Enumeration Reducibility and Polynomial Time Bounds

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Enumeration Reducibility and Polynomial Time Bounds Enumeration Reducibility and Polynomial Time Bounds Charles Milton Harris Submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The University of Leeds Department of Pure Mathematics January 2006 The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Barry Cooper for his help, and for always managing to make time to talk and give advice, during my time as a Phd student under his supervision. I am extremely grateful and indebted to my father Roland and my step- mother Paddy for their unstinting support during my years as a student. I would also like to thank my brothers Paul and Simon, and my sisters Tessa and Jane, who have often looked after me during my time at university. Thankyou to Tina and Chris for the bed, the midnight feasts, and their friendship. Finally I would like to mention Aldo, Frantz, and Olivier (formerly) of the “Caf´edes Ar`enes” in Paris who put up with me and fed me almost every day for the best part of two years. iii iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Abstract This thesis discusses enumeration reducibility and three of its variants. We begin with an appraisal of the basic properties of enumeration reducibility ( ≤e ). Underlying principles of the ≤e are discussed and six different definitions of the latter are introduced. Insights due to the different definitions are presented and particular attention is paid to Scott’s formulation of ≤e in terms of the λ-calculus. We introduce symmetric enumeration reducibility (≤se ) and we give a clas- sification of ≤se in terms of other standard reducibilities. We show that the natural embedding of the Turing degrees into the enumeration degrees (De) translates to an embedding ( ιse ) into Dse that preserves least element, suprema and infima. We define a weak and a strong jump and we observe that ιse preserves the jump operator relative to the latter definition. We prove various (global) results concerning branching, exact pairs, minimal covers and diamond embeddings in Dse. We show that certain classes of symmetric enumeration de- grees are first order definable, in particular the classes of semirecursive, Σn ∪Πn, ∆n (for any n ∈ ω), and embedded Turing degrees. This last result allows us to conclude that the theory of Dse has the same 1-degree as the theory of Second Order Arithmetic. We present two polynomial time variants of ≤e , non deterministic poly- NP nomial time conjunctive reducibility (≤c ) and polynomial time enumeration reducibility (≤pe ). The degree structure induced by ≤pe over the computable sets (hRECpe, ≤i) is studied. It is shown that the latter is a non distributive v vi ABSTRACT upper semi-lattice that is not a lattice. We demonstrate the relativised ver- sion of the property that every non zero polynomial time enumeration (pe-) degree is part of a minimal pair. We prove that the pe-degrees are dense and moreover, that any countable distributive lattice can be embedded in any in- terval of the pe-degrees via embeddings that either preserve least or greatest element. We also explain why there exist similar embeddings of finite nowhere complemented distributive lattices that preserve least and greatest elements. SN Strong non deterministic polynomial time Turing reducibility ( ≤T ) is intro- SN duced. A canonical embedding of the degree structure induced by ≤T over the computable sets into hRECpe, ≤i is presented. We observe that this em- bedding preserves suprema and least element and that it is also essentially an NP embedding into the equivalent degree structure induced by ≤c . We prove the existence of relativised quasiminimal degrees in the case of the latter embed- ding. In conclusion we show that there exists sets A, B ∈ E such that A≤pe B P whereas AT B. Contents Acknowledgements iii Abstract v 1 Introduction 1 1.1 General Overview and Background . 1 1.2 Preliminaries. 5 1.2.1 Basic Notation. 5 1.2.2 Finite Sets and Functions. 6 1.2.3 Strings and Finite Initial Segments. 7 1.2.4 Partial Orders and Lattices. 7 2 Defining Enumeration Reducibility 9 2.1 Overview . 9 2.2 Turing Machines and Reductions . 10 2.2.1 Main Matter . 10 2.2.2 Other Reducibilities and Notation . 19 2.3 Constructive Enumeration Reducibility . 21 2.3.1 Main matter . 21 2.3.2 Other Facts and Notation . 27 2.4 Enumeration Reducibility and n-T-reducibility . 27 2.5 Non Constructive Enumeration Reducibility . 33 2.6 Enumeration reducibility and Lambda . 40 vii viii CONTENTS 2.6.1 The language Lambda and the C.E. Sets. 41 2.6.2 Enumeration Degrees and Lambda . 58 3 Symmetric Enumeration Reducibility 65 3.1 Overview . 