And Self-Interpretation Natural Emotions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

And Self-Interpretation Natural Emotions Budapest Seminars in Early Modern Philosophy 2 & 3 N N O I NS O With the publication of the papers of the First Budapest Semi- I ETAT nar in Early Modern Philosophy in 2017, we accomplished over- OT R P coming such unfruitful divisions as the time-honoured inter- M E pretive distinction between “rationalists” and “empiricists”, lib- erating our perspectives from the rigid prejudices of simplifying handbooks. We also prepared the frame for further in-depth TURAL investigations in other areas of Early Modern thought, such as LF-INTER A E S are presented in our volume. It comprises papers based on the N contributions to the Second and Third Budapest Seminar in Ear- ly Modern Philosophy, held on 26–27 October 2017, and on 8–9 October 2018 at Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest. The topics Y AND T HT AND of both Seminars are relevant not only for the Early Modern phi- I losophy but also for our contemporary philosophical attempts G to find access to present reality: constructions of personal iden- Ri tity, and the multifarious relationship between theories and practices of natural right and the claims to live up to our nat- ural emotions. When composing this volume, our aim was not to present a systematic survey of any of these areas of topics in A N TURAL Early Modern philosophy. Rather, our modest goal was to foster & collaboration among researchers working in different countries IDENTPERSONAL and traditions. Many of the papers published here are already in implicit or explicit dialogue with others. We hope that they will generate more of an exchange of ideas both in early modern scholarship and in several related areas and disciplines. I LA (eds) ZA S T I ÓTH PERSONAL IDENTITY T JUD BTK . AND SELF-INTERPRETATION STVÁN STVÁN I NATURAL RiGHT AND OROS B & ÉR ISBN 978-963-489-228-1 V NATURAL EMOTIONS I L O Á G BOR G ÁBOR BOROS . JUDIT SZALAI . OLIVÉR ISTVÁN TÓTH (eds) Personal Identity and Self-Interpretation & Natural Right and Natural Emotions Budapest Seminars in Early Modern Philosophy 2 & 3 Gábor Boros – Judit Szalai – Olivér István Tóth (eds) Personal Identity and Self-Interpretation & Natural Right and Natural Emotions Budapest Seminars in Early Modern Philosophy 2 & 3 budapest • 2020 Cover: The Portrait's Box by Ridolfo del Ghirlandaio (1506–1510; Uffizi Museum) Photo: © Web Gallery of Art, 2011 © Authors, 2020 © Editors, 2020 ISBN 978-963-489-228-1 ISBN 978-963-489-229-8 (pdf) www.eotvoskiado.hu Executive Publisher: the Dean of the Faculty of Humanities of Eötvös Loránd University Layout: Ádám Bornemissza Cover: Ildikó Csele Kmotrik Print: CC Printing Ltd Table of Contents Introduction . ..................................................... 7 PERSONAL IDENTITY Judit Szalai: States of the “Person” in Descartes . 13 Przemysław Gut: Leibniz on Personal Identity . ....................... 22 Charles T. Wolfe: Diderot and Materialist Theories of Self . .............. 37 Ákos Forczek: Apperception and Affinity: Kant on the Material Condition of the Identity of the “Psychological Person” . 53 SELF-KNOWLEDGE Bartosz Żukowski: Richard Burthogge’s Epistemology and the Problem of Self-Knowledge . 69 Peter West: Knowing Me, Knowing You: Berkeley on Self-Knowledge and Other Spirits . 84 NATURAL LAW Wilhelm Schmidt-Biggemann: The Space for Emotions in Natural Law. 107 Szilárd Tattay: Francisco Suárez and Modern Rationalist Natural Law Theories . ........................................ 121 Gábor Boros: Natural Right and Worldly Emotions of Love: Descartes, Molière, Spinoza . 139 Heikki Haara: The Concept of Simple Esteem inDe jure naturae et gentium . 153 József Simon: Shame, Common Wealth and Religion in the Thought of Miklós Bethlen (1642–1714) . 167 Mariangela Priarolo: Love and Order: Malebranche and the Feeling of Natural Law . 180 Paolo Santangelo: Chinese Cultures of Love: The “Cult of Qing” and Qing’s “Naturalness” . 198 LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS . ....................................... 221 Gábor Boros – Judit Szalai – Olivér István Tóth Introduction At least from the time when Descartes announced that the mind of the subject is better known to itself than the physical world, self-knowledge and personal identity played a cen- tral role in early modern philosophy. The focal questions in this period include whether the subject can be identified with the knowing mind, whether personal identity is grounded in the identity or some properties of that mind, or is in some manner based in physical reality, and whether self-knowledge is indeed superior to other types of knowledge. Some of the classical answers were given by prominent early modern thinkers, characteristically aiming at compatibility with the new mechanistic natural sciences. Other, lesser-known, but at