Command Responsibility and the Defence of Superior Orders

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Command Responsibility and the Defence of Superior Orders COMMAND RESPONSIBILITY AND THE DEFENCE OF SUPERIOR ORDERS Lecture April 20, 2015 by Arne Willy Dahl Introduction It has been told that the French emperor Napoleon Bonaparte once summoned one of his generals to answer for a lost battle. The general pointed out that the cause of the defeat was some more or less random events completely beyond the control of the general. The defeat was therefore to be considered as the result of bad luck, not to be attributed to any fault by the general. The emperor answered: I cannot afford to have generals with bad luck. You are relieved from your command. Napoleons reaction may not have been an example of good legal reasoning, but it illustrates the fact that from a military commander results are demanded, and that excuses for failure are not easily accepted. - If the commander tells his superiors that his mission failed because of insufficient training of his troops, he will be asked why he did not provide sufficient training for them. - If the cause was insufficient supplies of ammunition or other essential supplies, he will have to explain what he did in order to provide the supplies to the troops at the frontline. - And if he says that the soldiers were not prepared when the enemy attacked, because they had been drinking beer and amusing themselves with the village girls instead of fortifying their positions and watching the movements of the enemy, he will have to answer to why he permitted such behaviour. If he then answers that he did not know what the soldiers were doing, he will be asked why didn’t he inspect them. In other words, a commander must generally be prepared to be held responsible for acts or omissions by his subordinates, if he could have corrected matters by his own activity. Criminal responsibility Such responsibility may also be criminal. In this country we have peacetime examples of accidents caused by junior officers, the commanding officer having to answer in court for his passivity. - Commanders have been asked whether they have entrusted vital tasks to persons with sufficient qualifications. - They have been asked whether operations have been properly organised, ensuring that each man knows his tasks. - Has there been sufficient control of what the subordinates were doing? - Has the commander inspired the subordinates by his presence, showing that he is interested in what is going on? - Has he reacted on information, which should have raised his suspicion that some problem might be developing? I think that every developed army has to demand from its officers that they keep themselves informed, stay active and ahead of events, and take corrective action if something seems to be developing in an undesirable direction. The passive commander may lose his command, or in the more serious cases, face a trial. Responsibility for criminal actions commited by the subordinates. If a commander is to be held responsible for losing battles by not controlling his men, it is obvious that he should also be held responsible for spoiling the good reputation of his army or even his country, by his omission to control his men. And when one is speaking of grave crimes against innocent people, it is not only a matter of spoiling a good reputation, but a concern for all men of good will: How could this commander permit such things to happen? Thus, command responsibility is not a recent development, but is flows from the nature of a military organisation. It is a general principle of military organization that military commanders are responsible for their subordinates (Hague IV art. 1, Protocol I art. 43). This principle of responsibility, taken together with the authority to give orders and to punish disobedience or other undisciplined behavior, makes the difference between a military unit of lawful combatants and a collection of individual franc-tireurs. Without going into details, it can generally be said that it is this principle of organization and responsibility which absolves the individual soldier from criminal responsibility for the use of deadly force against other human beings, when he acts according to his orders and within the rules for armed conflict. Command responsibility has been practised in well-known criminal cases after the World War II. One is the case against the Japanese general Yamashita, who was held responsible for the conduct of his troops towards the civilian population in the Philippines. The charge was that he between October 9, 1944 and September 2, 1945, in the Philippine islands, “while commander of armed forces of Japan at war with the United States of America and its allies, unlawfully disregarded and failed to discharge his duty as commander to control the operations of the members of his command, permitting them to commit brutal atrocities and other high crimes against people of the United States and its dependencies, particularly the Philippines; and he * * * thereby violated the laws of war.” The number of victims ran up into tens of thousands. Another was Hirota, former Foreign Minister of Japan, who was convicted of atrocities - including mass rape - committed in the "rape of Nanking", under a count which charged that he had " recklessly disregarded their legal duty by virtue of their offices to take adequate steps to secure the observance and prevent breaches of the law and customs of war". The Tokyo Tribunal held that: "Hirota was derelict in his duty in not insisting before the Cabinet that immediate action be taken to put an end to the atrocities, failing any other action open to him to bring about the same result. He was content to rely on assurances which he knew were not being implemented while hundreds