Cronbach & Meehl (1955)
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
MORALITY in IRAN 1 in Press, Evolution and Human Behavior
MORALITY IN IRAN 1 In press, Evolution and Human Behavior https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2020.07.014 Foundations of Morality in Iran Mohammad Atari1, Jesse Graham2, Morteza Dehghani1,3 1Department of Psychology, University of Southern California 2Department of Management, David Eccles School of Business, University of Utah 3Department of Computer Science, University of Southern California Author Note Correspondence regarding this article should be addressed to Mohammad Atari, [email protected], 362 S. McClintock Ave, Los Angeles, CA 90089-161 MORALITY IN IRAN 2 Abstract Most moral psychology research has been conducted in Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, and Democratic (WEIRD) societies. As such, moral judgment, as a psychological phenomenon, might be known to researchers only by its WEIRD manifestations. Here, we start with evaluating Moral Foundations Theory (MFT) using the Moral Foundations Questionnaire, and follow up by building a bottom-up model of moral values, in Iran, a non-WEIRD, Muslim-majority, understudied cultural setting. In six studies (N = 1,945) we examine the structural validity of the Persian translation of the Moral Foundations Questionnaire, compare moral foundations between Iran and the US, conduct qualitative interviews regarding moral values, expand the nomological network of “Qeirat” as a culture-specific set of moral values, and investigate the pragmatic validity of “Qeirat” in Iranian culture. Our findings suggest an additional moral foundation in Iran, above and beyond the five foundations identified by MFT. Specifically, qualitative studies highlighted the role of “Qeirat” values in Iranian culture, which are comprised of guarding and protectiveness of female kin, romantic partners, broader family, and country. -
Construct Validity in Psychological Tests
CONSTRUCT VALIDITY IN PSYCHOLOGICAL TF.STS - ----L. J. CRONBACH and P. E. MEEID..----- validity seems only to have stirred the muddy waters. Portions of the distinctions we shall discuss are implicit in Jenkins' paper, "Validity for 'What?" { 33), Gulliksen's "Intrinsic Validity" (27), Goo<lenough's dis tinction between tests as "signs" and "samples" (22), Cronbach's sepa· Construct Validity in Psychological Tests ration of "logical" and "empirical" validity ( 11 ), Guilford's "factorial validity" (25), and Mosier's papers on "face validity" and "validity gen eralization" ( 49, 50). Helen Peak ( 52) comes close to an explicit state ment of construct validity as we shall present it. VALIDATION of psychological tests has not yet been adequately concep· Four Types of Validation tua1ized, as the APA Committee on Psychological Tests learned when TI1e categories into which the Recommendations divide validity it undertook (1950-54) to specify what qualities should be investigated studies are: predictive validity, concurrent validity, content validity, and before a test is published. In order to make coherent recommendations constrnct validity. The first two of these may be considered together the Committee found it necessary to distinguish four types of validity, as criterion-oriented validation procedures. established by different types of research and requiring different interpre· TI1e pattern of a criterion-oriented study is familiar. The investigator tation. The chief innovation in the Committee's report was the term is primarily interested in some criterion which he wishes to predict. lie constmct validity.* This idea was first formulated hy a subcommittee administers the test, obtains an independent criterion measure on the {Meehl and R. -
A Nomological Network Analysis of Innovation in Hospitality Education and Industry
UNLV Theses, Dissertations, Professional Papers, and Capstones 12-1-2020 A Nomological Network Analysis of Innovation in Hospitality Education and Industry Robert H. Rippee Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalscholarship.unlv.edu/thesesdissertations Part of the Entrepreneurial and Small Business Operations Commons, Other Education Commons, Science and Mathematics Education Commons, and the Social and Behavioral Sciences Commons Repository Citation Rippee, Robert H., "A Nomological Network Analysis of Innovation in Hospitality Education and Industry" (2020). UNLV Theses, Dissertations, Professional Papers, and Capstones. 4076. https://digitalscholarship.unlv.edu/thesesdissertations/4076 This Dissertation is protected by copyright and/or related rights. It has been brought to you by Digital Scholarship@UNLV with permission from the rights-holder(s). You are free to use this Dissertation in any way that is permitted by the copyright and related rights legislation that applies to your use. For other uses you need to obtain permission from the rights-holder(s) directly, unless additional rights are indicated by a Creative Commons license in the record and/or on the work itself. This Dissertation has been accepted for inclusion in UNLV Theses, Dissertations, Professional Papers, and Capstones by an authorized administrator of Digital Scholarship@UNLV. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A NOMOLOGICAL NETWORK ANALYSIS OF INNOVATION IN HOSPITALITY EDUCATION AND INDUSTRY By Robert Rippee Bachelor of -
Download Preprint
Note: This is the accepted version of the manuscript now published in Perspectives on Psychological Science: https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/full/10.1177/1745691620966794 Grahek, I., Schaller, M., & Tackett, J. L. (2020). Anatomy of a Psychological Theory: Integrating Construct-Validation and Computational-Modeling Methods to Advance Theorizing. Perspectives on Psychological Science. Anatomy of a Psychological Theory: Integrating Construct Validation and Computational Modeling Methods to Advance Theorizing Ivan Grahek1*, Mark Schaller2, & Jennifer L. Tackett3 1. Brown University, Department of Cognitive, Linguistic, & Psychological Sciences, Providence, RI, United States 2. The University of British Columbia, Department of Psychology, Vancouver, Canada 3. Northwestern University, Department of Psychology, Evanston, IL, United States * Corresponding author at: Department of Cognitive, Linguistic, & Psychological Science, Brown University, Providence, RI 02912, USA. E-mail address: [email protected] Anatomy of a Psychological Theory 2 Abstract Discussions about replicability of psychological studies have primarily focused on improving research methods and practices, with less attention paid to the role of well-specified theories in facilitating the production of reliable empirical results. The field is currently in need of clearly articulated steps to theory specification and development, particularly regarding frameworks that may generalize across different fields of psychology. Here we focus on two approaches to theory specification and development which are typically associated with distinct research traditions: computational modeling and construct validation. We outline the points of convergence and divergence between them to illuminate the anatomy of a scientific theory in psychology - what a well specified theory should contain and how it should be interrogated and revised through iterative theory development processes. -