times comparably promising solutions were offered by philosophers some of whose ideas we have yet to assimilate. This volume is based on papers presented at the Second and Third Budapest Semi- nar in Early Modern Philosophy held at the Eötvös Loránd University of Budapest on 26–27 November 2017, and 8–9 October 2018, respectively. We do not aim at presenting a systematic survey of personal identity, self-knowledge and natural law in early modern philosophy. Instead, we sample texts by less visible authors and re-think better-known positions concerning affectivity and the related conceptual fields in the period. The papers published come from different traditions, and some of them are already in implicit or explicit dialogue with others. We hope that this collection will contribute to the growth of our knowledge about the role of personal identity, self-understanding and natural law in early modern philosophy, and generate a greater exchange of ideas in the broader early modern scholarship. We would like to thank the National Research, Development and Innovation Office (Hungary) for generous funding in the framework of a research project on “Self-Inter- pretation, Emotions, Narrativity” (K120375), which allowed both the organizing of the conferences and the publication of the present volume. We would also like to thank the Student Union of the Faculty of Humanities at ELTE (ELTE BTK HÖK) and of ELTE 7 (EHÖK) for the funding they provided, both for the organization of the conferences and the publication of this volume. Finally, we would like to express our special thanks to Ákos Forczek, who has helped us throughout the entire process. Judit Szalai’s paper revisits the Cartesian notion of the “person”. For Descartes, a person is constituted by a mind conjoined with a body; we know about the mind-body unity via functions that are both mental and physical. How can Descartes spell out these functions in terms of actual states of the mind and the body, given the narrow metaphysical con- straints established by his own philosophy? Szalai’s paper traces the psychophysical pro- cesses involved in the passions in order to see how they can be made sense of in the light of Descartes’ metaphysical and epistemological commitments. Remaining in the Cartesian tradition, Przemysław Gut’s paper targets those inter- pretations of Leibniz’s account of personal identity, according to which Leibniz failed to formulate a coherent theory. Gut argues that Leibniz held the continuity of both the sub- stance and the psychological phenomena necessary for personal identity, because both are grounded in the continuity of the existence of a substantial principle. Gut then identifies this substantial principle with the soul, i.e. the Cartesian thinking “I” that is the ultimate subject of both personal identity and moral responsibility, which are in the focus of Leibniz’s philosophy. Leaving Cartesianism and the seventeenth century behind, Charles T. Wolfe, in his highly engaging paper, takes a look at the broad implications of materialism for early mod- ern theories of the self. His essay accomplishes two things simultaneously. First, it presents Diderot’s materialist theory of the self as constituted by an externalist metaphysical theory and a biological understanding of individuality. Second, it manages to place this early modern development in the much broader context of the history of western philosophy. He argues for the necessity of a revision of the traditional dichotomy between metaphysically sound but mechanistic materialism lacking a viable philosophy of mind and dualism with a sound philosophy of mind built on a shaky metaphysical theory. The last paper in the personal identity section focuses on Immanuel Kant, the key fig- ure of the transition from early modern philosophy to German Idealism. Ákos Forczek in his contribution links Kant’s major critical writings with his less studied texts in his Opus postumum, and maintains that “transcendental affinity” and personal unity are closely re- lated concepts, even though at first glance this is far from obvious. His main focus is the problem of what guarantees that the sensible manifold is suitable for experiencing it with- out violating the autonomy of the sensible. Forczek argues that after the failed attempt of the firstCritique , and the question-begging answer of the third, the true answer, related to self-knowledge, can be found in the Opus postumum. Opening the section on self-knowledge, Bartosz Żukowski’s paper examines the less- er-known Richard Burthogge’s philosophy of mind. Burthogge was an English physician at the end of the seventeenth century, whose views on the mind were considered highly unusual in his time and therefore remained unappreciated both by his contemporaries and by posterity. Żukowski shows, however, that behind Burthogge’s idiosyncratic language, 8 Introduction the epistemology of an interesting and innovative thinker can be reconstructed, someone who shared some affinities concerning self-knowledge with Leibniz and Kant. In contrast with Burthogge’s idealism, which has been largely ignored by early modern scholarship, that of George Berkeley has received much attention. Peter West takes a look at the classical problem of self-knowledge in Berkeley’s idealism: if ideas in the human mind represent their objects due to their similarity to external objects, and spirits are of a different metaphysical kind than ideas, how is self-knowledge, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • Lev Vygotsky Area of Research