of murders, violations of women, and other atrocities were being committed daily. His inaction amounted to criminal negligence". Codification Codification in international treaties of the responsibility of commanders, is however comparatively recent. The Protocol 1 of 1977 to the Geneva conventions lays down in article 86 that the fact that a breach of the Conventions or of this Protocol was committed by a subordinate does not absolve his superiors from penal or disciplinary responsibility, as the case may be, if they knew, or had information which should have enabled them to conclude in the circumstances at the time, that he was committing or was going to commit such a breach and if they did not take all feasible measures within their power to prevent or repress the breach. It furthermore lays down in article 87, that the High Contracting Parties and the Parties to the conflict shall require military commanders, with respect to members of the armed forces under their command and other persons under their control, to prevent and, where necessary, to suppress and report to competent authorities breaches of the Conventions and of this Protocol. The Geneva Conventions and Additional Protocols are, however, neither written nor negotiated as criminal law texts. They give substantial guidance, but the final assessment of the guilt of an accused, should preferably be made with reference to a national or an international criminal legal text, and in the absence of applicable texts, with reference to international customary law according to the best assessment of the court or tribunal having jurisdiction, for instance the Yugoslavia and Rwanda tribunals. Command responsibility was included in the ICTY Statute ICTY Art. 7 3. The fact that any of the acts referred to in articles 2 to 5 of the present Statute was committed by a subordinate does not relieve his or her superior of criminal responsibility if he or she knew or had reason to know that the subordinate was about to commit such acts or had done so and the superior failed to take the necessary and reasonable measures to prevent such acts or to punish the perpetrators thereof. A similar provision is included in the 1994 ICTR Statute. In the negotiation of the 1998 ICC Statute, the provision was refined somewhat. To put it short, the article 28 makes a distinction between military commanders on the one hand, and civilian administrative or political leaders on the other. The article, however, equates a person effectively acting as a military commander, with military commanders. The reason is that in some cases a person can have the same functions and command authority as a military commander, without having a military rank, and should therefore have the same responsibility. From these persons – military commanders and civilians effectively acting as military commanders, the statute expects that they keep themselves informed of what is going on in the field. A military commander will have resources to obtain such information, and good military reasons to do so. He can therefore not be heard with that he did not know. From superiors “not described in paragraph 1” – which means ordinary civilian leaders, the statute expects that they act on the knowledge that they actually possess, equating positive knowledge with the conscious disregarding of information that is at hand. The Law expects from both the military commanders and ordinary civilian leaders that they “take all necessary and reasonable measures within his or her power to prevent or repress their commission or to submit the matter to the competent authorities for investigation and prosecution”. One may ask how action after the event can absolve the commander from responsibility for a crime that has taken place. - One answer may be that crimes that are likely to invoke command responsibility will be of some duration, and that early punitive action will be the best way to stop actual and potential future perpetrators. - Another answer may be that punishing crimes or submitting the matter to competent authorities will be the only possible alternative to inaction, if the crime has already taken place.
Recommended publications
  • Erosion of the Rule of Law As a Basis for Command Responsibility Under International Humanitarian Law
    Chicago Journal of International Law Volume 18 Number 2 Article 4 1-1-2018 Erosion of the Rule of Law as a Basis for Command Responsibility under International Humanitarian Law Amy H. McCarthy Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cjil Recommended Citation McCarthy, Amy H. (2018) "Erosion of the Rule of Law as a Basis for Command Responsibility under International Humanitarian Law," Chicago Journal of International Law: Vol. 18: No. 2, Article 4. Available at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cjil/vol18/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chicago Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Erosion of the Rule of Law as a Basis for Command Responsibility under International Humanitarian Law Amy H. McCarthy Abstract Many examples of modern war crimes exhibit a strong link between the institutional breakdown of the rule of law and subsequent commission of humanitarian abuses by service members. Unchecked misconduct, specifically including dehumanizing acts, tends to foster a climate where war crimes are likely to occur. Does the law adequately account for this common thread? This article examines the doctrine of command responsibility in the context of a superior’s failure to maintain discipline among troops, and resulting criminal culpability for violations of the law of armed conflict. While customary international law, as applied by modern ad hoc tribunals, contemplates a wide range of misconduct that may trigger a commander’s affirmative duty to prevent future abuses by subordinates, U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Command Responsibility After Bemba
