I Aim to Show That Socrates Extensively Uses Rhetoric in the Gorgias

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

I Aim to Show That Socrates Extensively Uses Rhetoric in the Gorgias COLLOQUIUM 3 RHETORIC, REFUTATION, AND WHAT SOCRATES BELIEVES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS HENRYTELOH ABSTRACT I argue that Socrates employs rhetoric on Gorgias, Polus, and Callicles in the Gorgias. Moreover, in each conversation, Socrates distinguishes good from bad rhetoric, and he uses good rhetoric on his interlocutors. Socrates, I main­ tain, believes that good rhetoric is a techne because it aims at the health of the soul. Finally, I defend the view that good rhetoric is a techne against the criticisms of Brickhouse and Smith, and Roochnik, as well as the fact that in the Gorgias Socrates does not tum his interlocutors to a life of philosophy. I aim to show that Socrates extensively uses rhetoric in the Gorgias; in fact, it is reasonable to categorize a large part of what Socrates does in that dialogue as rhetorical. Socrates uses rhetoric as part of his philosophical and educational task to attempt a care of his interlocutors' souls ('l'uxa{). I further aim to show that Socrates recognizes that he uses rhetoric, and that he implies that the sort of rhetoric which he uses is a real art ('rEXVTl) of rhetoric. To support this claim I argue that in each of his conversations with Gorgias, Polus, and Callicles, Socrates distinguishes good from bad rhetoric where the former aims at the good of an interlocutor's soul, and the latter is only a repertoire of techniques for persuasion, which serve whatever aim a rhetorician may have. To accomplish my task I will argue the following for each of Socrates' three conversations: (a) that Socrates uses rhetoric, (b) that he thinks his rhetoric to be an art, and (c) he believes that his use of this art aims to improve the souls of his interlocutors. A result of my interpretation is that Socrates' words and deeds "chime in harmony together" (Laches 193d-e ). The art he talks about is the art he uses. A number of interpreters believe that the Gorgias constitutes a condem­ nation of all rhetoric, and it is one of my aims to show that this position is mistaken 1 Martha Nussbaum says the following in The Fragility of Good­ ness.2 1 Many commentators believe that Socrates condemns rhetoric. See among others, Thompson 1894, xiv-xviii; Zeller 1876, 190; Pater 1920, ch. 4; Rendalll977, 165; Cushman 1958, 231; Jaeger 1943, 1851. Kaufman 1979, 115-125 states that Plato's condemnation of 58 HENRYTELOH The last part of the dialogue [Phaedrus] breaks with the Gorgias' general condemnation of rhetoric, describing a 'true' rhetorical art in which a central place is given to the knowledge, through experience, of the souls of individu­ als. (268a-b) Presumably Nussbaum would agree that Socrates states or implies the "general condemnation of rhetoric" in the Gorg. If we conjoin Nuss­ baum's claim with my arguments that Socrates uses rhetoric, and knows that he uses rhetoric, then Socrates is a hypocrite who condemns what he uses. Socrates is no better than any other relativistic rhetorician who tries to outmuscle his opponents. 3 Can we save Socrates from this charge? I think we can. My distinction between good rhetoric (the art of rhetoric) and bad rhetoric (no art at all) will exonerate Socrates from the charge of hypocrisy; Socrates practices the art of rhetoric which aims at the care of the soul, while he condemns a rhetoric which is only concerned with tech­ niques for persuasion. 4 Moreover, we can explain why Socrates implies praise of one type of rhetoric with Gorgias, namely, the real art, and con­ demns another with Polus, namely, the empirical knack (Ef.ll"t:ctp{a) which only consists ofthe techniques for persuasion (see Gorg. 450b-c, 452e). 5 rhetoric is conditional, but he also believes that the rhetoric Socrates practices is defective. Kaufman says that dialectic and rhetoric are complementary, but he does not say what this means. Black 1958, 365-369 argues that Socrates only attacks Gorgias' view of rhetoric; a position with which I agree. He goes on to assert that the same view of rhetoric is found in both the Gorgias and the Phaedrus, a view which I deny. Among those who realize that the Gorg. is mostly rhetoric are Lewis 1986, 195-210, and Tarrant 2002, 61-78. Roochnik 1995, 82 denies that there is a sharp distinction between rhetoric and philosophy, and that Socrates is ambiguous in his hostility to rhetoric. As we will see, I disagree with the latter claim. A. Spitzer 1975, 15-21 holds the position closest to mine. She distinguishes true from false rhetoric, and correctly sees that Socrates is the true rhetorician. Moreoever, she sees that Socrates addresses different characters differently in order to care for their souls. She does not, however, analyze Socrates' use of rhetoric or address the issue of techne. Stauffer 2006, 80, 133 mentions once that Socrates uses rhetoric on Polus, and he mentions that Socrates uses rhetorical punishment on Callicles, but neither of these claims is devel­ oped, and on p. 160 he states that Socrates is unwilling to take up a new good rhetoric. Stauffer is too concerned with his claim that Socrates wants Gorgias to embrace the new rhetoric, to see clearly that Socrates does it. 2 Nussbaum 1979, 227. 3 The connection between rhetoric and relativism is the following: the best way to per­ suade the people is to tell them what they want, but what they want changes from context to context. 4 I say that Socrates aims at care because it is clear to him that he faces an uphill battle which he well might lose. The reason he might lose is that his interlocutors are corrupted by society, and filled with imperialistic desires for power. 5 This is in opposition to Roochnik's position. See Roochnik 1995, 87 and 1996, 189. .