    Lev Vygotsky Area of Research ● Vygotsky's first big research project was in 1925 ● Vygotsky's theories stress the fundamental role of social interaction in the development of cognition Vygotsky, 1978, as he believed strongly that community plays a central role in the process of "making meaning." ● Unlike Piaget's notion that children’s development must necessarily precede their learning, Vygotsky argued, "learning is a necessary and universal aspect of the process of developing culturally organized.” Process of Research ● Started teaching at various institutions ● First big research project was in 1925 with his Psychology of Art ● Pursued a career as a psychologist working with Alexander Luria and Alexei Leontiev ● Began the Vygotskian approach to psychology with Alexander Luria and Alexei Leontiev ● His works were revealed after the Cold War ended ● Wrote several articles and books on the subject of his theories and psychology -Thought and Language(1934) ● His research in how children solve their problems that surpassed their level of development led Vygotsky to create the Zone of Proximal Development theory Age of Children Researched ● Crisis of the newborn. ● Infancy (two months to one year). ● Crisis at age one. ● Early childhood (one to three years). ● Crisis at age three. ● Preschool age (three to seven years). ● Crisis at age seven. ● School age (eight to twelve years). ● Crisis at age thirteen. ● Age of puberty (fourteen to eighteen years). ● Crisis at age seventeen. Research Findings ● Private speech: Where children speak themselves to plan or guide their own behavior this is most common among pre schoolers. ● Sociocultural (ZPD) Zone of proximal development Vygotsky believed For example a child accomplishes a task he/she cannot do alone by a more skilled person.
    [Show full text]
  • How Much of a Loss Is the Loss of Self? Undersanding
    This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and education use, including for instruction at the authors institution and sharing with colleagues. Other uses, including reproduction and distribution, or selling or licensing copies, or posting to personal, institutional or third party websites are prohibited. In most cases authors are permitted to post their version of the article (e.g. in Word or Tex form) to their personal website or institutional repository. Authors requiring further information regarding Elsevier’s archiving and manuscript policies are encouraged to visit: http://www.elsevier.com/copyright Author's personal copy New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 98–105 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect New Ideas in Psychology journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/newideapsych How much of a loss is the loss of self? Understanding Vygotsky from a social therapeutic perspective and vice versaq Lois Holzman* East Side Institute for Group and Short Term Psychotherapy, 920 Broadway, New York NY 10010, United States abstract Keywords: Using the example of Fred Newman’s social therapy, a methodology that works with the Marx human capability of growing as social units, the contemporary self is explored as an Vygotsky impediment to human development and learning. Following Karl Marx in political Wittgenstein philosophy and Lev Vygotsky in child psychology, it is the group/the collective/the mass Self that engages in developmental activity. In losing the self, we gain the opportunity to create Psychotherapy Social therapy collectivity and in that process come to sense the social-relational-collective quality of creativity and development.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transition from Studying Philosophy to Doing Philosophy
