Legal Interpretivism by Ronald Dworkin

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Legal Interpretivism by Ronald Dworkin Legal Interpretivism by Ronald Dworkin (1931-2013): He is the greatest legal philosopher ever and is among the most influential moral and political philosopher of our time. He developed an original legal theory, which not only has transcended the Natural Law and Legal Positivism dichotomy, but also has reintegrated law into a branch of political morality. Interpretivism views law as being interpreted by the practice of lawyers and jurists, and claims this is the nature of law itself. Unlike other schools of legal philosophy, interpretivism views law not as something imposed from outside, but as a product of the practice of law. Interpretivists claim law has a relationship with ethics and morality, but that they are not the same. Legal interpretivism was developed in the late 20th and early 21st centuries. It emerged into a legal world dominated by two ways of thinking about the philosophy of law namely legal positivism and natural law theory. Interpretivism has some similarities to both schools of thought and some important differences. It has sometimes been thought of as a middle ground between the two. Natural law theory is the older of the two schools of thought. But there is an underlying natural law that serves as the foundation for manmade law. Natural law consists of basic principles of fairness, justice, and equity that transcend cultural boundaries, and manmade or "positive" law should respect these. In some traditions, natural law is believed to proceed from divine or supernatural sources, while others see it as inherent in human nature. Dworkin integrates morality both into the choice of legal theory and into the legal argument itself. In particular, this paper will explore Dworkin’s theory of Legal Interpretivism and how it appropriates the prior concepts of Natural Law Theory and Legal Positivism. For Dworkin, the goal of a lawyer is to construct law through his profession. Dworkin then uses this professional objective of “what lawyers and those versed in the law aim to build” as a denition for the law. This important responsibility is vested in individuals with a love of those subject to the law – society’s ideal lawyers. The main claims of interpretivism are that Law is not a set of given data or physical facts, but what lawyers aim to construct in their practice. There is no separation between law and morality, although there are differences. This is not in accordance with the main claim of legal positivism. Law is not immanent in nature nor do legal values and principles exist independently and outside of the legal practice itself. In the English speaking world, interpretivism is usually identified with Ronald Dworkin's theses on the nature of law as discussed in his text titled Law's Empire, which is sometimes seen as a third way between natural law and legal positivism. Ronald Dworking is one of the main opponents of legal Positivisms. Interpretative Approaches to Law : To resolve legal disputes, courts often need to interpret sources of law such as constitutions and statutes and precedents, and they need to interpret the communications by which parties try to order their own and others' legal rights and duties (such as leases and wills). Ronald Dworkin argues that law is an 'interpretive concept', by which he means that any true statement of law is true because it follows from the best interpretation of the legal practice of the community. Interpretivism about the nature of law is the view that legal rights and duties are determined by the scheme of principle that provides the best justification of certain political practices of a community: a scheme identifiable through an interpretation of the practices that is sensitive both to the facts of the practices and to the values or principles that the practices serve. Interpretivism has been developed by Ronald Dworkin in a number of publications over 30 years or so. Interpretivism as developed by Dworkin includes the claim that interpretation is sensitive to values in the way just explained, and that it is fundamental to the nature of law. Many theorists accept that, given the law, interpretation that is sensitive to values is necessarily employed in its application. For example, the rationale of giving up one's seat to a senior in the name of courtesy may be to show respect; if so, the display of respect would constitute the point of the practice, so that, if faced with the question what the practice requires that one do in a different context, the right answer would be sensitive to that point. For another example, which greatly simplifies a far more complicated practice, the rationale of awarding compensation for injuries caused by defective products may be that manufacturers should bear the cost of the risk associated with the use of the relevant products. Such a rationale would justify awarding damages when such injuries occur, whether or not the manufacturer is at fault — i.e. would justify no-fault liability. Case study To see how Legal Interpretivism