    Command Responsibility after Bemba Ray Murphy* 1 Introduction Command responsibility is a subject that has generated significant controversy since its adoption in the post-World War ii trials. It took a long time for omis- sion liability to evolve under international criminal law.1 However, today it is a well established principal that superiors are criminally responsible for the ac- tions of subordinates under their effective command or authority.2 According to Schabas, the topic has generated “more heat than light”.3 This seems an apt description of how this doctrine is interpreted and applied by international tribunals and courts. Command responsibility is a complex form of criminal responsibility and its most recent iteration is Article 28 of the Rome Statute (“icc Statute”), governing responsibility of commanders and other superiors. This contains a lengthy and complex definition of what is a long established modality dealing with individual criminal responsibility under international law.4 For an act or omission to constitute the physical element of a crime, it is not sufficient that a commander be under a mere duty to act; he or she must * Professor, Irish Centre for Human Rights, School of Law, National University of Ireland Galway 1 Antonio Cassese and Paola Gaeta, Cassese’s International Criminal Law (Oxford University Press, 3rd ed, 2013) 180. 2 Otto Triffterer and Kai Ambos (eds), Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court – A Commentary (Beck Hart Nomos, 3rd ed, 2016) 1059; UK Ministry of Defence, The Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict (Oxford University Press, 2004) 436–8. 3 William Schabas, The International Criminal Court (Oxford University Press, 2010) 455.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 1 US Torture Policy and Command Responsibility James P. Pfiffner Abstract: Civilian Control of the Military and Political Cont
    A revised version of this paper was published in Examining Torture: Empirical Studies of State Repression, ed. Tracy Lightcap and James P. Pfiffner (NY: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014), pp. 103-126. US Torture Policy and Command Responsibility James P. Pfiffner Abstract: Civilian control of the military and political control of the executive branch are important constitutional principles upon which the United States government is based. After the 9/11 atrocities, President Bush used his power as president very effectively to pursue policies that would allow and encourage U.S. personnel to use harsh interrogation techniques to obtain intelligence in the war on terror. In implementing these interrogation policies, the Bush administration used legal arguments and the chain of command to ensure that the harsh interrogation policies would be carried out. In this process, the administration failed to heed the warnings of both civilian and military career professionals, and this led to the abuse and torture of detainees in the war on terror. This chapter will examine U.S. policy making on interrogation in the war on terror in light of several important principles of American government and international law: the politics-administration dichotomy, civilian control of the military, and command responsibility. President Bush used his power as president very effectively to pursue a policy direction that would allow and encourage U.S. personnel to use harsh interrogation methods to obtain intelligence in the war on terror. His aides marshaled legal arguments to support his position, despite serious objections from his Secretary of State, Colin Powell, and professional military lawyers in the Judge Advocate General Corps, among others.
    [Show full text]
  • Command Responsibility in International and Domestic Criminal Law
    2/24 ZBORNIK ZNANSTVENIH RAZPRAV – LXVIII. LETNIK, 2008 Command Responsibility in International and Domestic Criminal Law Summary The principle of command responsibility establishes the responsibility of mili- tary commanders and non-military superiors for unlawful actions committed by their subordinates or other persons subject to their control. This legal institution was invented by the international criminal law, which initially developed it as an institution of customary international criminal law. Later it also found its way into positive law. The paper discusses command responsibility stricto sensu, also known as indi- rect command responsibility. This type of command responsibility is based on the culpable omission of adequate supervision over subordinate persons who commit international crimes. It should be distinguished from direct command responsibility, i.e. international crimes committed on superiors’ order. In the latter case, superiors are hold responsible according to general rules !as instigators or indirect perpetra- tors), in which case a specific institution of command responsibility is not required. International criminal court practice, International Criminal Tribunal for the former %ugoslavia (the ICTY) in particular, proves that it is much harder to obtain evidence of direct command responsibility (i.e. that a crime has been committed pursuant to an superior’s order), while it is less difficult to prove omission of adequate supervi- sion over subordinate persons. This is the reason why in practice command responsi- bility stricto sensu became an extremely frequently used »backup« or »safety device« to prevent superior persons from escaping unpunished. This solution raised numer- ous questions among interpreters whether international criminal law went too far in its endeavours to create an institution that would enable a more apt conviction of superiors, and that in doing so, it came too close to strict liability.