65 3.2 Introduction to Symmetric Enumeration Reducibility . 66 3.3 Embedding the Turing Degrees . 70 3.4 Jump Operators . 73 3.5 The Symmetric Enumeration Hierarchy . 77 3.6 Basic Properties of Dse ........................ 82 3.7 CEA and co-CEA substructures of Dse . 89 3.8 Diamond embeddings and minimal covers . 92 3.9 Automorphisms and definability . 105 4 Polynomial Time Enumeration Reducibility 115 4.1 Overview . 115 4.2 Preliminaries . 116 4.2.1 Background Notation . 116 4.2.2 Coding Finite Sets and Pairs of Strings . 117 4.2.3 Turing Machines and Time Bounds . 118 4.2.4 Deterministic Turing Machines and Reductions . 119 4.2.5 Non Deterministic Turing machines and Reductions . 120 4.2.6 Complexity Classes . 126 4.3 Polynomial Time Enumeration Reducibility . 126 4.4 Basic Properties of hRECpe, ≤i . 150 4.5 Join and Meet Lemmas . 165 4.6 Lattice Embeddings in hRECpe, ≤i . 172 4.7 Embedding the sn-T-degrees . 181 P 4.8 Separating ≤T and ≤pe in E . 193 A Additional Proofs and Results 205 A.1 Proofs in Lambda . 205 CONTENTS ix A.2 Strong Definability in Lambda . 215 A.3 Complete sets, jumps and Lambda . 225 Bibliography 235 x CONTENTS Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 General Overview and Background Enumeration reducibility (≤e ) is a relation between sets of numbers in which only positive information is processed. The first informal definition of ≤e appeared in an early draft of [Rog67]. According to this definition, a set A is enumeration reducible to a set B (A≤e B) if there is an effective procedure for getting an enumeration A from any enumeration of B. The formalised version1 of this definition appeared in [FR59]. Essentially it is this latter formulation that has been the basic tool in the ensuing research on enumeration reducibility and its degree structure. However two other equivalent definitions appeared in the literature in the 1970’s. The first of these was due to Selman [Sel71] who defined a relation G1 between sets such that AG1B iff, for any set X, if B is computably enumerable (c.e.) in X, then so is A. Selman proved in the same paper that (over non trivial sets), this relation is equivalent to ≤e despite the fact that the former is defined in a non constructive manner whereas the latter is defined with respect to a given effective procedure. The second equivalent definition appeared in Scott [Sco75]. In this paper Scott defined the language Lambda—an extension of the lambda calculus—and an interpretation in Pω 1In other words Definition 2.3.2 below. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION of the language according to which a set is c.e. iff it is the interpretation of a closed Lambda term. Moreover, for any A, B ⊆ ω, and supposing B to be a constant with interpretation B, A≤e B iff there exists a closed Lambda term u such that A is the interpretation of the (parametrised2) Lambda term (u) B. Thus an enumeration reduction corresponds to an application by a closed term in Scott’s language Lambda (whereas abstraction corresponds to the formation of an enumeration operator). In Chapter 2 we present these three different approaches to enumeration reducibility with a view to giving a more complete picture of the basic properties of the latter. In particular, by a careful analysis of oracle computations we reformulate ≤e in terms of oracle Turing machines (Definition 2.3.4). We also underline and extend previous work by Sasso, Cooper and McEvoy [McE84] on the relationship between deterministic (≤T) and non deterministic Turing reducibility, enumeration reducibility, and the relation “computably enumerable in” (c.e. in). A standard result that follows from the work reviewed in Chapter 2 is the fact that the Turing degrees (DT) canonically embed into the enumeration de- grees (De). In other words the Turing degrees can be regarded as a (partial order) substructure of the enumeration degrees. This leads to the question of the status of the former within the latter. In particular, are the Turing degrees first order definable in the enumeration degrees? A recent paper by Kalimullin [Kal03] addresses this question. Namely, Kalimullin shows that the enumera- tion jump operation is first order definable and, as a consequence of Friedberg’s completeness criterion, that the the class of embedded Turing degrees in the 0 cone above 0e is also first order definable within the structure. Kalimullin’s methods, which originate in earlier work on splitting properties of the embed- ded Turing degrees [AKC03] in De, underpin the main results in the work on the degree structure presented in Chapter 3. This work originated in a problem raised by McEvoy [McE84] of how one might refine the arithmetical hierarchy in such a way as to make it compatible with enumeration reducibility.