plays out in practice, an example is important. We will turn our attention to a historic New York case, Riggs v. Palmer. In this foundational case, the testator Francis B. Palmer left a bulk of the estate in his will to his grandson, Elmer E. Palmer, and a lesser amount to his two daughters, Mrs. Riggs and Mrs. Preston. Fearing that the favorable will could be altered, Elmer Palmer then willfully murdered Francis Palmer and proceeded to claim title to the property that was left to him in the will. Here was the issue: even though the defendant, Elmer, was charged with his grandfather’s murder, there was no legal statute in place preventing Elmer from claiming the inheritance! The law of society at that time had no statutory prohibition on Elmer claiming title in this circumstance, and the defendant factually argued, “the testator is dead; that his will was made in due form and has been admitted to probate, and that, therefore, it must have effect according to the letter of the law.” However, the New York Court of Appeals’ decision states, “It was not the intention of the legislature, in the general laws passed for the devolution of property by will or descent, that they should, and they do not, operate in favor of one who murdered his ancestor or benefactor in order to speedily come into possession of his estate.” Instead of adopting a verbatim understanding of the textual law, the courts “favor a decision which upholds common decency and common morals, and violates no rule of law or equity.” There existed a value society saw as representing legal justice, which was not articulated in the statutes, “No one shall be permitted to profit by his own fraud, to take advantage of his own wrong, to found any claim upon his own inequity or to acquire property by his own crime.” The plaintiffs successfully argued to the Court of Appeals that Elmer would be unfairly profiting from his crime, which is inconsistent with what society viewed as just even though it was technically legal. The Court ruled in favor of the plaintiffs reasoning that the legislative statute (that is society’s law) was not adequate. Because Elmer committed the harm, he was not entitled to the compensation of the will because of a moral principle that had not yet been articulated by the law. Here, Legal Interpretivism is valuable, since it does not fall into the trap of Legal Positivism, which isolates law from morality. Conclusion Dworkin challenges the emerging positivist viewpoint that rejects the natural theory. In doing so, Dworkin claims that there are historical moral terminologies. They may derive from the Eternal Law in the holy books, or from society’s established principles of what is fair and just. Because of this, Dworkin concedes that morality is and always will be a part of the law, even though societies may change with time. Ultimately, it is the legal profession’s responsibility to maintain this presence of morality in the law. Legal principles have the ability to be moral, but this requires a sincere effort on behalf of the law–makers, law–executers, and law–deciders in a given society. This responsibility of the three branches of governance is to not be overlooked according to Dworkin’s appropriated Legal Interpretivism. .
Recommended publications
  • The Philosophical Underpinnings of Educational Research
    The Philosophical Underpinnings of Educational Research Lindsay Mack Abstract This article traces the underlying theoretical framework of educational research. It outlines the definitions of epistemology, ontology and paradigm and the origins, main tenets, and key thinkers of the 3 paradigms; positivist, interpetivist and critical. By closely analyzing each paradigm, the literature review focuses on the ontological and epistemological assumptions of each paradigm. Finally the author analyzes not only the paradigm’s weakness but also the author’s own construct of reality and knowledge which align with the critical paradigm. Key terms: Paradigm, Ontology, Epistemology, Positivism, Interpretivism The English Language Teaching (ELT) field has moved from an ad hoc field with amateurish research to a much more serious enterprise of professionalism. More teachers are conducting research to not only inform their teaching in the classroom but also to bridge the gap between the external researcher dictating policy and the teacher negotiating that policy with the practical demands of their classroom. I was a layperson, not an educational researcher. Determined to emancipate myself from my layperson identity, I began to analyze the different philosophical underpinnings of each paradigm, reading about the great thinkers’ theories and the evolution of social science research. Through this process I began to examine how I view the world, thus realizing my own construction of knowledge and social reality, which is actually quite loose and chaotic. Most importantly, I realized that I identify most with the critical paradigm assumptions and that my future desired role as an educational researcher is to affect change and challenge dominant social and political discourses in ELT.