Recommended publications
  • Refuting Polus (466–481)
    Γοργίας | Gorgias 8 Refuting Polus (466–481) 1. Genuine and Spurious Expertise (463d–465d)1 Mind (politikē) Body (sōmatos therapeias) regulative corrective regulative corrective true or genuine good state, legislative justice exercise medicine technē; leads to physical (nomothetikē) (dikaiosunē) (gumnastikē) (iatrikē) real being and mental health spurious pseudo- merely apparent technē, ‘good’ state; sophistry rhetoric cosmetics cookery appearance, forms of flattery (sophistikē) (rhetorikē) (kommōtikē) (opsopoiikē) simulacrum; (kolakeia), ‘fake’ being see 464c–d 2. Refuting Polus in Four Stages First Paradox. Rhetors are the least powerful members of society. (466b–468e) 1.1 Power is a good thing (agathon) for its possessor. 1.2 Rhetoric lacks logos (465a), and hence its aim cannot be our welfare (i.e. what is best for us: to beltiston). 1.3 Rhetors do not know what is best for them. 1.4 Rhetors only do what seems best for them. (This follows on from the flattery discussion; see table above.) 1.5 There is a difference between doing what one wants and doing what seems best (for one to do). (For those who know, these two things coincide—this is real power.) 1.6 Things are either good (agathon), bad (kakon), or indifferent (metaxu [= in between], adiaphora). We avoid what is bad, choose or seek what is good, and use indifferents as a means for good. 1.7 Everyone does things in pursuit of good. 1.8 We want (boulesthai) good things because they are in our interest (ōphelima). Only the good is best for us. 1.9 Actions that produce harm do not reflect one’s will: agents only do what seems best or beneficial, but they do not want these actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Phaedrus Plato
    Phaedrus Plato TRANSLATED BY BENJAMIN JOWETT ROMAN ROADS MEDIA Classical education, from a Christian perspective, created for the homeschool. Roman Roads combines its technical expertise with the experience of established authorities in the field of classical education to create quality video courses and resources tailored to the homeschooler. Just as the first century roads of the Roman Empire were the physical means by which the early church spread the gospel far and wide, so Roman Roads Media uses today’s technology to bring timeless truth, goodness, and beauty into your home. By combining excellent instruction augmented with visual aids and examples, we help inspire in your children a lifelong love of learning. Phaedrus by Plato translated by Benjamin Jowett This text was designed to accompany Roman Roads Media's 4-year video course Old Western Culture: A Christian Approach to the Great Books. For more information visit: www.romanroadsmedia.com. Other video courses by Roman Roads Media include: Grammar of Poetry featuring Matt Whitling Introductory Logic taught by Jim Nance Intermediate Logic taught by Jim Nance French Cuisine taught by Francis Foucachon Copyright © 2013 by Roman Roads Media, LLC Roman Roads Media 739 S Hayes St, Moscow, Idaho 83843 A ROMAN ROADS ETEXT Phaedrus Plato TRANSLATED BY BENJAMIN JOWETT INTRODUCTION The Phaedrus is closely connected with the Symposium, and may be regarded either as introducing or following it. The two Dialogues together contain the whole philosophy of Plato on the nature of love, which in the Republic and in the later writings of Plato is only introduced playfully or as a figure of speech.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2014 Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2014). Rhetoric and Platonism in fifth-century Athens. In R. C. Fowler (Ed.), Plato in the third sophistic (pp. 57-72). De Gruyter. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori (Trinity University) Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens There are reasons to believe that relations between Platonism and rhetoric in Athens during the fifth century CE were rather close.Z Both were major pillars of pagan cul- ture, or paideia, and thus essential elements in the defense of paganism against in- creasingly powerful and repressive Christian opponents. It is easy to imagine that, under these circumstances, paganism was closing ranks and that philosophers and orators united in their efforts to save traditional ways and values. Although there is no doubt some truth to this view, a closer look reveals that the relations be- tween philosophy and rhetoric were rather more complicated. In what follows, I will discuss these relations with a view to the Platonist school of Athens. By “the Platon- ist school of Athens” I mean the Platonist school founded by Plutarch of Athens in the late fourth century CE, and reaching a famous end under the leadership of Dam- ascius in 529.X I will first survey the evidence for the attitudes towards rhetoric pre- vailing amongst the most important Athenian Platonists of the time.
