Sub Specie Aeternitatis Somogy Varga

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sub Specie Aeternitatis Somogy Varga Sub Specie Aeternitatis An Actualization of Wittgenstein on Ethics and Aesthetics Somogy Varga abstract This article will present an interpretation of Wittgenstein’s under­ standing of the relationship between ethics and aesthetics. In extension, it will inform recent discussions regarding a special kind of nonsensicality, which forms a central part of ethical and aesthetical expressions. Instead of identity between ethics and aesthetics, we should understand the relationship in terms of interdependence. Both attitudes provide a view sub specie aeternitatis and thus permit a view of the world as a whole. Employing the vocabulary of Charles Taylor and Harry Frankfurt, it must be remembered that rather than a neutral view from nowhere, such wholeness arises out of strong evaluations that are made against the backdrop of a constitutive framework of intelligibility. At this point, the epistemic gain of actualizing Wittgenstein will reveal itself: it will put us in a position where it is possible to differentiate between ethi­ cal and aesthetical forms of identification that Taylor and Frankfurt neglect. However, in order to actualize Wittgenstein’s ideas, it is necessary to argue that Tractatus should not be understood in a Kantian fashion as suggested by Tilghman for instance. keywords Wittgenstein, sub specie aeternitatis, ethics, aesthetics, identifi­ cation In his famous sentence, “Ethics and Aesthetics are one and the same,”1 Wittgenstein emphasizes the intrinsic connection between two fields of study, to which he was particularly devoted. He points to his profound fascination of aesthetical questions: “I may find scientific questions in- teresting, but they never really grip me. Only conceptual and aesthetical questions do that.”2 On the other hand, although the reception of his early work was regarded as a foundation for logical positivism,3 Wittgen- stein has given ethics as a central theme of the treatise in diary record- ings and letters written parallel to the treatise.4 In a letter to the editor of Der Brenner, Ludwig von Ficker, Wittgenstein notes: My work consists of two parts: the one presented here plus all that I have not written. And it is precisely this second part that is the important one. My book draws limits to the sphere of the ethical from the inside as it were, and I am convinced that this is the ONLY rigorous way of drawing those limits.5 Other sources, such as Paul Engelmann, confirm that Wittgenstein em- phasized the ethical dimension of his book and considered this its fun- damental point.6 The notion of sub specie aeternitatis is central to under- standing his struggle to identify something he could classify as ethically The Nordic Journal of Aesthetics No. 35 (2008), pp. 35–50 Somogy Varga good. In Tractatus he says, “[t]o view the world sub specie aeternitatis is to view it as a whole – a limited whole.”7 In a later remark from the Notebooks dealing with this subject, Wittgenstein emphasizes the ethical importance: “… the good life is the world seen sub specie aeternitatis.”8 In Tractatus, ethics and aesthetics – these two apparently central con- cerns in Wittgenstein’s thought – are brought together in a rather short bracketed remark: It is clear that ethics cannot be put into words. Ethics is transcendental. (Ethics and Aesthetics are one and the same.)9 Even though Wittgenstein emphasized aesthetics and ethics, it seems that his thoughts on these subjects received comparatively modest at- tention in subsequent Wittgenstein research. To a certain degree this has to do with the fact that Wittgenstein’s remarks about this subject are ex- ceedingly brief, fragmented and sometimes enigmatic. This also makes any attempt at extracting a theory of aesthetics or ethics from these spor- adic remarks rather challenging and perhaps even problematic. Addi- tionally, the assumption of a faultless unified aesthetics or ethics seems problematic and in many ways outdated; so why the inconvenience of engaging in this problematic subject? The motivation for working with these considerations lies in the potential for informing more recent dis- cussions. This is why the aim of this article will be to shed light on his views regarding the unity of ethics and aesthetics and to clarify the role of aesthetics in an ethical orientation. In the initial presentation I will examine the possibility of talking about ethics and aesthetics within Tractatus; and proceed by elucidating the posited oneness of ethics, aesthetics and the common perspective of the whole (sub specie aeternitatis) that this provides us with (I).10 Rather than emphasizing oneness, I will elaborate on internal differences of per- spectives in the second part, which makes clear the relationship between ethics and aesthetics and the ethical role of aesthetics (II). In conclusion, I will spell out the genuine merits and the actuality of Wittgenstein’s ac- count. I will attempt to show that Wittgenstein’s