    Teaching Philosophy 34:3, September 2011 241 The Transition from Studying Philosophy to Doing Philosophy JOHN RUDISILL The College of Wooster Abstract: In this paper I articulate a minimal conception of the idea of doing philosophy that informs a curriculum and pedagogy for producing students who are capable of engaging in philosophical activity and not just competent with a specific domain of knowledge. The paper then relates, by way of back- ground, the departmental assessment practices that have played a vital role in the development of my department’s current curriculum and in particular in the design of a junior-year seminar in philosophical research required of all majors. After a brief survey of the learning theory literature that has informed its design, I share the content of this junior-year seminar. In the paper’s conclusion I provide some initial data that indicates our approach to curriculum and pedagogy has had a positive impact on student achievement with respect to reaching the learning goals associated with “doing” as opposed to “merely studying” philosophy. 1. Introduction Capstone projects are common among liberal arts colleges and fre- quently carry an expectation that the final product demonstrates the student’s achievement of becoming a budding biologist, historian, sociologist, philosopher and so on. Even without a formal capstone requirement, I would hope that my philosophy students could—as they finish their undergraduate studies—demonstrate such an achievement. This is because the full set of benefits made available by an education in philosophy includes but extends well beyond knowledge of the history of philosophy and mastery of a philosophical lexicon.
    [Show full text]
  • The Points of Viewing Theory for Engaged Learning with Digital Media
    The Points of Viewing Theory for Engaged Learning with Digital Media Ricki Goldman New York University John Black Columbia University John W. Maxwell Simon Fraser University Jan J. L. Plass New York University Mark J. Keitges University of Illinois, Urbana Champaign - 1 - Introduction Theories are dangerous things. All the same we must risk making one this afternoon since we are going to discuss modern tendencies. Directly we speak of tendencies or movements we commit to, the belief that there is some force, influence, outer pressure that is strong enough to stamp itself upon a whole group of different writers so that all their writing has a certain common likeness. — Virginia Woolff, The Leaning Tower, lecture delivered to the Workers' Educational Association, Brighton (May 1940). With full acknowledgement of the warning from the 1940 lecture by Virginia Woolf, this chapter begins by presenting a theory of mind, knowing only too well, that “a whole group of different” learning theorists cannot find adequate coverage under one umbrella. Nor should they. However, there is a movement occurring, a form of social activism created by the affordances of social media, an infrastructure that was built incrementally during two to three decades of hard scholarly research that brought us to this historic time and place. To honor the convergence of theories and technologies, this paper proposes the Points of Viewing Theory to provide researchers, teachers, and the public with an opportunity to discuss and perhaps change the epistemology of education from its formal structures to more do-it-yourself learning environments that dig deeper and better into content knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Developmental Psychology: Incorporating Piaget's and Vygotsky's Theories in Classrooms
    Journal of Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives in Education Vol. 1, No. 1 (May 2008) 59 - 67 Developmental Psychology: Incorporating Piaget’s and Vygotsky’s Theories in Classrooms Barbara Blake and Tambra Pope In today’s society, there is disagreement of their students’ cognitive development, which will among researchers and educators as to the role of lead to the needs of the whole child being satisfied. developmental psychology and its application in the Cognitive psychology is a branch of psychology elementary classrooms. It is widely accepted in the that focuses on studies mental processes, which educational field that children must go through the include how people think, perceive, remember, and process of learning to think and thinking to learn. learn. Its core focus is on how people acquire, Therefore, teachers, who can incorporate the process, and store information. It is advantageous theories of Piaget and Vygotsky into their teaching for teachers to understand cognitive psychology strategies, will be better able to increase student because it can help them improve their teaching and achievement. student learning. Teachers become more cognizant Developmental Psychology, the study of to how people process, learn, and remember age-related changes in behavior, examines the information, which helps them plan more effective psychological processes of development, which lessons and create positive learning environments means it describes the sequence of biological, for their students. By using appropriate cognitive, and socio-emotional changes that humans developmental instructional techniques, teachers undergo as they grow older. It describes the growth have been able to increase the test scores of children of humans, which consists of physical, emotional, in public schools (Black & Green, 2005).