The Power of Quantitative Thinking
18 The Power of Quantitative Thinking At age 14, having been fascinated by Karl Menninger’s book, The Human Mind, I decided to become a psychoanalyst rather than a lawyer. In the late 1930s, the Minnesota psychology department was not favorably inclined toward Freud’s teachings. Theoreticians William T. Heron and B. F. Skinner were archbehavior- ists, and the applied psychologists John G. Darley, Starke R. Hathaway, and Donald G. Paterson were hyper-operational psychometricians. John Harding left Minnesota to get his PhD at Harvard, and he described our department as “the hotbed of dust-bowl empiricism.” Professor Charles Bird, who taught an excel- lent course in abnormal psychology, grudgingly allowed for the existence of unconscious mental processes, and, like my mentor Hathaway, did think well of the mechanisms of defense. It is exactly 100 years since Freud abandoned the pressure technique in favor of free association; he considered this, especially as applied to the interpretation of dreams, to be his big methodological discovery. But we still do not know with any scientific confidence whether Freud’s doc- trines are 10%, 50%, or 90% correct. My colleague, David T. Lykken, whose analyst was the same as mine, has become quite skeptical about the whole busi- ness, although I note that, like me, he has a picture of Freud on his office wall. A former Skinnerian colleague rejected all of it, and in class lectures habitually referred to its creator as “Dr. Fraud.” How are we to explain this amazing epi- sode in the history of science, a system of ideas which has had such a profound and pervasive effect on the thinking of almost all educated persons but, after a century of research and practice, is still in such doubtful status? The standard explanations of my experimental colleagues, despite elements of truth, are inadequate, and I think wrong-headed. -
How Critical Realism Clarifies Validity Issues in Theory-Testing Research: Analysis and Case
2. How critical realism clarifies validity issues in theory-testing research: analysis and case ROBERT B . JOHnSTOn UnIvERSITy cOllEGE DUBlIn STEPHEn P . SMITH MOnASH UnIvERSITy AnD UnIvERSITy OF MElBOURnE Abstract Much discussion of research validity in information systems (IS) draws on the empiricist tradition, which presents an impoverished account of reality, making it difficult to formulate issues of validity that are pertinent to a practitioner- oriented discipline. This is particularly true for external validity, which refers to the applicability, or relevance, of research to phenomena in the broader environment of practices, but also for construct and internal validity, which seek to establish rigour in human-centred practical research. Discussions of validity are often supplemented with implicitly realist notions that are not compatible with the espoused empiricism. We argue that critical realism presents a number of insights that profoundly clarify a discussion of validity in practitioner-oriented theory-testing research. We reformulate the notions of theory testing and research validity from the critical realist perspective and illustrate them using a description of a controlled experiment. Important new insights are gained into establishing each kind of validity. 21 Information Systems Foundations: The Role of Design Science Introduction Ensuring that research is valid is an enduring theme in the information systems (IS) domain, as evidenced by the large number of articles in our premier journals that focus only on that topic and the amount of column space in more conventional theory-testing articles that purports to demonstrate that the work is valid in some way. In research that comes from the ‘positivist’ tradition in IS—such as laboratory experiments, surveys and theory-testing case studies— discussions of research validity typically draw either implicitly or explicitly on the empiricist position of quantitative social science for their justification. -
The Tragedy of Operationalism
The Tragedy of Operationalism Mark H. Bickhard Mark H. Bickhard Department of Psychology 17 Memorial Drive East Lehigh University Bethlehem, PA 18015 610-758-3633 office [email protected] [email protected] http://www.lehigh.edu/~mhb0/mhb0.html Keywords: operational definition, positivism, logical positivism, philosophy of science The Tragedy of Operationalism Mark H. Bickhard Abstract Operational definitions were a neo-Machean development that connected with the positivism of Logical Positivism. Logical Positivism failed, with the failure of operational definitions being just one of multiple and multifarious failures of Logical Positivism more broadly. Operationalism, however, has continued to seduce psychology more than half a century after it was repudiated by philosophers of science, including the very Logical Positivists who had first taken it seriously. It carries with it a presupposed metaphysics that is false in virtually all of its particulars, and thereby distorts and obscures genuine issues concerning the nature of theory and of science. It makes it particularly difficult for psychologists, under the thrall of this dogma, to free themselves from these false presuppositions, and to think about, create, and critique genuine scientific theory and process. That is the tragedy of operationalism. The Tragedy of Operationalism Mark H. Bickhard One of the central assumptions of Logical Positivism was that all meaning is empirical. Empirical content, and only empirical content, constituted genuine cognitive significance. A strong motivation for this assumption was the power it presumably provided for banishing metaphysics: metaphysical sentences had no empirical content, and, therefore, were simply meaningless. An early development of this radical empiricism was the attempt to construct a verifiability theory of meaning: the meaning of a sentence is its means of verification — the means by which its truth value could be determined (Suppe, 1977).