    [Show full text]
  • The Superior Orders Defense: a Principal-Agent Analysis
    GEORGIA JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL AND COMPARATIVE LAW VOLUME 41 2012 NUMBER 1 ARTICLES THE SUPERIOR ORDERS DEFENSE: A PRINCIPAL-AGENT ANALYSIS Ziv Bohrer* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 3 II. THE CORE PREMISE OF THE CURRENT SUPERIOR ORDERS DEFENSE DISCOURSE .......................................................................................... 7 A. The Balancing Test ....................................................................... 7 B. The State of Applied Law............................................................ 13 1. International Law ................................................................ 14 2. American Military Law ........................................................ 17 III. AGENCY ANALYSIS OF OBEDIENCE TO ORDERS ............................... 19 A. Use of Agency Models ................................................................ 19 B. Agency Model of Obedience to Orders ...................................... 20 C. Command Responsibility Rule .................................................... 23 * Research Fellow, Sacher Institute, Hebrew University Faculty of Law (2012–2013); Visiting Research Scholar, University of Michigan Law School (2011–2012). The ideas in this Article were developed as part of my doctoral thesis, see Ziv Bohrer, The Superior Orders Defense in Domestic and International Law—A Doctrinal and Theoretical Revision (June 21, 2012) (unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Tel Aviv University) (on file
    [Show full text]
  • Command Responsibility: a Model for Defining Meaningful Human Control
    Cite as Miller, 11 J. NAT’L SECURITY L. & POL’Y __ (forthcoming 2021) Command Responsibility: A Model for Defining Meaningful Human Control By Matthew T. Miller* In the relatively near future, the United States and other countries are likely to develop varying levels of artificial intelligence (AI) and integrate it into autonomous weapons.1 There are significant voices, spearheaded by The Campaign to Ban Killer Robots, advocating for a preemptive ban on these weapons.2 The opponents of lethal autonomous weapon systems (LAWS) argue that it is unethical to allow a machine to decide when to kill and that AI will never be able to adhere to International Humanitarian Law (IHL) obligations.3 Although this opposition campaign has not yet achieved its goal of a ban, it has prompted considerable debate over the legality of developing and using LAWS. One of the concepts that has arisen in this debate is a legal requirement for meaningful human control (MHC) over LAWS.4 The idea of MHC has gained traction within discussions at the United Nations Convention on Certain Conventional Weapons (CCW), but the concept has its detractors.5 One of those detractors is the United States, whose delegation to the CCW Group of Governmental Experts continues to warn that MHC is an ambiguous term that “obscures rather than clarifies the genuine challenges” related to LAWS.6 Instead of human control, the U.S. argues that the key issue is ensuring “machines help effectuate the intention of commanders and the operators of weapon systems.”7 The U.S. Department of Defense showed its focus on intent, rather than control, by adopted the policy that “autonomous and semi-autonomous weapon systems shall * Major Matthew Miller is a Judge Advocate in the U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Command Responsibility for War Crimes
    Command Responsibility for War Crimes Citing the principle of command responsibility established by several post-World War II international tribunals,' various commentators have suggested that high American military and political leaders were re- sponsible for the many unordered war crimes committed by low-level troops in the Indochina War.2 The allegation is difficult to assess, partly because the post-war precedents left the principle's meaning unclear, and partly because the applicability of the precedents to Amer- ican defendants in American courts is an unsettled issue of domestic law. In the only command responsibility prosecution brought against an American officer during the Indochina War, the court-martial of Captain Ernest Medina, the laws of war played only a minor and am- biguous role, and the defendant was acquitted. a Thus the law on com- 1. Most of the tribunals which applied the principle are mentioned in a discussion of command responsibility in 15 UNITED NATIONS WAR CRIMES COMMISSION, LAW RFI'ORTS OF TRIALS OF WAR CRIMINALS 65-76 (H.M.S.O. 1945-1948) [hereinafter cited as UNLR). That a commander is responsible for subordinate crimes does not of course relieve the subordinate perpetrators of their direct responsibility for the crimes. Though coin- manders are also responsible for subordinate crimes which they have directly ordered, the term "command responsibility" refers throughout this Note only to liability for sub- ordinate crimes committed either under no order or tinder the order of someone other than the defendant-commander in question. This Note does not deal with a commander's duty to investigate and punish crimes after their commission.