    [Show full text]
  • Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Excerpt More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Excerpt More information Gorgias Dramatis personae Dates of birth and death given below are conjectural, except for Socrates. CALLICLES His boyfriend Demos, son of Plato’s stepfather Pyrilampes, was in Dodds’s words (Plato: Gorgias, p., relying here primarily on Aristophanes’ Wasps ) ‘a leading beauty about ’. On usual assumptions about relative ages of lover and beloved, we might infer that Callicles was probably in his mid to late twen- ties at the same point in time. Although his ambition to succeed in politics makes Socrates describe him as lover of the Athenian demos (punning on Demos), this behaviour must be interpreted as opportunistic on Callicles’ part. The views Plato attributes to him are anything but democratic. And it is probably significant that of the friends of Callicles mentioned at c, one at least – Andron – is known to have been a member of the short-lived oligarchic regime of the Four Hundred in , and the other two probably to be identified with Athenians known from other evidence to have been wealthy men. There is no trace of Callicles in history outside the Gorgias. It seems likely that for whatever reason his ambitions were unfulfilled. CHAEREPHON (–) One of Socrates’ oldest and closest friends, and a well-known figure in the Athens of the Peloponnesian War, frequently the topic of jokes on the comic stage, perhaps in part because of his demonic energy (Apology a, Charmides b). © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Excerpt More information Gorgias Aristophanes treats him as Socrates’ partner in running the bogus philosophical school portrayed in the Clouds of BC.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 515 Galen, Outline of Empiricism.Docx
    PHI 515: Topics in the History of Philosophy Hendrik Lorenz and Benjamin Morison Galen’s Outline of Empiricism In this short treatise, Galen provides a fairly detailed presentation of the views of an ancient medical school according to which medical knowledge, the knowledge by possessing which one is a medical doctor, is just a matter of experience, without reason, conceived of as a power to grasp imperceptible essences or natures of things, playing any role either in the constitution or in the formation of such knowledge. We want to understand this way of thinking about medical knowledge in its own right by carefully studying Galen’s treatise. But we also want to study it in the broader context of ancient theories and debates about the nature of expert knowledge. Medical Empiricism needs to be understood in part as a reaction to the high-powered theoretical conceptions of reason introduced or relied on by Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics, to the effect that reason is a power to grasp imperceptible natures of things and to grasp imperceptible relations such as logical consequence and incompatibility. But it also needs to be understood as presupposing and building on a tradition of thinkers who held that expert knowledge was just a matter of observation, memory, and experience, like Polus (Aristotle, Metaphysics A 1, 981a3-5) and Alcmaeon of Croton (?) (Phaedo 96 b). In fact, Medical Empiricism is the most fully articulated or anyhow the best- preserved example of this tradition that is available to us. Another kind of context that is relevant background to a study of Medical Empiricism is the context of debates among it and its rival medical schools, namely various forms of Rationalism, and Methodism.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the "Phaedrus" Author(S): Brad Mcadon Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol
    Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the "Phaedrus" Author(s): Brad McAdon Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol. 23, No. 1 (2004), pp. 21-39 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20176594 Accessed: 22/09/2010 21:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=taylorfrancis. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Rhetoric Review. http://www.jstor.org Brad McAdon University of Memphis Plato's Denunciation of Rhetoric in the Phaedrus Contrary to a prevailing view within rhetoric and composition circles thatfinds a positive view of rhetoric in the Phaedrus, / contend that Plato mockingly de nounces rhetoric in the Phaedrus.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle-Rhetoric.Pdf