Recommended publications
  • Relationships Between Computability-Theoretic Properties of Problems
    RELATIONSHIPS BETWEEN COMPUTABILITY-THEORETIC PROPERTIES OF PROBLEMS ROD DOWNEY, NOAM GREENBERG, MATTHEW HARRISON-TRAINOR, LUDOVIC PATEY, AND DAN TURETSKY Abstract. A problem is a multivalued function from a set of instances to a set of solutions. We consider only instances and solutions coded by sets of integers. A problem admits preservation of some computability-theoretic weakness property if every computable instance of the problem admits a solu- tion relative to which the property holds. For example, cone avoidance is the ability, given a non-computable set A and a computable instance of a problem P, to find a solution relative to which A is still non-computable. In this article, we compare relativized versions of computability-theoretic notions of preservation which have been studied in reverse mathematics, and prove that the ones which were not already separated by natural statements in the literature actually coincide. In particular, we prove that it is equivalent 0 to admit avoidance of 1 cone, of ! cones, of 1 hyperimmunity or of 1 non-Σ1 definition. We also prove that the hierarchies of preservation of hyperimmunity 0 and non-Σ1 definitions coincide. On the other hand, none of these notions coincide in a non-relativized setting. 1. Introduction In this article, we classify computability-theoretic preservation properties studied in reverse mathematics, namely cone avoidance, preservation of hyperimmunities, 0 preservation of non-Σ1 definitions, among others. Many of these preservation prop- erties have already been separated using natural problems in reverse mathematics { that is, there is a natural problem which is known to admit preservation of one property but not preservation of the other.
    [Show full text]
  • Co~Nparison of Polynomial- Time Reducibilities Richard Ladner University of Washington Seattle, Wash. Nanay Lynch University Of
    Co~nparison of Polynomial- Time Reducibilities interesting relationships. Richard Ladner University of Washington I. Introduction Seattle, Wash. Computation-resource-bounded reducibil- Nanay Lynch University of Southern California ities play a role in the theory of computational Los Angeles, Cal. complexity which is analogous to, and perhaps AlaD Selman Florida State University as important as, the various kinds of effective Tallahas see, Fla. reducibilities used in recursive function theory. Abstract Just as the effective reducibilities are used to Comparison of the polynomial-time-bounded classify problems according to their degrees reducibilities introduced by Cook [1] and of unsolvability, [9] space- and time- bou6ded t<arp [4] leads naturally to the definition of reducibilities may be used to classify problems several intermediate truth-table reducibilities. according to their complexity level. We give definitions and comparisons for these Tne most fruitful resource-bounded reducibilities ; we note, in particular, that reducibilities thus far have been the polynomial- all reducibilities of this type which do not time-bounded reducibilities of Cook [I] and have obvious implication relationships are I<arp [4], corresponding respectively to in fact distinct in a strong sense. Proofs Turing and many-one reducibilities in recursive are by simultaneous diagonalization and function theory. Other resource-bounded encoding constructions. reducibilities have been defined and used as well Work of Meyer and Stockmeyer [7] and [3] [5] [6] [8]; they differ from Cook's or Karp's Gill [Z] then leads u.,~ to define nondeterministic only in the bound on time or space allowed versions of all of our reducibilities. Although for the reduction, and thus they also correspond many of the definitions degenerate, comparison to Turing or many-one reducibility.