    [Show full text]
  • Perspectives on Ethical Leadership: an Overview Drs Ir Sophia Viet MTD
    Perspectives on ethical leadership: an overview drs ir Sophia Viet MTD Paper submitted to the International Congress on Public and Political Leadership 2016 Draft version. Do not site or quote without the author’s permission Abstract There is a growing scientific interest in ethical leadership of organizations as public confidence in organizational leaders continues to decline. Among scholarly communities there is considerable disagreement on the appropriate way to conceptualize, define and study ethical leadership. This disagreement is partly due to the ontological and epistemological differences between the scholarly communities, resulting in different views of organizations, on the role of organizational leadership in general, and on ethical leadership of organizations in particular. Because of the differences in their ontological and epistemological assumptions scholars endlessly debate the concept of ethical leadership. This paper provides a comprehensive overview of the academic concepts of ethical leadership by classifying these concepts in terms of their ontological and epistemological assumptions and views of organizations into the modern, symbolic and the critical perspectives of postmodernism and communitarianism. Each category represents a particular set of perspectives on organizations, business ethics, and ethical leadership. The overview can serve as a guide to decode the academic debate and to determine the positions of the scholars participating in the debate. In addition it can serve as a multi-perspective-framework to study lay concepts of ethical leadership of (executive) directors of contemporary organizations. In this article the overview serves as a guide of how to classify some of the most common concepts in the debate on ethical leadership. Introduction There is a growing scientific interest in ethical leadership of organizations as public confidence in organizational leaders continues to decline.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretivism, Freedom of Expression, and Equal Protection
    Interpretivism, Freedom of Expression, and Equal Protection MICHAEL J. PERRY* I. A. We in the United States are philosophically committed to the political prin- ciple that governmental policymaking-by which I mean simply decisions as to which values among competing values shall prevail, and as to how those values shall be implemented'-ought to be subject to control by persons accountable to the electorate.2 As a general matter, a person is accountable to © Michael J. Perry 1981. * Professor of Law, The Ohio State University. A.B., 1968, Georgetown University; J.D., 1973, Columbia University. This Article is part of a larger work-in-progress, which will be published as a book by the Yale University Press in 1982, and which is tentatively titled THE CONSTITUTION, THE COURTS, AND HUMAN RIGHTS: AN INQUIRY INTO THE LEGITIMACY OF CONSTITUTIONAL POLICYMAKING BY THE JUDICIARY. Another part will be published in another symposium on judicial review. See Perry, Noninterpretive Review in Human Rights Cases: A Functional Justification, 56 N.Y.U.L. REV. - (1981). I. Cf. Hazard, The Supreme Court as a Legislature, 64 CORNELL L. REV. 1, 2 (1978): By a -legislature," I mean a body whose chief function in government is to formulate general rules of law that primarily reflect the notions of utility and value held by its members. Such a body is to be distinguished from a trial court, which applies law received from legally superior sources; from an administrative agency, which, in its rule-making capacity, formulates policy only within the limits of its organic statute; and from a "traditional" appellate court, which, in formulating law, is guided primarily by precedent.