account does not inscribe itself in the Kantian or Nietzschean discourse, but establishes a middle path between these two views (III). The elucidation of this matter will entail going beyond the limits of Tractatus and take into consideration additional sources such as the Notebooks (1914–1916) and the more long-winded thoughts from ‘Lecture on Aesthetics’, ‘Lecture on Ethics’ and On Certainty.11 36 Sub Specie Aeternitatis: An Actualization of Wittgenstein on Ethics and Aesthetics I. The importance of nonsense At first sight it may seem somewhat odd to discuss these subjects, es- pecially with the opening remarks of the Tractatus in mind. Wittgen- stein states that the whole argument of the book could be summed up as follows: “What can be said at all can be said clearly; and whereof one cannot speak thereof one must be silent.”12 Since ethical and aesthetical statements are not logically connected to facts in the world they clearly belong to these spheres of silence. So how can Wittgenstein emphasize the ethical impetus of his work? After all, as Russell notes, “Mr Wittgen- stein manages to say a good deal about what cannot be said.”13 What sense does it make to clarify their relationship when they exceed the limits of propositional language such that nothing can be said about them? There is a tradition for what one could call the therapeutic interpreta- tion of what Wittgenstein calls nonsense. There is the resolute way of do- ing this (defended by C. Diamond and J. Conant),14 which takes nonsense to mean nothing but plain nonsense, but one that engages us – one that shows us the limits of sense and cures us from our need for metaphys- ics.15 Also, in P. M. S. Hacker’s far less radical and in many ways different interpretation, we find the idea of nonsense as something with a thera- peutic potential.16 What I am suggesting is also a therapeutic reading, but a reading that approaches the issue differently than these authors. I suggest that we understand the issue of nonsense through his late work, especially On Certainty. Although there are major differences between Wittgenstein’s early and later thoughts, I think there are good reasons for taking up such an approach. Firstly, there are interesting parallels be- tween the way in which he addresses the scaffolding of our thoughts in On Certainty and the idea of the scaffolding of the world found in Tractatus 6.124. In On Certainty, this scaffolding is the non-propositional basis of thought, which – construed as propositions – is deemed to be nonsensi- cal. Such scaffolding does not have a contrast and is falsifiable.17 Also, as G. E. Moore explained, we cannot imagine it not being true, wherefore it can be said to have “no sense.”18 In this regard, Tractarian sentences elu- cidate the conditions of sense, describe the scaffolding of the world and must therefore remain nonsensical. Writing, thinking or understanding propositions about this basic level of being must always already presup- pose the scaffolding, the fundamental framework of the world, within which observations regarding entities can intelligibly be stated, which it aims to explain. It is on such grounds that Wittgenstein maintains that ethics and aesthetics have been misunderstood throughout the history of western 37 Somogy Varga philosophical thought.19 The pictorial form of language depicts and presents the structure of the world in its form, representing the con- figuration of things by being connected to the thing through “feelers.”20 This is exactly what ethical and aesthetical value statements lack; the absence of referents in the world makes them stand outside the realm of what I might call propositionality.21 They cannot generate truth or false- hood, since truth or falsehood would only emerge between the world and its picture.22 So for Wittgenstein, the philosophical misapprehen- sion of ethics and aesthetics derives from such a referentiality-mistake. The construction of meaning through referentiality is not applicable to these realms, since they lie outside of the space of referential language. This begs a somewhat provocative question: why then engage in deal- ing ethical and aesthetical stands, which Wittgenstein clearly does? Here, I think the key term is again nonsense. Nonsense is, as we have seen, not necessarily a pejorative term. As Wittgenstein says in Culture and Value, “… don’t for heaven’s sake, be afraid of talking nonsense! But you must pay attention to your nonsense.”23 Curiously, for Wittgenstein, men have attempted an intentional transgression of linguistic boundaries to reflect on the meaning of life and values. This is an “… absolutely hopeless …” attempt, “… running against the walls of our cage …”24 This attempt is a document of a tendency in the human mind: “My whole tendency and I believe the tendency of all men who ever tried to write or talk Ethics or Religion was to turn against the boundaries of language.”25 It is a mani- festation of a tendency, which Wittgenstein “… personally cannot help respecting …”26 as an essential part of being human.