    [Show full text]
  • {\Alpha} Degrees As an Automorphism Base for the {\Alpha}-Enumeration
    α degrees as an automorphism base for the α-enumeration degrees Dávid Natingga February 13, 2019 Abstract Selman’s Theorem [10] in classical Computability Theory gives a characterization of the enumeration re- ducibility for arbitrary sets in terms of the enumeration reducibility on the total sets: A ≤e B ⇐⇒ ∀X[X ≡e X ⊕ X ∧ B ≤e X ⊕ X =⇒ A ≤e X ⊕ .X]. This theorem implies directly that the Turing degrees are an automorphism base of the enumeration degrees. We lift the classical proof to the setting of the α-Computability Theory to obtain the full generalization when α is a regular cardinal and partial results for a general admissible ordinal α. 1 α-Computability Theory α-Computability Theory is the study of the definability theory over Gödel’s Lα where α is an admissible ordinal. One can think of equivalent definitions on Turing machines with a transfinite tape and time [3] [4] [5] [6] or on generalized register machines [7]. Recommended references for this section are [9], [1], [8] and [2]. Classical Computability Theory is α-Computability Theory where α = ω. 1.1 Gödel’s Constructible Universe Definition 1.1. (Gödel’s Constructible Universe) Define Gödel’s constructible universe as L := Sβ∈Ord Lβ where γ,δ ∈ Ord, δ is a limit ordinal and: L0 := ∅, arXiv:1812.11308v2 [math.LO] 12 Feb 2019 Lγ+1 := Def(Lγ ) := {x|x ⊆ Lγ and x is first-order definable over Lγ}, Lδ = Sγ<δ Lγ. 1.2 Admissibility Definition 1.2. (Admissible ordinal[1]) An ordinal α is Σ1 admissible (admissible for short) iff α is a limit ordinal and Lα satisfies Σ1-collection: ∀φ(x, y) ∈ Σ1(Lα).Lα |= ∀u[∀x ∈ u∃y.φ(x, y) =⇒ ∃z∀x ∈ u∃y ∈ z.φ(x, y)] where Lα is the α-th level of the Gödel’s Constructible Hierarchy (definition 1.1).
    [Show full text]
  • Symmetric Enumeration Reducibility
    SYMMETRIC ENUMERATION REDUCIBILITY CHARLES M. HARRIS DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS, LEEDS, UK. Abstract. Symmetric Enumeration reducibility ( ≤se ) is a subrelation of Enu- meration reducibility (≤e) in which both the positive and negative informa- tion content of sets is compared. In contrast with Turing reducibility (≤T) however, the positive and negative parts of this relation are separate. A basic classification of ≤se in terms of standard reducibilities is carried out and it is shown that the natural embedding of the Turing degrees into the Enumera- tion degrees easily translates to this context. A generalisation of the relativised Arithmetical Hierarchy is achieved by replacing the relation c.e. in by ≤e and ≤T by ≤se in the underlying framework of the latter. 1. Introduction The structure of the relativised Arithmetical Hierarchy is dictated by the relation computably enumerable in (c.e. in) in the sense that a set belongs to level n + 1 of the hierarchy if either it or its complement is c.e. in some set belonging to level n. This of course means that each level is the union of a positive (Σ) class and a negative (Π) class. The intersection (∆) of these classes comprises, by definition, those sets B such that B is Turing reducible to (i.e. B and B are both c.e. in) a set in the antecedent level. A natural question to ask is whether one can refine the framework of the rela- tivised Arithmetical Hierarchy to the context of Enumeration Reducibility. In other words, can one define a similar hierarchy in which the levels are dictated by the relation enumeration reducible to (≤e) and which is identical to the Arithmetical Hierarchy when relativised to graphs of characteristic functions (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Enumeration Order Equivalency