    [Show full text]
  • Holding Military Leaders Accountable for Wartime Rape
    Rethinking Yam ashita : Holding Military Leaders Accountable for Wartime Rape Joshua H. Joseph I. Introduction………………………………………………………………………..……1 II. The Nature of Rape in Armed Conflict…………………………………………..…….4 A. History of Wartime Rape …………………………………………………….4 B. Staggering Statistics …………………………………………………...….…..5 C. Darfur : the latest example ………………………………………………...….6 D. Rape as a Tool of War ……………………………………………………..…7 III. The Doctrine of Command Responsibility ……………………………….………….11 A. Wartime leaders and Rape ……………………………………….…………11 B. History of Command Responsibility ……………………………………….12 C. The Doctrine …………………………...…………………………………….14 D. Actus Reus Requirement ……………………………………………………16 E. Mens Rea Requirement ………………………………..……………………18 II. Returning to an Old Standard: Presumption of Knowledge & Yamashita …………...19 A. The Yamashita standard ……………………………………………………20 B. Customary International Law & Yamashita…………………………….. ...22 C. Why an expanded Yamashita test is preferable ……………………...…….23 III. Imposing a duty on commanders to take proactive measures ..………………………25 A. Celebici ………………………………………………………………………25 B. Akayesu and the ICTR ………………...……………………………………28 C. Joint Criminal Enterprise as a mechanism for punishing commanders ...28 1 IV. Factors the Court may consider in determining whether leaders have successfully rebut the presumption........................................................................................................31 A. Training ………………………..…………………………………………….31 Monitoring, Reporting, & Intervention .………………………………………33 V. How the ICC
    [Show full text]
  • A Contemporary Approach to the Oldest International Crime Michael Scharf* and Mistale Taylor†
    UTRECHT JOURNAL OF Michael Scharf and Mistale Taylor, ‘A Contemporary Approach to the Oldest INTERNATIONAL AND EUROPEAN LAW International Crime’ (2017) 33(84) Utrecht Journal of International and European La, pp. 77-89, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/ujiel.373 RESEARCH ARTICLE A Contemporary Approach to the Oldest International Crime Michael Scharf* and Mistale Taylor† Maritime piracy began to re-emerge a decade ago, mostly off the coast of Somalia, thereby presenting major economic, security and humanitarian concerns. Prosecuting piracy raises many issues, not in the least because traditional maritime piracy from 200 years ago is so notably different from contemporary piracy. The present article describes the Public International Law and Policy Group’s formation of the High Level Piracy Working Group (HLPWG), which since 2011 has been producing memoranda on major issues in contemporary piracy prosecution. The issues span the legal foundations of piracy prosecution, including how to criminalise certain acts and how to exercise jurisdiction over such acts. Laws governing the use of force could apply to government or private actors when capturing and apprehending pirates. Once captured, there are questions of extraditing and transferring these pirates. Moreover, when such pirates are eventually brought to trial, there are pre-trial, evidentiary, substantive and post-prosecution issues to consider. The article also explores the merits and likelihood of creating an international piracy court. It shows how the HLPWG has influenced legal and policy developments today that draw on the distant past, and will undoubtedly have an enduring legacy in the future. Keywords: Piracy; Maritime security; Jurisdiction; Somalia; International crimes I.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prosecution of Sexual Violence in Conflict: the Importance of Human Rights As Means of Interpretation
    The Prosecution of Sexual Violence in conflict: The Importance of Human Rights as Means of Interpretation. Patricia Viseur Sellers TABLE OF CONTENTS Executive Summary I. Introduction II. Sexual Violence and Access to Justice – Progress and Obstacles a. Progress a.i. The recognition of Sexual Violence under International Humanitarian, Criminal and Human Rights Law 1. International Humanitarian Law 2. International Criminal law 3. International Human Rights Law a.ii. Direct and Indirect Criminal Responsibility 1. Direct Responsibility 2. Indirect Responsibility b. Obstacles – Prosecuting the Crime of Rape – the Element of Consent III. Possible Solutions – The International Human Rights and Criminal Law Frameworks a. The Relevance of International Human Rights Norms and Standards b. Rape under International Human Rights and Criminal Law b.i. International Human Rights b.ii. International Criminal Law IV. Concluding Observations Annex 2 Executive Summary The myriad forms of gender-based violence exemplify the human rights violation of gender discrimination. Pervasive sexual violence, a manifestation of gender-based violence, occurs during wartime, in its aftermath or in any period of societal breakdown. Gender-based violence undermines, impairs, nullifies and deprives females of the exercise of their human rights which are deemed inalienable, interdependent and indivisible from any and all other human rights. War related gender-based violence usually encompasses individual criminal responsibility and can exacerbate the denial of women’s human rights. Accordingly, several human rights instruments, declarations and pronouncements, such as the Convention on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women (CEDAW) General Recommendation No. 19 uphold a right to equal access to justice under the recognized and emerging humanitarian norms and international criminal law.