    [Show full text]
  • Strategies in Research Garima Malhotra Assistant Professor, Department of Business Economics, Sri Guru Nanak Dev Khalsa College, Dev Nagar, Delhi University
    Malhotra Garima; International Journal of Advance Research and Development. (Volume2, Issue5) Available online at www.ijarnd.com Strategies in Research Garima Malhotra Assistant Professor, Department of Business Economics, Sri Guru Nanak Dev Khalsa College, Dev Nagar, Delhi University ABSTRACT A plan or scheme by which the activity of searching for and assessing information found is carried out is called a research strategy. A research strategy usually involves a number of steps. Firstly, the analysis of the major concepts of the topic. Secondly, defining relevant keywords and their synonyms. Thirdly, searching appropriate information sources (e.g. databases), and fourthly, assessing the quantity and quality (relevance) of the information found. The research strategy, a subset of research design, includes elements of data collection and interpretation and emerges from both the research purpose and question. These strategies differ in their Ontological assumptions, Starting points, Steps or logic use of concepts and theory, Styles of explanation and understanding and the status of their products. Each strategy has connections with particular philosophical and theoretical traditions, i.e. research paradigms (Blaikie 2007).The paper has been analyzed in view of the research strategies which are done in carrying out the research activity. They provide a ladder which helps in carrying out the research. The strategies Inductive, Deductive, Retroductive & Abductive have been explained in the paper with their epsitelmogical assumptions. The paper
    [Show full text]
  • World Views, Paradigms, and the Practice of Social Science Research
    01-Willis (Foundations)-45170.qxd 1/1/2007 12:01 PM Page 1 CHAPTER 1 World Views, Paradigms, and the Practice of Social Science Research Case 1. Quantitative Research Dr. James Jackson was concerned about whether a particular approach to teaching undergraduate courses is effective. The approach is called the per- sonalized system of instruction (PSI), developed by Fred Keller, a Columbia University psychologist and personal friend of B. F. Skinner. PSI (Martin, 1997) has been used for several decades in the sciences, but Dr. Jackson was not able to find convincing research about the suitability of PSI for humanities courses. Personalized System of Instruction (PSI) The PSI method of teaching was popular in the 1970s and is still used in many science classes. The content to be learned is divided into units or modules. Students get assignments with each module. When they think they have mastered a module, they come to class and take a test on that module. If they make 85% or more on the test, they get credit for the module and begin studying the next module. When they pass all the modules they are finished with the course and receive an A. In a course with 13 modules, anyone who completes all 13 might receive an A, students who finish 11 would receive Bs, and so on. The approach was called “personalized” because students could go at their own pace and decide when they wanted to be tested. Critics argued that PSI wasn’t very person- alized because all students had to learn the same content, which was selected by the instructor, and everyone was evaluated with the same objective tests.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Positivism, Interpretivism and Critical Theory
    Open Research Online The Open University’s repository of research publications and other research outputs Introduction to positivism, interpretivism and critical theory Journal Item How to cite: Ryan, Gemma (2018). Introduction to positivism, interpretivism and critical theory. Nurse Researcher, 25(4) pp. 41–49. For guidance on citations see FAQs. c [not recorded] https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ Version: Accepted Manuscript Link(s) to article on publisher’s website: http://dx.doi.org/doi:10.7748/nr.2018.e1466 Copyright and Moral Rights for the articles on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. For more information on Open Research Online’s data policy on reuse of materials please consult the policies page. oro.open.ac.uk Introduction to positivist, interpretivism & critical theory Abstract Background There are three commonly known philosophical research paradigms used to guide research methods and analysis: positivism, interpretivism and critical theory. Being able to justify the decision to adopt or reject a philosophy should be part of the basis of research. It is therefore important to understand these paradigms, their origins and principles, and to decide which is appropriate for a study and inform its design, methodology and analysis. Aim To help those new to research philosophy by explaining positivism, interpretivism and critical theory. Discussion Positivism resulted from foundationalism and empiricism; positivists value objectivity and proving or disproving hypotheses. Interpretivism is in direct opposition to positivism; it originated from principles developed by Kant and values subjectivity. Critical theory originated in the Frankfurt School and considers the wider oppressive nature of politics or societal influences, and often includes feminist research.