    Rhetoric Aristotle (Translated by W. Rhys Roberts) Book I 1 Rhetoric is the counterpart of Dialectic. Both alike are con- cerned with such things as come, more or less, within the general ken of all men and belong to no definite science. Accordingly all men make use, more or less, of both; for to a certain extent all men attempt to discuss statements and to maintain them, to defend themselves and to attack others. Ordinary people do this either at random or through practice and from acquired habit. Both ways being possible, the subject can plainly be handled systematically, for it is possible to inquire the reason why some speakers succeed through practice and others spontaneously; and every one will at once agree that such an inquiry is the function of an art. Now, the framers of the current treatises on rhetoric have cons- tructed but a small portion of that art. The modes of persuasion are the only true constituents of the art: everything else is me- rely accessory. These writers, however, say nothing about en- thymemes, which are the substance of rhetorical persuasion, but deal mainly with non-essentials. The arousing of prejudice, pity, anger, and similar emotions has nothing to do with the essential facts, but is merely a personal appeal to the man who is judging the case. Consequently if the rules for trials which are now laid down some states-especially in well-governed states-were applied everywhere, such people would have nothing to say. All men, no doubt, think that the laws should prescribe such rules, but some, as in the court of Areopagus, give practical effect to their thoughts 4 Aristotle and forbid talk about non-essentials.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetorical Being: a Metaphysics of Freedom and Essence Nathan Wagner Georgia State University
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Georgia State University Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University English Dissertations Department of English 4-30-2018 Rhetorical Being: A Metaphysics of Freedom and Essence Nathan Wagner Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_diss Recommended Citation Wagner, Nathan, "Rhetorical Being: A Metaphysics of Freedom and Essence." Dissertation, Georgia State University, 2018. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_diss/191 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of English at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in English Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RHETORICAL BEING: A METAPHYSICS OF FREEDOM AND ESSENCE by NATHAN R. WAGNER Under the Direction of Lynée Lewis Gaillet, PhD and Michael Harker, PhD ABSTRACT My dissertation examines the connection between rhetoric and being. I critique subject- oriented phenomenological assumptions that have perpetuated for decades within rhetorical theory and offer an alternative metaphysical methodology. I initially focus on Lloyd Bitzer and Richard Vatz’s debate about the rhetorical situation, which shaped accepted theories of subjectivity for decades to come. I offer an alternative model of the subject that is based on Augustine’s metaphysical model of being, and I focus on this notion of rhetorical being as a means of revealing knowledge as potentially, contextually already present through readings of Martin Heidegger and Emmanuel Levinas’s work. Augustine’s paradigm of the human being as perpetually free yet dependent on contextual surroundings for meaning, whether empirical or ephemeral, affords this study a framework through which to examine the subject within the rhetorical situation.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Rhetoric: the Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion
    Portland State University PDXScholar Young Historians Conference Young Historians Conference 2014 Apr 29th, 10:30 AM - 11:45 AM Aristotle's Rhetoric: The Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion Claire Floyd-Lapp Grant High School Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/younghistorians Part of the Intellectual History Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Floyd-Lapp, Claire, "Aristotle's Rhetoric: The Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion" (2014). Young Historians Conference. 12. https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/younghistorians/2014/oralpres/12 This Event is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Young Historians Conference by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. Aristotle’s Rhetoric The Power of Words and the Continued Relevance of Persuasion Claire Floyd-Lapp 19 March 2014 PSU World History 105 Floyd-Lapp 1 A critical work in the field of persuasion—Aristotle essentially established the discipline—Rhetoric offers historians a framework by which to study the subject’s history. In his text, Aristotle argues what successful rhetoric entails, for what purposes rhetoric should be used, and what effective rhetoricians do. Aristotle’s Rhetoric speaks to the power of words and has remained relevant since its publication. Rhetoric offers writers and speakers a foundation from which to build their arguments. Although the perceived importance of persuasion has faded since Aristotle’s time, we still use words, and many scholars encourage the reclamation of rhetoric.