    [Show full text]
  • The Historic Importance of LS Vygotsky's “The Psychology of Art
    International Journal of Psychological Research ISSN: 2011-2084 [email protected] Universidad de San Buenaventura Colombia Khinkanina, Alla The Historic Importance of L. S. Vygotsky’s “The Psychology of Art” and Some Problems of Modern Psychological and Pedagogical Field International Journal of Psychological Research, vol. 7, núm. 2, 2014, pp. 85-91 Universidad de San Buenaventura Medellín, Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=299032684009 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative INT.J.PSYCHOL.RES. 2014; 7 (2): 85-91 The Historic Importance of L. S. Vygotsky’s “The Psychology of Art” and Some Problems of Modern Psychological and Pedagogical Field La importancia histórica de L. S. Vygotsky: “La Psicología del arte” y algunos problemas de la Psicología y Pedagogía Moderna. R e f l e c t i o n a Alla Khinkanina * a Department of Psychology, Volga State University of Technology, Yoshkar-Ola, Russia. Article History ARTICLE INFO Received: 20-05-2014 Revised: 10-08-2014 Accepted: 04-09-2014 ABSTRACT Key words: The article deals with the importance of L. S. Vygotsky‟s paper “The Psychology Cultural-historical of Art” in the present time. The shortage of ideal values is the reality of this time that in a psychology, game, certain way arises the issues of children and young people‟s cultural evolution. Cultural psychological- and historic theory of L.
    [Show full text]
  • Let's Pretend
    Solving the Education Crisis in America: A Special Report LET’S PRETEND by Fred Newman, Ph.D. and Lenora Fulani, Ph.D. January 2011 LET’S PRETEND 1. Here is an idea for solving the education crisis in America. What if all the kids currently failing in school pretended to be good learners? What if all the adults – teachers, principals, administrators, parents – played along and pretended that the kids were school achievers, heading for college? What if this national “ensemble” pretended this was the case day after day, classroom after classroom, school district after school district? We believe that if such a national “performance” were created, the education crisis in America would be over. Children, having developed the capacity to pretend to be who Learning takes they are not, i.e., good learners, also develop the capacity to become the thing they are pretending to be. And, thus, if we could all together assist poor and minority kids in development, pretending that they are classroom achievers, they could choose to become that. and if kids are Is this idea as ridiculous as it might seem at first glance? At the risk of seeming ridiculous, our answer is an emphatic “no.” Because the most innovative researchers and practitioners underdeveloped, have come to discover that pretending, or “creatively imitating,” or performing in social contexts, is how human development is produced.1 Harnessing the uniquely human they do not capacity to perform someone or something we are not, underachieving kids can pretend their way to growth. We have seen the repeated success of this approach – not only in our become after-school programs at the All Stars Project, but also (perhaps unknowingly) in school settings now applauded as the most successful interventions into the “achievement gap” learners.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 12-15-2015 12:00 AM Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics Michael H. Walschots The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Corey Dyck The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Walschots, Michael H., "Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3383. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3383 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MORAL SENSE THEORY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF KANT’S ETHICS (Thesis format: Monograph) by Michael H. Walschots Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Abstract This dissertation investigates a number of ways in which an eighteenth century British philosophical movement known as “moral sense theory” influenced the development of German philosopher Immanuel Kant’s (1724-1804) moral theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham E-Theses
    Durham E-Theses Theodicy and evolution: aspects of theology from Pierre Bayle to J.S. Mill Loades, Ann Lomas How to cite: Loades, Ann Lomas (1975) Theodicy and evolution: aspects of theology from Pierre Bayle to J.S. Mill, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/8091/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk The copyright of this thesis rests with the author. No quotation from it should be published without his prior written consent and information derived from it should be acknowledged. THEODICY AND EVOUJriON: ASPECTS OF THEOJXXSy FROM PIERRE BAYIE TO J .S . MILL By Atiu Ixsmas Loades, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Submitted in Fullilaient of the Reqtiiremeats for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy Durhara University, 1975 Table of Contenta Page Summaxy ii Preface iii Introduotion 1 Section I % Bayle to Kant A Bayle 6 B Leibniz .
