The Analytic/Continental Divide in Philosophy, Fall 2020
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3. -
Logical Investigations, Vols I & II Edmund Husserl Logical Investigations
International Library of Philosophy Edited by Jose Bermudez, Tim Crane and Peter Sullivan Advisory Board: Jonathan Barnes, Fred Dretske, Frances Kamm, Brian Leiter, Huw Price and Sydney Shoemaker Recent titles in the ILP: The Facts of Causation D. H. Mellor The Conceptual Roots of Mathematics j. R. Lucas Stream of Consciousness Barry Dainton Knowledge and Reference in Empirical Science Jody Azzouni Reason without Freedom David Owens The Price of Doubt N. M. L Nathan Matters of Mind Scott Sturgeon Logic, Form and Grammar Peter Long The Metaphysicians of Meaning Gideon Makin Logical Investigations, Vols I & II Edmund Husserl Logical Investigations Edmund Husserl Translated by J. N. Findlay from the Second German edition of Logische Untersuchungen with a new Preface by Michael Dummett and edited with a new Introduction by Dermot Moran Volume I Prolegomena to pure logic (Volume I of the German editions) Expression and meaning (Investigation I, Volume II of the German editions) The ideal unity of the species and modern theories of abstraction (Investigation II, Volume II of the German editions) London and New York First published in German as Logische Untersuchungen by M. Niemeyer, Halle 1900/1901 Second German edition, Vol. I and Vol. II, Part I, first published 1913 First published in English 1970 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Reprinted 1976, 1977, 1982 This paperback edition first published 200 I by Routledge I I New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is on imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Translation © 1970 J. -
Early Continental Philosophy of Science Babette Babich Fordham University, [email protected]
Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Philosophy Collections Fall 2010 Early Continental Philosophy of Science Babette Babich Fordham University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Babich, Babette, "Early Continental Philosophy of Science" (2010). Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections. 31. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich/31 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 10 EARLY CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Babette Babich During the years leading up to and after 1890-1930, the continental concep tion of science had a far broader scope than the anglophone notion of science today. Even today, the German term Wissenschaft embraces not only the natural and the social sciences, including economics, l but also the full panoply of the so-called humanities, including the theoretical study of art and theology, both important in the nineteenth century for, among other things, the formation of the life sciences.2 Philosophy itself was also counted as a science and was, in its phenomenological articulation, nothing less than the science ofscientific origins or "original science" the «Urwissenschaft" - as Martin Heidegger defined it in 1919,3 following his own intensive engagement with Edmund Hussed's Logical Investigations. -
Continental Philosophy from Hegel Michael Rosen
1 Continental Philosophy from Hegel Michael Rosen I The Continental Tradition Historians of philosophy writing in English typically construct their narratives as if the authors whom they are discussing were all taking part in a single argument -- an argument that is conducted in terms of those problems that we now recognize to be relevant. This appears to leave no place for those who do not share our current assumptions regarding the nature of the issues — who lie outside what we think of as "our tradition".1 Yet what is the alternative? Unless we can situate the authors whom we study in relation to our own concerns what philosophical value (rather than value of a historical, biographical or sociological kind) is there in engaging with them? Fortunately, this apparent dilemma rests on a misunderstanding. Philosophy is not a discipline carried on according to rules and assumptions fixed once and for all. On the contrary, it has always involved an attempt to examine and call into question ideas and commitments that are otherwise taken for granted. Thus we do not need to share assumptions with the authors whom we study (or, worse, pretend that we share them, when we do not) in order to include them in our discussion. Indeed, it may be the very fact that authors proceed from an underlying position very different from our own that makes studying them valuable: the difference challenges us to reflect on commitments that we would otherwise not even realize that we had. The problem is to explain the distinctiveness of the authors' own concerns in sufficient detail to make them intelligible and to find enough common ground to make the challenge that they represent a productive one. -
Bachyryczdavid.Pdf
THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL FOUNDATION OF TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY: HUSSERL AND THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy By David John Bachyrycz, B.A. Washington, D.C. December 18, 2009 Copyright 2010 by David John Bachyrycz All Rights Reserved ii THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL FOUNDATION OF TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY: HUSSERL AND THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE David John Bachyrycz, B.A. Thesis Advisor: John B. Brough, Ph.D. ABSTRACT The goal of this dissertation is to provide an account of Edmund Husserl’s epistemology and its place within his phenomenology up through the publication of Ideas I in 1913. It represents a challenge to the view that Husserl is a Cartesian epistemologist seeking to safeguard the foundations of theoretical knowledge from the challenge of skepticism. Instead, I argue that Husserl aims to provide a transcendental clarification of knowledge understood as particular kind of intentional performance. The animating question of Husserl’s theory of knowledge is not whether the achievement of objective knowledge is possible for an experiencing subject, but how it is possible. I begin by examining Husserl’s earliest attempt at a general theory of knowledge in the First Edition Logical Investigations, which I argue should be understood in broadly Kantian terms, as a project of disclosing the conditions for possibility of knowledge by way of a phenomenological investigation of intentional consciousness. I next look at how Husserl articulates his analysis of knowledge on the basis of the cardinal phenomenological distinction between empty and fulfilled intentions. -