    [Show full text]
  • Full Thesis FINISHED 4-20-09
    BEING IN PLACE: ON UNITY AND BODY IN ATISTOTLE A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Robert Samuel Leib May, 2009 i Thesis written by Robert Samuel Leib B.A., Mount St. Mary’s University, 2005 M.A., St. John’s College, Annapolis, 2007 M.A., Kent State University, 2009 Approved by _______________Gina Zavota_____________, Advisor _______________Polycarp Ikuenobe________, Acting Chair, Department of Philosophy _______________Timothy Moerland________, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS…………………………………………………………...iv INTRODUCTION……………………………………………..…………………….1 Chapter I. Context...………...........................................................................................8 1. The Physics: Nature and Change…………………………………..8 2. The Task of the Physicist………………………………………….16 3. Place and Things…………………………………………………..19 4. The Boat Puzzle……………………………………………………23 II. Benjamin Morison’s On Location...............................................................33 1. Kinds of Containment……………………………………………...33 2. The Maximal Surrounder……………...…………………………..37 3. Problems with Morison’s Interpretation…………………………...41 4. Place is Not Location…………………...…….……………………45 III. Unity and Body..........................................................................................54 1. Is the Universe a Body?...................................................................54 2. Oneness, Unity, and Parts………………………..………………..61 3. Heaps, Wholes, and Physical
    [Show full text]
  • An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle) Phillip Keith St
    Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal Issue 20 Article 28 7-1-1999 An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle) Phillip Keith St. Cloud State University Sandra Z. Keith St. Cloud State University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj Part of the Intellectual History Commons, Logic and Foundations Commons, and the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Keith, Phillip and Keith, Sandra Z. (1999) "An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle)," Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal: Iss. 20, Article 28. Available at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj/vol1/iss20/28 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Claremont at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. An Informal History of Classical Rhetoric for Mathematicians (Plato and Aristotle) Philip Keith Sandy Z. Keith St. Cloud State University, MN Rhetoric, “the art of persuasion,” gets a bad rap among advantage for plaintiffs and accused, and as in courts workers in the mathematical sciences. This is unfor- today, the expression of pain and suffering would tunate, since although mathematics is concerned pri- carry a lot of weight. Not surprisingly, some entre- marily with the demonstration of formal truth, math- preneurial individuals offered lessons in speaking to ematicians do live in the world and need to concern get maximum benefit from these situations. The best themselves with persuading students, business agents known of these individuals are Corax and Tisias, to and others not on the mathematical team of the im- whom the art of rhetoric is traced by Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Review I: from Ancient Greece Through Rome
    2 Historical Review I: From Ancient Greece through Rome This chapter traces the evolution of thought on style from Ancient Greece through the end of antiquity, emphasizing primary texts and interpretations by contemporary historians. Teachers may want to consult the classical treatises described here to develop a sense of what style has meant to different rhetoricians over time. Most of the authors of these treatises were themselves educators and, even if they do not provide particular instructions about how to teach style, their discus- sions of this canon directly impact promoting the value of style in con- temporary college classrooms. These treatises take a range of positions regarding the importance of style to the overall theorizing and teach- ing of rhetoric and writing. Some treatises address style as a small part of a larger rhetorical system, some discuss style as a substantial means of developing arguments, and others are devoted entirely to style, and see it as the most central aspect of effective discourse. Aristotle treated style as one small component of rhetoric, and em- phasized clarity and plainness. By contrast, later rhetoricians such as Demetrius, Longinus, and (much later) Erasmus elevated style as a significant rhetorical tool, encouraging students to develop a wide rep- ertoire of rhetorical devices to enhance their persuasiveness with dif- ferent audiences. The Roman rhetorician Quintilian’s Education of the Orator remains the most thorough and comprehensive catalog of sty- listic devices and their appropriate use in different rhetorical situations. A discussion of St. Augustine’s adaptation of the classical tradition for preaching concludes this chapter.
    [Show full text]