Recommended publications
  • Rethinking Fideism Through the Lens of Wittgenstein's Engineering Outlook
    University of Dayton eCommons Religious Studies Faculty Publications Department of Religious Studies 2012 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad Kallenberg University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub Part of the Catholic Studies Commons, Christianity Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other Religion Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons eCommons Citation Kallenberg, Brad, "Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook" (2012). Religious Studies Faculty Publications. 82. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub/82 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Religious Studies at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Note: This is the accepted manuscript for the following article: Kallenberg, Brad J. “Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71, no. 1 (2012): 55-73. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11153-011-9327-0 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad J. Kallenberg University of Dayton, 2011 In an otherwise superbly edited compilation of student notes from Wittgenstein’s 1939 Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cora Diamond makes an false step that reveals to us our own tendencies to misread Wittgenstein. The student notes she collated attributed the following remark to a student named Watson: “The point is that these [data] tables do not by themselves determine that one builds the bridge in this way: only the tables together with certain scientific theory determine that.”1 But Diamond thinks this a mistake, presuming instead to change the manuscript and put these words into the mouth of Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza's Ethics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Eternity and Immortality in Spinoza’s Ethics STEVEN NADLER I Descartes famously prided himself on the felicitous consequences of his philoso- phy for religion. In particular, he believed that by so separating the mind from the corruptible body, his radical substance dualism offered the best possible defense of and explanation for the immortality of the soul. “Our natural knowledge tells us that the mind is distinct from the body, and that it is a substance...And this entitles us to conclude that the mind, insofar as it can be known by natural phi- losophy, is immortal.”1 Though he cannot with certainty rule out the possibility that God has miraculously endowed the soul with “such a nature that its duration will come to an end simultaneously with the end of the body,” nonetheless, because the soul (unlike the human body, which is merely a collection of material parts) is a substance in its own right, and is not subject to the kind of decomposition to which the body is subject, it is by its nature immortal. When the body dies, the soul—which was only temporarily united with it—is to enjoy a separate existence. By contrast, Spinoza’s views on the immortality of the soul—like his views on many issues—are, at least in the eyes of most readers, notoriously difficult to fathom. One prominent scholar, in what seems to be a cry of frustration after having wrestled with the relevant propositions in Part Five of Ethics,claims that this part of the work is an “unmitigated and seemingly unmotivated disaster..