    [Show full text]
  • Ways of Attributing International Crimes to the 'Most Responsible'
    6 Command responsibility and Organisationsherrschaft : ways of attributing international crimes to the ‘most responsible’ K a i A m b o s * I . I n t r o d u c t o r y r e m a r k s Th e increasing trend to prosecute and punish international crimes and criminals, to fi ght against the widespread impunity for gross violations of human rights, with the means of (international) criminal law (see para. 4 of the preamble of the ICC Statute) is certainly to be welcomed and has received broad support in the academic literature, including by this author. 1 At the same time, however, one must not lose sight of the funda- mental principles of criminal law which are the product of centuries’ long fi ghts for fairness and the rule of law and which must not be ignored by the international criminal tribunals, especially the International Criminal Court (hereinaft er ‘ICC’). Indeed, from a national criminal law perspective, rooted in the trad- ition of enlightenment, there exists a tension between International Criminal Law (hereinaft er ICL)/international criminal jurisdiction and national criminal law/domestic jurisdictions at least in two respects. On the one hand, the increasing trend to criminalization, especially in its extreme form promoted by certain NGOs as prosecution and punishment at whatever cost, oft en confl icts with the traditional criminal law * Professor of Criminal Law, Criminal Procedure, Comparative Law and International Criminal Law at the Georg-August Universität Göttingen; Head of the Department of Foreign and International Criminal Law of the Institute of Criminal Law and Criminal Justice; Judge at the State Court (Landgericht) Göttingen.
    [Show full text]
  • The Brief Was Filed in Support of The
    No. 09-16246 & 10-13071 IN THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT ELOY ROYAS MAMANI, ET AL, Plaintiffs and Appellees, v. JOSE CARLOS SÁNCHEZ BERZAÍN AND GONZALO SÁNCHEZ DE LOZADA SÁNCHEZ BUSTAMENTE, Defendants and Appellants. APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF FLORIDA HON. ADALBERTO JORDAN, J., JUDGE CASE No. 07-22459 & 08-21-63 BRIEF OF AMICI CURIAE IN SUPPORT OF PLAINTIFF-APPELLEES’ MOTION FOR REHEARING EN BANC Leo P. Cunningham Andrea Evans Lee-Anne Mulholland Nushin Sarkarati WILSON SONSINI GOODRICH & ROSATI CENTER FOR JUSTICE & Professional Corporation ACCOUNTABILITY 650 Page Mill Road 870 Market Street, Suite 682 Palo Alto, California 94304-1050 San Francisco, CA 94102 Telephone: (650) 493-9300 Telephone: (415) 544-0444 Facsimile: (650) 565-5100 Facsimile: (415) 544-0456 Attorneys for Amici Curiae Retired Military Professionals, Scholars and Professors of Military Law INTEREST OF AMICI CURIAE Amici are retired military professionals, scholars and professors of military law. Professor Victor Hansen teaches at New England Law School. Before joining that faculty in 2005, he served 20 years in the Army, primarily as a JAG Corps officer. He was a regional defense counsel for the U.S. Army Trial Defense Service. His previous assignments included work as a military prosecutor and supervising prosecutor. He also served as an associate professor of law at The Judge Advocate General‟s Legal Center and School in Charlottesville, Virginia. He is the author of articles and books on military law and national security issues. Professor Richard Rosen teaches at Texas Tech University School of Law and joined the faculty after completing a career as an officer in the Judge Advocate General's Corps, U.
    [Show full text]