    [Show full text]
  • Justifying the Natural Law Theory of Constitutional Interpretation
    Fordham Law Review Volume 69 Issue 5 Article 22 2001 Justifying the Natural Law Theory of Constitutional Interpretation Michael S. Moore Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Michael S. Moore, Justifying the Natural Law Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Fordham L. Rev. 2087 (2001). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol69/iss5/22 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION AND ASPIRATIONS TO A GOOD SOCIETY JUSTIFYING THE NATURAL LAW THEORY OF CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION Michael S. Moore* INTRODUCFION An interpretive problem always exists in preparing papers on pre- set topics in symposia such as the present one. The questions my fellow panelists and I were asked to address were: (1) whether (and to what extent) the aspirations for a good society should enter into judicial interpretations of the Constitution; and (2) whether such infusion of moral theorizing by judges was consistent with their duties of fidelity to the Constitution? The interpretive problem arises because of the different readings possible for the phrase, "aspirations for a good society." One reading suggested by these Fullerian phrases-"morality of aspiration," "fidelity to law"-is that we are to address the possibility/desirability of judges interpreting the Constitution so as to further both the public and private virtue of our citizens.
    [Show full text]
  • Essays the Debate That Never Was
    ESSAYS THE DEBATE THAT NEVER WAS Nicos Stavropoulos∗ In September 1994, Professor Ronald Dworkin presented a new paper at the NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political, and Social Philoso- phy. Earlier that year, the second edition of Professor H.L.A. Hart’s The Concept of Law had appeared, which now included as a postscript an edited version of an unfinished manuscript that Hart had left at his death.1 Hart’s Postscript (as it came to be known) was Hart’s re- sponse to Dworkin’s work. In part, the Postscript addressed Dworkin’s arguments from the late 1960s and early 1970s that had di- rectly discussed Hart’s claims in the book.2 But it also addressed Dworkin’s own theory of law, developed in the 1970s and early 1980s and, most fully and systematically, in Law’s Empire, which appeared in 1986.3 The paper that Dworkin presented at the Colloquium, entitled Hart’s Posthumous Reply,4 was a rebuttal of Hart’s claims in the Post- script. This was an exciting development: Dworkin’s manuscript cir- ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ∗ Associate Professor of Legal Theory, University of Oxford. I am grateful to Mark Greenberg, Scott Hershovitz, and George Letsas for comments and suggestions on an earlier draft. Special thanks to Michael Zuckerman and Ahson Azmat, as well as to Robert Batista, Jenya Godina, and other editors of the Harvard Law Review, for their helpful suggestions. Harrison Tait provided valuable research assistance. 1 H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (2d ed. 1994) (with a Postscript edited by Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz).
    [Show full text]
  • Hart's Methodological Positivism
    University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law 1998 Hart's Methodological Positivism Stephen R. Perry University of Pennsylvania Carey Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Society Commons, Legal History Commons, and the Legal Theory Commons Repository Citation Perry, Stephen R., "Hart's Methodological Positivism" (1998). Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law. 1136. https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/1136 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship at Penn Law by an authorized administrator of Penn Law: Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Legal Theory http://journals.cambridge.org/LEG Additional services for Legal Theory: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Hart's Methodological Positivism Stephen R. Perry Legal Theory / Volume 4 / Issue 04 / December 1998, pp 427 - 467 DOI: 10.1017/S1352325200001105, Published online: 16 February 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S1352325200001105 How to cite this article: Stephen R. Perry (1998). Hart's Methodological Positivism. Legal Theory, 4, pp 427-467 doi:10.1017/S1352325200001105 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/LEG, IP address: 130.91.146.35 on 10 Dec 2013 Legal Theory, 4 (1998), 427-467. Printed in the United States of America Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1352-3252/98 $9.50 HART'S METHODOLOGICAL POSITIVISM Stephen R.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism As a Research Paradigm and Its Implications for Social Work Research
    social sciences $€ £ ¥ Article Pragmatism as a Research Paradigm and Its Implications for Social Work Research Vibha Kaushik * and Christine A. Walsh Faculty of Social Work, University of Calgary, Calgary, AB T2N 1N4, Canada * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 18 July 2019; Accepted: 3 September 2019; Published: 6 September 2019 Abstract: Debates around the issues of knowledge of, and for, social work and other social justice–oriented professions are not uncommon. More prevalent are the discussions around the ways by which social work knowledge is obtained. In recent years, social work scholars have drawn on the epistemology of pragmatism to present a case for its value in the creation of knowledge for social work and other social justice–oriented professions. The primary focus of this essay is on providing a critical review and synthesis of the literature regarding pragmatism as a research paradigm. In this essay, we analyze the major philosophical underpinnings and methodological challenges associated with pragmatism, synthesize the works of scholars who have contributed to the understanding of pragmatism as a research paradigm, articulate our thoughts about how pragmatism fits within social work research, and illustrate how it is linked to the pursuit of social justice. This article brings together a variety of perspectives to argue that pragmatism has the potential to closely engage and empower marginalized and oppressed communities and provide hard evidence for the macro level discourse. Keywords: pragmatism; pragmatic research; social justice research; social work research 1. Introduction In social research, the term “paradigm” is used to refer to the philosophical assumptions or to the basic set of beliefs that guide the actions and define the worldview of the researcher (Lincoln et al.