    Enumeration Order Equivalency Ali Akbar Safilian (AmirKabir University of Technology, Tehran, Iran [email protected] ) Farzad Didehvar (AmirKabir University of Technology, Tehran, Iran [email protected] ) Let ̻ ɛ ͈ be an infinite recursively enumerable set. There are some total computable functions ͜: ͈ Ŵ ̻ connected with a Turing machine such that ̻ Ɣ ʜ͜ʚ1ʛ, ͜ʚ2ʛ,… ʝ. Definition 2.1 (Listing) A listing of an infinite r.e. set ̻ ɛ ͈ is a bijective computable function ͚: ͈ Ŵ ̻. As mentioned above we can connect every Turing machine with a listing uniquely. Namely, each listing shows the enumeration order of the elements enumerated by the related Turing machine. In the following, we define a reduction on listings and sets based on enumeration orders. Definition 2.2 (Enumeration Order Reducibility on Listings and sets) 1. For listings ͚, ͛: ͈ Ŵ ͈ we say ͚ is “Enumeration order reducible” to ͛ and write ͚ ƙ * ͛, if and only if, Ǣ͝ Ɨ ͞, (͚ʚ͝ʛ Ƙ ͚ʚ͞ʛ ƴ ͛ʚ͝ʛ Ƙ ͛ʚ͞ʛʛ. 2. For r.e. sets ̻, ̼ ɛ ͈, we say ̻ is “Enumeration order reducible” to ̼ and write ̻ ƙ * ̼, if and only if, for any listing ͛ of ̼ there exist some computable function ̀ (from the listings of ̼ to the listings of ̻) such that ̀ ʚ͛ʛ ƙ * ͛. 3. For two listings ͚, ͛ (r.e. sets ̻, ̼), we say ͚ is “Enumeration order equivalent” to ͛ and write ͚ ȸ * ͛ (̻ ȸ * ̼) ,if and only if, both ͚ ƙ * ͛ and ͛ ƙ * ͚ (̻ ƙ * ̼ and ̼ ƙ * ̻) Let ̻ be an r.e.
    [Show full text]
  • On Sets Polynomially Enumerable by Iteration*
    Theoretical Computer Science 80 ( 1991 ) 2(13-225 203 Elsevier On sets polynomially enumerable by iteration* Lane A. Hemachandra** Department oJ Computer Science. Univer.~iO. q/' Roche~ter. Rochester. N Y 14627. U.S.A. Albrecht Hoene and Dirk Siefkes Fachhereich Inlormalik. Technische Unit,er.sitiit Berlin. D.1000 Berlin I0. Fed. Rep. Germany Paul Young*** Department of Computer Science and Engineering, FR-35, Unirer~ity O! Washington, Seattle, WA 98195, U.S.A. Abxtracl Hemachandra, L.A.. A. Hoene, D. Siefkes and P. Young. On sets polynomially enumerable by iteration, Theoretical Computer Science 80 ( 1991 ) 203-225. Sets whose members are enumerated by some Turin$ machine are called recursively enumerable. We define a set to be po(rnomially enumerahle hy iteration if its members are e~cientlr enumerated by iterated application of some Turin8 machine. We prove that many complex sets--including all exponential-time complete s¢:.,, all NP-complete sets yet obtained by direct construction, and the complements of all such sets--are polynomially enumen'able by iteration. These results follow from more general results. In fact. we show that all recursi~,ely enumerabl¢ sets that are ['.,,-sel.freducihle are polynomially enumerable by iteration, and that all recursive sets that are ~'.,,-wl[reducihle i.ire bi-enumerable. We also ,how thai when Ihe ~ ~'.,-self-reduction is via a function whose inverse is computable in polynomial time, then the above results hold with the polynomial enumeration gi,,en by a function whose inverse is computable in pol.~nomial time. In the final section of the paper we show that ato NP.complete set can be iteratively enumerated in lexicographically increasing order unless the polynomial time hierarchy collapses to N P.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Results on Enumeration Reductibility
    SOME RESULTS ENUMERATION REDUCIBILITY by LANCE GUTTERIDGE B.Sc., University of British Columbia, 1967 M.Sc., University of British Columbia, 1969 A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREZWNTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in the Department of Mathematics LANCE GUTTERIDGE 1971 SIMON FR9SER 'VNIVERS ITY AUGUST 1971 APPROVAL Name : Lance Gutteridge Degree : Doctor of Philosophy Title of Dissertation: Some results on enumeration reducibility 1 Examining Committee: 7 , --L-- - I ' r , Chairman: N. R. Reilly ,' A. H. Lachlan Senior Supervisor A. R. Freedman - .- - G. E. Sacks External Examiner, Professor, Massachusetts Institute of Technology Cambridge, Mass. Date ~pproved: September 24, 1971 ABSTRACT Enumeration reducibility was defined by Friedberg and Rogers in 1959. Medvedev showed that there are partial degrees which are not total. Rogers in his book Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability gives all the basic results and definitions concerning enumeration reducibility and the partial degrees. He mentions in this book that the existence of a minimal partial degree is an open problem. In this thesis it is shown that there are no minimal partial degrees. This leads naturally to the conjecture that the partial degrees are dense. This thesis leaves this question unanswered, but it is shown that there are no degrees minimal above a total degree, and there are at most countably many degrees minimal above a non-total degree. J. W. Case has proved several results about the partial degrees. He conjectured that there is no set in a total degree whose complement is in a non-total degree. In this thesis that conjecture is disproved.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility
    Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility Charles M. Harris Department Of Mathematics University of Leeds Computability Theory Seminar, Autumn 2009 (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 1 / 34 Outline 1 Introducing Enumeration Reducibility The Basic Definitions Examples Alternative definitions 2 Properties of De Definition of 0e Lattice Theoretic Properties (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 2 / 34 Outline 3 The Enumeration Jump Operator The Enumeration Jump (over sets) The Enumeration Jump Operator 4 Embedding DT into De Total Degrees Definition of the Embedding Quasi-minimal Enumeration Degrees (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 3 / 34 Outline 5 Further Properties of De Exact Pairs and Branching Density and Minimality Next Week (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 4 / 34 Subsection Guide 1 Introducing Enumeration Reducibility The Basic Definitions Examples Alternative definitions 2 Properties of De Definition of 0e Lattice Theoretic Properties (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 5 / 34 What is enumeration reducibility? Definition (Intuitive) A≤e B if there exists an effective procedure that, given any enumeration of B, computes an enumeration A. Definition (Formal) A≤e B if there exists a c.e. set W such that for all x 2 ! x 2 A iff 9u [ hx; ui 2 W & Du ⊆ B ] This is written A = ΦW (B). (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 6 / 34 Subsection Guide 1 Introducing Enumeration Reducibility The Basic Definitions Examples Alternative definitions 2 Properties of De Definition of 0e Lattice Theoretic Properties (University Of Leeds) Introduction to Enumeration Reducibility CTS 2009 7 / 34 Examples of sets W and X such that x 2 A iff 9D ( hx; Di 2 W & D ⊆ X ) A≤e A via the c.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Symmetric Enumeration Reducibility
    Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Symmetric Enumeration Reducibility Charles M. Harris Department Of Mathematics University of Leeds Computability Theory Seminar, Autumn 2005 Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Outline 1 Enumeration Reducibility The Basic Definitions Examples Alternative definitions 2 Properties of ≤se Defining ≤se Classifying ≤se Basic Structure of Dse Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Outline 1 Enumeration Reducibility The Basic Definitions Examples Alternative definitions 2 Properties of ≤se Defining ≤se Classifying ≤se Basic Structure of Dse Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Outline 3 DT and Dse Characteristic Degrees Definition of the Embedding Quasi-minimal Degrees 4 Jump Operators The Enumeration Jump The Symmetric Enumeration Jump Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Outline 3 DT and Dse Characteristic Degrees Definition of the Embedding Quasi-minimal Degrees 4 Jump Operators The Enumeration Jump The Symmetric Enumeration Jump Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Outline 5 Some Properties of Dse The c.e. and co-c.e. degrees Minimal and Exact Pairs Next Week Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse Subsection Guide 1 Enumeration Reducibility The Basic Definitions Examples Alternative definitions 2 Properties of ≤se Defining ≤se Classifying ≤se Basic Structure of Dse Enumeration Reducibility Properties of ≤se DT and Dse Jump Operators Some Properties of Dse What is enumeration reducibility? Definition (Intuitive) A≤e B if there exists an effective procedure that, given any enumeration of B, computes an enumeration A.