    [Show full text]
  • A REDUCTIVE READING of the TRACTATUS Interpretation of the Book Being About How to Defeat Skepticism
    2015 Umeå University, Department of Historical, Philosophical and Religious Studies Stefan Karlsson Supervisor: Andreas Stokke Examinor: Peter Melander Level: Bachelor’s thesis A REDUCTIVE READING OF THE TRACTATUS Interpretation of the book being about how to defeat skepticism. Content Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 4 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................. 5 Contents .................................................................................................................................................. 6 Traditional readings ................................................................................................................................. 7 Meta-physical interpretations ............................................................................................................. 7 Traditional readings of the nonsense concept in the Tractatus ......................................................... 8 The ineffable truth interpretation ................................................................................................... 8 What can be said and what can be shown ...................................................................................... 9 Modern readings ..................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein in Exile
    Wittgenstein in Exile “My thoughts are one hundred per cent Hebraic.” -Wittgenstein to Drury, 19491 Wittgenstein was born in 1889 into one of the richest families in Central Europe. He lived and learned at home, in Vienna, until 1903, when he was 14. We have no record of his thoughts about the turn of the last century, but it is unlikely that it seemed very significant to him. The Viennese of the time had little inclination to consider the possibilities of change, and the over-ripe era in which Wittgenstein grew up did not really end until Austria-Hungary’s defeat, in World War I, and subsequent dismantling. But the family in which Wittgenstein grew up apparently felt that European culture had already come to an end in the 1840’s. And Wittgenstein himself felt he belonged to an era that had vanished with the death of the composer Robert Schumann (1810-1856).2 Somewhere in the middle of the Nineteenth Century there was an important change into the contemporary era, of which Wittgenstein did not feel a part. Wittgenstein’s understanding of history, and his consequent self-understanding in relation to his times, was deeply influenced by Oswald Spengler, who in 1918 published The Decline of the West [Der Untergang des Abenlandes]. This book, expanded to a second volume in 1922, and revised in 1923, became a best-seller in post-war Europe. Wittgenstein made numerous references to it in 1930-1931, and acknowledged Spengler as one of his ten noteworthy influences.3 According to Spengler, cultures grow, flower, and deteriorate naturally, according to their own internal form, much as a human being does.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 1994 Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson T. Potter Jr. University of Nebraska - Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal History Commons Potter, Nelson T. Jr., "Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics" (1994). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 15. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Potter in Jarbuch für Recht und Ethik (1994) 2. Copyright 1994, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg. Used by permission. Kant on Obligation and Motivation in Law and Ethics Nelson Potter I. There is a passage in Immanuel Kant's general introduction to both parts of Die Metaphysik der Sitten that deserves more attention than it has received. I plan to build the present paper around the implil:ations of this passage: In all lawgiving (Gesetzgebung) (whether it prescribes for internal or external actions, and whether it prescribes them a priori by reason alone or by the choice of another) there are two elements: first, a law, which represents an action that is to be done as objectively necessary, that is, which makes the action a duty; and second, an incentive, which connects a ground for determining choice to this action subjectively with the representation of the law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Shortcomings of a Concept Inertia and Conatus in the Philosophy of Spinoza
    http://dx.doi.org/10.18778/8142-286-4.36 Alexandre Rouette Université du Québec à Trois-Rivières, Canada THE SHORTCOMINGS OF A CONCEPT INERTIA AND CONATUS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA n the third part of the Ethics, Spinoza express the desire to talk about “human actions and appetites just as if it were a question of lines, planes, and bodies” (E3, Appendix).1 With this sentence, it seems clear that Spinoza sides with Hobbes and Descartes and that he wants to con- struct a mechanistic theory of the affects. In the same part of the Ethics, Spinoza also introduces the concept of conatus: “Each thing, as far as it can by its own power, strives to persevere in its being” (E3P6), Spinoza says. One will immedi- ately understand this concept of conatus as the core concept of his mechanistic theory of the affects, the concept without which this mechanistic account of the affects would be impossible. However, in the second part of the Ethics, there is another concept that could have accomplished that same goal, namely, the principle of inertia. In the words of Spinoza, “A body which moves or is at rest must be determined to motion or rest by another body, which has also been determined to motion or rest by another, and that again by another, and so on, to infinity” (E2L3). Inter- estingly enough, in the philosophy of Hobbes, the concept of endeavour/conatus is much nearer to the Spinozistic principle of inertia in its meaning than it is to the Spinozistic version of the conatus.
    [Show full text]
  • SPINOZA's ETHICS: FREEDOM and DETERMINISM by Alfredo Lucero
    SPINOZA’S ETHICS: FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM by Alfredo Lucero-Montaño 1. What remains alive of a philosopher's thought are the realities that concern him, the problems that he addresses, as well as the questions that he poses. The breath and depth of a philosopher's thought is what continues to excite and incite today. However, his answers are limited to his time and circumstances, and these are subject to the historical evolution of thought, yet his principal commitments are based on the problems and questions with which he is concerned. And this is what resounds of a philosopher's thought, which we can theoretically and practically adopt and adapt. Spinoza is immersed in a time of reforms, and he is a revolutionary and a reformer himself. The reforming trend in modern philosophy is expressed in an eminent way by Descartes' philosophy. Descartes, the great restorer of science and metaphysics, had left unfinished the task of a new foundation of ethics. Spinoza was thus faced with this enterprise. But he couldn't carry it out without the conviction of the importance of the ethical problems or that ethics is involved in a fundamental aspect of existence: the moral destiny of man. Spinoza's Ethics[1] is based on a theory of man or, more precisely, on an ontology of man. Ethics is, for him, ontology. He does not approach the problems of morality — the nature of good and evil, why and wherefore of human life — if it is not on the basis of a conception of man's being-in-itself, to wit, that the moral existence of man can only be explained by its own condition.