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Realism/Moral Realism Ethical Propositions That Refer to Objective Features May Be True If They Are Free of Subjectivis
    Metaethics: Cognitivism Metaethics: What is morality, or “right”? Normative (prescriptive) ethics: How should people act? Descriptive ethics: What do people think is right? Applied ethics: Putting moral ideas into practice Thin moral concepts Thick moral concepts more general: good, bad, right, and wrong more specic: courageous, inequitable, just, or dishonest Centralism- thin concepts are antecedent to the thick ones Non-centralism- thick concepts are a sucient starting point for understanding thin ones because thin and thick concepts are equal. Normativity is a non-excisable aspect of language and there is no way of analyzing thick moral concepts into a purely descriptive element attached to a thin moral evaluation, thus undermining any fundamental division between facts and norms. Cognitivism ethical propositions are truth-apt (can be true or false), unlike questions or commands Ethical subjectivism/moral anti-realism Ethical realism/moral realism True ethical propositions are a function of subjective features Ethical propositions that refer to objective features may be true if they are free of subjectivism Moral relativism Moral universalism/ Robust and Minimal Robust moral objectivism/ nobody is objectively right or wrong universal morality 1. Semantic thesis: moral predicates 3. Metaphysical thesis: the facts in regards to diagreements about are to refer to moral properties so and properties of #1 are robust-- moral questions a system of ethics, or a universal ethic, moral statements represent moral their metaphysical status is not applies universally to "all" facts, and express propositions that relevantly dierent from ordinary are true or false non-moral facts and properties Cultural relativism not all forms of moral universalism 2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral Philosophy of Francis Hutcheson
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. The Moral Philosophy of Francis Hutcheson by John D. Bishop Ph.D. University of Edinburgh 1979 Contents Page 1. Introduction 1 i. Hutcheson's Philosophical Writings 4 ii. Locke's Influence 7 2. Theory of Human Nature i. Sensation 9 ii. Affections a. Internal Sensations 14 b. Passions 21 c. Desires 23 d. Desire and Motivation 32 e. Free-will 45 iii. Reason 51 3. The Moral Sense i. Introduction 53 ii. Intuitionist Aspects a. Analogy With the External Senses 54 b. Relationship Between Goodness & Benevolence 61 c. Whose Moral Sense? 67 d. Moral Error 71 iii. Justification of Approval 78 iv. Moral Sense and Pleasure and Pain 88 v. Moral Sense and Motivation 99 vi. S mnmary 102 Page 4. Benevolence i. First Version 105 ii.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 of Law, Virtue and Justice – an Introduction
    1 Of Law, Virtue and Justice – An Introduction AMALIA AMAYA AND HO HOCK LAI I. THE REVIVAL OF VIRTUE N THE LAST decades, there has been a blossoming of virtue-based approaches to a number of philosophical problems. Virtue theory has a I prominent place in both contemporary ethics and epistemology. A. Virtue Ethics Virtue ethics has its origins in Classical Greece and it was the dominant approach in western moral philosophy until the Enlightenment. During the nineteenth cen- tury and the first half of the twentieth century, virtue theory faded from the land- scape of moral philosophy, and the discussion on ethics centered around two traditions, namely, deontology and utilitarianism. Virtue ethics re-emerged in the late 1950s, with Elizabeth Anscombe’s important article ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’, and has established itself as a major approach in normative ethics.1 The revival of virtue ethics was motivated by an increasing dissatisfaction with deontology and utilitarianism. Proponents of virtue theories objected that these theories sidestepped or ignored a number of topics that any adequate moral phi- losophy should address, such as motives, moral character, moral education, the moral significance of friendship, family relations, and community bonds, ques- tions about what sort of person one should be, the role of emotions in our moral life, and a concern with happiness and flourishing.2 There is a wide variety of views that fall under the heading of virtue ethics, as critics have objected to differ- ent aspects of modern ethical theory and have developed a virtue-based approach 1 Anscombe (1958), reprinted in Crisp and Slote (1997).
    [Show full text]