    [Show full text]
  • Enumeration Degrees
    Decidability and Definability in the 0 Σ2-Enumeration Degrees By Thomas F. Kent A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Mathematics) at the UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN – MADISON 2005 i Abstract Enumeration reducibility was introduced by Friedberg and Rogers in 1959 as a positive reducibility between sets. The enumeration degrees provide a wider con- text in which to view the Turing degrees by allowing us to use any set as an oracle instead of just total functions. However, in spite of the fact that there are several applications of enumeration reducibility in computable mathematics, until recently relatively little research had been done in this area. In Chapter 2 of my thesis, I show that the ∀∃∀-fragment of the first order 0 theory of the Σ2-enumeration degrees is undecidable. I then show how this result actually demonstrates that the ∀∃∀-theory of any substructure of the enumeration 0 degrees which contains the ∆2-degrees is undecidable. In Chapter 3, I present current research that Andrea Sorbi and I are engaged in, in regards to classifying 0 properties of non-splitting Σ2-degrees. In particular I give proofs that there is a 0 0 properly Σ2-enumeration degree and that every ∆2-enumeration degree bounds a 0 non-splitting ∆2-degree. Advisor: Prof. Steffen Lempp ii Acknowledgements I am grateful to Steffen Lempp, my thesis advisor, for all the time, effort, and patience that he put in on my behalf. His insight and suggestions have been of great worth to me, both in and out of my research.
    [Show full text]
  • A. Definitions of Reductions and Complexity Classes, and Notation List
    A. Definitions of Reductions and Complexity Classes, and N otation List A.I Reductions Below, in naming the reductions, "polynomial-time" is implicit unless ot her­ wise noted, e.g., "many-one reduction" means "many-one polynomial-time reduction." This list sorts among t he :Sb first by b, and in the case of identical b's, bya. :S -y - Gamma reduction. -A :S -y B if there is a nondeterministic polynomial-time machine N such that (a) for each st ring x, N(x) has at least one accepting path, and (b) for each string x and each accepting path p of N(x) it holds that: x E A if and only if the output of N(x) on path p is an element of B. :S ~ - Many-one reduction. -A :S~ B if (3f E FP)(Vx)[x E A {=} f(x) EB] . :S~ o s - (Globally) Positive Turing reduction. -A :S~o s B if there is a deterministic Turing machine Mand a polyno­ mial q such that 1. (VD)[runtimeMD(x):s q(lxl)], B 2. A = L(M ), and 3. (VC, D)[C ç D =} L(MC) ç L(MD)]. :S:08 - Locally positive Turing reduction. -A :S:os B if there is a deterministic polynomial-time Turing machine M such that 1. A = L(MB), 2. (VC)[L(M BUC) :2 L(MB)] , and 3. (VC)[L(M B- C) ç L(MB)] . :ST - Exponential-time Turing reduction. -A :ST B if A E EB. If A E EB via an exponential-time machine, M, having the property that on each input of length n it holds that M makes at most g(n) queries to its orade, we write A :S~ ( n ) - T B.
    [Show full text]
  • Enumeration Reducibility and Computable Structure Theory
    ENUMERATION REDUCIBILITY AND COMPUTABLE STRUCTURE THEORY ALEXANDRA A. SOSKOVA AND MARIYA I. SOSKOVA 1. Introduction In classical computability theory the main underlying structure is that of the natural numbers or equivalently a structure consisting of some constructive objects, such as words in a finite alphabet. In the 1960's computability theorists saw it as a challenge to extend the notion of computable to arbitrary structure. The resulting subfield of computability theory is commonly referred to as computability on abstract structures. One approach towards this is the theory of computability in admissible sets of the hereditarily finite superstructure HF(A) over a structure A. The development of computability on ordinals was initiated by Kreisel and Sacks [43, 42], who investigated computability notions on the first incomputable ordinal, and then further developed by Kripke and Platek [44, 58] on arbitrary admissible ordinals and by Barwise [6], who considered admissible sets with urelements. The notion of Σ-definability on HF(A), introduced and studied by Ershov [16, 17] and his students Goncharov, Morozov, Puzarenko, Stukachev, Korovina, etc., is a model of nondeterministic computability on A. A survey of results on HF-computability and on abstract computability based on the notion of Σ-definability can be found in [18, 95]. Montague [53] took a model theoretic approach to generalized computability theory, considering computability as definability in higher order logics. The approach towards abstract computability that ultimately lead to the results discussed in this article starts with searching for ways in which one can identify abstract computability on a structure internally. Let A be an arbitrary abstract structure.
    [Show full text]