    [Show full text]
  • JUDICIAL DECISION MAKING in CASES with an INHERENTLY ETHICAL CONTENT by CLARK ASHLEY HOBSON
    INTERPRETIVISM AND THE FOUR PRINCIPLES APPROACH TO BIOMEDICAL ETHICS: JUDICIAL DECISION MAKING IN CASES WITH AN INHERENTLY ETHICAL CONTENT By CLARK ASHLEY HOBSON A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham For the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Birmingham Law School University of Birmingham September 2014 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. Abstract Judges are often reluctant to interact with medical ethics when deciding cases with an inherently ethical content. They sometimes even transfer decision-making responsibilities to medical ethics groups. At times this unwillingness is based on the presumption that medical ethics will be able to perform an effective regulatory function. The problem is there is a wide range of ethical discourse, both official and unofficial; so much it can cancel itself out. Therefore, as a regulatory tool for the medical profession, medical ethics is insufficient for the job. Judges, on the other hand, could arbitrate between competing ethical conclusions. Indeed, there is a strong argument they should. This thesis addresses this timely and complex issue. Judges need to be willing and able to rely on the soundness of their own moral convictions to recognise and deal appropriately with the inherent ethical content in certain cases.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretivism in IS – a Postmodernist (Or Postpositivist?) Knowledge Theory Jan H
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) AMCIS 2012 Proceedings Proceedings Interpretivism in IS – a Postmodernist (or Postpositivist?) Knowledge Theory Jan H. Kroeze School of Computing, University of South Africa, Pretoria, South Africa., [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2012 Recommended Citation Kroeze, Jan H., "Interpretivism in IS – a Postmodernist (or Postpositivist?) Knowledge Theory" (2012). AMCIS 2012 Proceedings. 7. https://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2012/proceedings/PerspectivesIS/7 This material is brought to you by the Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) at AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). It has been accepted for inclusion in AMCIS 2012 Proceedings by an authorized administrator of AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Kroeze Interpretivism in IS – a Postmodernist Knowledge Theory Americas Conference on Information Systems AMCIS2012 Seattle Interpretivism in IS – a Postmodernist (or Postpositivist?) Knowledge Theory Jan H. Kroeze University of South Africa [email protected] ABSTRACT This paper explores the association between postmodernism and interpretivism. The paper’s objective is to show that the interpretivist research paradigm shows very clear postmodernist traits. After defining the two concepts the paper attempts to answer the research question whether interpretivism is a typical postmodernist approach to Information Systems science and research. The paper is conceptual, using a philosophical-logical approach. It makes a contribution to the discipline of Information Systems by taking the reflection on the continuum of positivism-interpretivism-critical research a level deeper by connecting interpretivism with the broader, encompassing paradigm of postmodernism.
    [Show full text]