    [Show full text]
  • Rational Ethics
    Chapter 5 Rational Ethics Bertrand Meyer Abstract An effort, originating from an invited talk on “ethics and computers”, to re-found ethics on the rules of logical reasoning, from three concrete principles (Goodness, Truth, Fairness) and two meta-principles (Restraint and Importance). 5.1 Introduction In the attempt to address the assigned theme for this contribution, ethics and computers, it became clear that while the second term is well defined the first is not. What kind of behavior qualifies as ethical? The established works on ethics, from Aristotle to Spinoza, Kant and modern moral philosophers, lack precise definitions of the concepts they discuss. They bring to mind C.P. Snow’s Two Cultures thesis that instead of berating scientists for not reading Dickens we might ask writers and philosophers to explain the second law of thermodynamics. Of the two cultures, the humanities indeed have as much to learn from science and technology as the other way around. The latter’s advantage comes from three fundamental characteristics of scientific discussions. First, they devote great care to defining precisely the concepts under consideration. Second, to draw conclusions from principles, they use simple and firmly grounded laws of reasoning, rather than appeals to emotion or authority. Third, all their propositions are subject to refuta- tion through objective criteria (of which the most practical is that a single counter- example suffices to refute a proposition of the universally quantified kind, such as “all French women are red-haired”). Ethics is one of the parts of the humanities that has the most to gain from the scientific method of reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on China and Christianity: the Reformation of Religion and European Ethics Through Converting China to Christianity
    Bard College Bard Digital Commons Senior Projects Spring 2016 Bard Undergraduate Senior Projects Spring 2016 Leibniz on China and Christianity: The Reformation of Religion and European Ethics through Converting China to Christianity Ela Megan Kaplan Bard College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bard.edu/senproj_s2016 Part of the European History Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Kaplan, Ela Megan, "Leibniz on China and Christianity: The Reformation of Religion and European Ethics through Converting China to Christianity" (2016). Senior Projects Spring 2016. 279. https://digitalcommons.bard.edu/senproj_s2016/279 This Open Access work is protected by copyright and/or related rights. It has been provided to you by Bard College's Stevenson Library with permission from the rights-holder(s). You are free to use this work in any way that is permitted by the copyright and related rights. For other uses you need to obtain permission from the rights- holder(s) directly, unless additional rights are indicated by a Creative Commons license in the record and/or on the work itself. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Leibniz on China and Christianity: The Reformation of Religion and European Ethics through Converting China to Christianity Senior Project submitted to The Division of Social Studies Of Bard College by Ela Megan Kaplan Annandale-on-Hudson, New York May 2016 5 Acknowledgements I would like to thank my mother, father and omniscient advisor for tolerating me for the duration of my senior project.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on the Nature of British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Philosophy J Wittgenstein and His Times
    @Basil Blackwdl Publisher Limitcd 1982 Contents Fiesr published 1982 Basil BlackwelJ Publisher Limited 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 IJF, England All rights rcserved. No part ofthis publicarion may bc reproduccd, stored in a retricval system, or trammitted. in an y form or hy any means. clcctronic, mcchanicaJ, photocopying. recording or otherwisc. withollt the prior permission of Basil Blackwell Publisher Limited. Editor's Preface v Anthony Kenny Wittgenstein on the Nature of British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Philosophy J Wittgenstein and his times. Brian McGuinness Freud and Wittgenstein 27 I. Wittgenstein, Ludwig I. McGuinness, Brian J. C. NYlri Wittgenstein's Later Work in '92 B)376.W)64 reiation co Conservatism 44 ISBN 0-63'-11161-1 Rush Rhees Wittgenstein on Language and Ritual 69 G. H von Wright Wittgenstein in relation