Gottlob Frege
GOTTLOB FREGE i GF_vol.1_A01 1 5/18/05, 12:34 Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers Other titles in the series: Ludwig Wittgenstein Edited by Stuart Shanker René Descartes Edited by Georges J. D. Moyal George Berkeley Edited by Walter E. Creery Martin Heidegger Edited by Christopher Macann Immanuel Kant Edited by Ruth Chadwick John Dewey Edited by Jim Tiles G. W. Leibniz Edited by Roger Woolhouse David Hume Edited by Stanley Tweyman Socrates Edited by William J. Prior Plato Edited and with an introduction by Nicholas D. Smith Nietzche Edited and with an introduction by Daniel W. Conway Bertrand Russell Edited and with an introduction by Andrew Irvine Aristotle Edited and with an introduction by Lloyd P. Gerson Deleuze and Guattari Edited and with an introduction by Gary Genosko ii GF_vol.1_A01 2 5/18/05, 12:34 Spinoza Edited and with an introduction by Genevieve Lloyd Ludwig Wittgenstein Second Series Edited and with an introduction by Stuart Shanker and David Kilfoyle Kierkegaard Edited and with an introduction by Daniel W. Conway Derrida Edited and with an introduction by Len Lawlor and Zeynep Direk Karl Popper Edited by Anthony O’Hear Emmanuel Levinas Edited and with a new introduction by Claire Katz Edmund Husserl Edited and with a new introduction by Rudolf Bernet, Donn Welton, and Gina Zavota iii GF_vol.1_A01 3 5/18/05, 12:34 iv GF_vol.1_A01 4 5/18/05, 12:34 GOTTLOB FREGE Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers Edited by Michael Beaney and Erich H. Reck Volume I Frege’s philosophy in context v GF_vol.1_A01 5/18/05, 12:345 First published 2005 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 270 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Editorial material and selection © 2005 Michael Beaney and Erich H. -
Logical Investigations Edited by Jose Bermudez, Tim Crane and Peter Sullivan
International Library of Philosophy Logical Investigations Edited by Jose Bermudez, Tim Crane and Peter Sullivan Advisory Board: Jonathan Barnes, Fred Dretske, Frances Kamm, Brian Leiter, Huw Price and Sydney Shoemaker Recent titles in the ILP: Edmund Husserl The Facts of Causation Translated by J. N. Findlay D. H. Mellor from the Second German edition of Logische Untersuchungen The Conceptual Roots of Mathematics with a new Preface by Michael Dummett J. R. Lucas and edited with a new Introduction by Dermot Moran Stream of Consciousness Barry Dainton Volume I Knowledge and Reference in Empirical Science Prolegomena to pure logic jody Azzouni (Volume I of the German editions) Reason without Freedom Expression and meaning David Owens (Investigation I, Volume II of the German editions) The Price of Doubt The ideal unity of the species and modern theories N. M. L Nathan of abstraction (Investigation II, Volume II of the German editions) Matters of Mind Scott Sturgeon Logic, Form and Grammar Peter Long The Metaphysicians of Meaning Gideon Makin Logical Investigations, Vols I & II Edmund Husserl London and New York Dedicated to Carl Stumpf with Honour and III Friendship First published in German as Logische Untersuchungen by M. Niemeyer. Halle 1900/190 I Second German edition. Vol. I and Vol. II. Part I. first published 1913 First published in English 1970 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Reprinted 1976. 1977. 1982 This paperback edition first published 200 I by Routledge I I New Fetter Lane. London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street. New York. NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Translation © 1970 J. -
Edmund Husserl and Bertrand Russell, 1905-1918: the Not-So-Odd Couple (Nikolay Milkov)
Edmund Husserl and Bertrand Russell, 1905-1918: The Not-So-Odd Couple (Nikolay Milkov) 1. INTRODUCTION 1.1 Why Husserl and Russell? Historians of philosophy usually define phenomenology as a theory of intentionality and Husserl as a theorist of meaning. This explains why when students of phenomenology compare Husserl with analytic philosophers at all (indeed, for decades Husserl was considered antipodal to analytic philosophy) they usually turn to Frege. Typical- ly, their comparative studies tend to concentrate on parallels between Frege‘s famed differen- tiation of ―sense‖ from ―meaning‖ and Husserl‘s distinction between noema from ―object.‖ One can trace an extended series of such studies beginning with Dagfinn Føllesdal and con- tinuing through works of J. N. Mohanty, Michael Dummett, and others. To be sure, this approach is not without its theoretical and historical value. However, we should not forget that ―Husserl repeatedly states loud and clear that what he is trying to do is to find the basis of our conceptual world in immediate experience‖ (emphasis in original; Hintikka 1995, p. 82), while Frege is anything but a philosopher of immediate experience. That was what the Cambridge philosophers G. E. Moore and especially Bertrand Russell were. It is this fact that motivates the venture here to examine the largely overlooked, yet his- torically and philosophically significant relatedness of Husserl and Russell. One reason why this topic has received little attention is that historians of phenome- nology and of early analytic philosophy by and large still lack substantive knowledge of the theoretical stance of their counterparts. This is particularly true in the case of phenomenolo- gists, who generally persist in the view that: (i) Russell was nothing but a radical reductionist, and that (ii) his sense-data are nothing but Hume‘s impressions.