. Inspired Professional Learning. Inspired Learning Professionals. • 2019 1 Welcome to Las Vegas Welcome to Las Vegas and the 2019 AECT International Convention! Inspired denotes the extraordinary quality of the sessions at our convention, and we endeavor to improve ourselves through exceptional professional learning opportunities.
    [Show full text]
  • German Idealism by Espen Hammer
    GERMAN IDEALISM German Idealism is one of the most important movements in the history of philosophy. It is also increasingly acknowledged to contain the seeds of many current philosophical issues and debates. This outstanding collection of spe- cially commissioned chapters examines German idealism from several angles and assesses the renewed interest in the subject from a wide range of fields. Including discussions of the key representatives of German idealism such as Kant, Fichte and Hegel, it is structured in clear sections dealing with: metaphysics the legacy of Hegel’s philosophy Brandom and Hegel recognition and agency autonomy and nature the philosophy of German romanticism Amongst other important topics, German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives addresses the debates surrounding the metaphysical and epistemological legacy of German idealism; its importance for understanding recent debates in moral and political thought; its appropriation in recent theories of language and the relationship between mind and world; and how German idealism affected sub- sequent movements such as romanticism, pragmatism, and critical theory. Contributors: Frederick Beiser, Jay Bernstein, Andrew Bowie, Richard Eldridge, Manfred Frank, Paul Franks, Sebastian Gardner, Espen Hammer, Stephen Houlgate, Terry Pinkard, Robert Pippin, Paul Redding, Fred Rush, Robert Stern. Espen Hammer is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oslo and a Reader in Philosophy at the University of Essex. He is the author of Adorno and the Political (Routledge, 2006). GERMAN IDEALISM Contemporary Perspectives Edited by Espen Hammer First published 2007 by Routledge 2 Milton Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, OX14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2007.
    [Show full text]
  • Derren Brown Mentalism Tricks
    Make money Selling Ebooks Click here for details! Welcome to Derren Brown Mentalism Tricks The effects I’m revealing in this book and some of the strongest in all of mental magic. All of these effects can be successfully performed by a complete beginner almost immediately. Please, do yourself justice though, read through the book several times and practice by speaking out loud. If you do this, I promise – you will be baffling your mates and literally be the star attraction of any party of club you go to! I have written the instructions as concisely as possible. It has taken me a long time to work through countless magic books in order to provide this information – I’ve done the hard work for you, so the last thing I wanted to do is over complicate things with unnecessary information. For each trick, I have explained the Effect, the Basic Secret and then a Full Methodology which will allow you to amaze whoever you perform on. Each of the main tricks has a full script you can use when performing. Feel free to change it to suit your needs. The words in (italic brackets) explain what you should Make money Selling Ebooks Click here for details! Make money Selling Ebooks Click here for details! be doing whilst reading the script. The Invisible Touch: Although Derren Brown did not invent the principle for this effect, you will have seen this perform this trick with ‘the twins’ and also ‘the lap dancers’ in his TV show. It is a classic trick of mentalism any completely impromptu.
    [Show full text]
  • Creation Care and Loving Our Neighbors
    The way we Christians talk about our responsibility for creation and to our neigh- our Neighbors and Loving Care Creation Th. K. Johnson / Schirrmacher Th. bors should not be entirely controlled by the scientific and ideological arguments Thomas Schirrmacher, coming either from the right or from the left. The great biblical narrative of creati- on, fall, redemption, and final restoration provides the larger story within which Thomas K. Johnson we should deliberate. There are also particular texts and themes in the Bible that provide crucial components of a biblically informed humane environmental ethic, such as the way in which Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob were historically famous for digging wells, or the way in which the ancient Israelites talked about developments Creation Care and in agricultural technology. And biblically informed Christians will never want to for- get the development mandate given to Adam and Eve or the way in which God has long been active in his world as both Creator and Redeemer. Loving our Neighbors Johnson and Schirrmacher have teamed up to present essays which attempt to ar- ticulate and address selected themes in environmental ethics that unite a proper concern for creation care with loving our neighbors. Read, and then try to think farther along the paths they suggest. Studies in Environmental Ethics Sponsored by: ISBN 978-3-86269-116-6 ISSNISBN 1867-73209783862691166 90000 > The WEA Global Issues Series 17 The WEA Verlag für Kultur und Wissenschaft VKW (Culture and Science Publ.) 9 783862 691166 Dr. Thomas Schirrmacher VKW Thomas Schirrmacher Thomas K. Johnson Creation Care and Loving our Neighbors: Studies in Environmental Ethics The WEA Global Issues Series Editors: Bishop Efraim Tendero, Philippines, Secretary General, World Evangelical Alliance Thomas Schirrmacher, Director, International Institute for Religious Liberty and Speaker for Human Rights of the World Evangelical Alliance Volumes: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Critique of the Concept of Consciousness: Its Relevance to Contemporary Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind
    Hegel's Critique of the Concept of Consciousness: Its Relevance to Contemporary Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind Jay A. Gupta A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 0 Copyright by lay A. Gupta 200 1 Nationai Library Bibliothique nationale 1+1 of Cûnada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395. me Wellington OnrxON KtAON4 dnawa ON KiA ON4 Canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence aliowing the exclusive permettant a la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or seii reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la foxme de microfiche/fk, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fiom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be priated or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. Abstract Hegel's Critique of the Concept of Consciousness: Its Relevance to Contemporary Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind Jay A. Gupta Ph.D., 200 1 Department of Philosophy University of Toronto This study develops a particular interpretation of G.W.F.Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, and extends it to contemporary philosophical concerns.
    [Show full text]