to his Times 108 Index 121 Printe<! in Great Britain at Thc Blackwell Press Limitcd, Guildford, Landon, Oxford, Worcester. LATER WORK IN RELATION 1'0 CONSERVATISM 45 since Wittgenstein 's position in respect to the body ofconserva­ Wittgenstein 's Later Work in relation tive literature cannot be satisfactorily dctcrmined in the absence to Conservatism * ofa thorough analysis ofhis unpublished manuscripts. I Still, the interpretation here presented, cven ifmerely an approximation, C. Nyiri seems to me to constitute a necessary step towards a more J. complere pieture of Wittgenstcin's philosophy. Wittgenstein's later philosophy emerged at a time when conservatism - in tbe form of neo-conservatism - was one of the dominant spiritual currents in Germany and Austria; and Wittgenstein received decisive impulses both from authors who deeply influenced this The well-kno"vn fact that in Wittgenstein's later philosophy current and trom representatives ofthe I1ew conservatism itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Morality: a Kantian Perspective
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1987 Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective George P. Fletcher Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation George P. Fletcher, Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective, 87 COLUM. L. REV. 533 (1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1071 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW AND MORALITY: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE George P. Fletcher* The relationship between law and morality has emerged as the cen- tral question in the jurisprudential reflection of our time. Those who call themselves positivists hold with H.L.A. Hart' that calling a statute or a judicial decision "law" need not carry any implications about the morality of that statute or decision.2 Valid laws might be immoral or unjust. Those who resist this reduction of law to valid enactments sometimes argue, with Lon Fuller, that moral acceptability is a neces- sary condition for holding that a statute is law; 3 or, with Ronald Dworkin, that moral principles supplement valid enactments as compo- 4 nents of the law. Whether the positivists or their "moralist" opponents are right about the nature of law, all seem to agree about the nature of morality. We have to distinguish, it is commonly said, between conventional and critical morality.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Vienna Our Aim Is, by Academic Standards, a Radical One : to Use Each of Our Four Topics As a Mirror in Which to Reflect and to Study All the Others
    TOUCHSTONE Gustav Klimt, from Ver Sacrum Wittgenstein' s VIENNA Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin TOUCHSTONE A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster Copyright ® 1973 by Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin All rights reserved including the right of reproduction in whole or in part in any form A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster A Division of Gulf & Western Corporation Simon & Schuster Building Rockefeller Center 1230 Avenue of the Americas New York, N.Y. 10020 TOUCHSTONE and colophon are trademarks of Simon & Schuster ISBN o-671-2136()-1 ISBN o-671-21725-9Pbk. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 72-83932 Designed by Eve Metz Manufactured in the United States of America 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 The publishers wish to thank the following for permission to repro­ duce photographs: Bettmann Archives, Art Forum, du magazine, and the National Library of Austria. For permission to reproduce a portion of Arnold SchOnberg's Verklarte Nacht, our thanks to As­ sociated Music Publishers, Inc., New York, N.Y., copyright by Bel­ mont Music, Los Angeles, California. Contents PREFACE 9 1. Introduction: PROBLEMS AND METHODS 13 2. Habsburg Vienna: CITY OF PARADOXES 33 The Ambiguity of Viennese Life The Habsburg Hausmacht: Francis I The Cilli Affair Francis Joseph The Character of the Viennese Bourgeoisie The Home and Family Life-The Role of the Press­ The Position of Women-The Failure of Liberalism The Conditions of Working-Class Life : The Housing Problem Viktor Adler and Austrian Social Democracy Karl Lueger and the Christian Social Party Georg von Schonerer and the German Nationalist Party Theodor Herzl and Zionism The Redl Affair Arthur Schnitzler's Literary Diagnosis of the Viennese Malaise Suicide inVienna 3.
    [Show full text]