Chinese and Western

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chinese and Western Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series III, Asia, Volume 16 The Bases of Values in a Time of Change: Chinese and Western Chinese Philosophical Studies XVI Edited by Kirti Bunchua, Liu Fangtong, Yu Xuanmeng and Yu Xujin The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1999 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication The bases of values in a time of change: Chinese and Western ; Chinese Philosophical Studies 16 / edited by Kirti Bunchua, Liu Fangtong, Yu Xianmeng, Yu Wujin. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change . Series III. Asia, vol. 16) Includes bibliographies and index. 1. Values. 2. East and West. 3. Philosophy, Chinese. 4. Philosophy, Comparative. I. Bunchua, Kirti. II. Liu, Fangtong. III. Yu, Xuanmeng. IV. Yu, Wujin. V. Series. VI. Series: Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series III, Asia ; vol. 16. BD232.B36 1999 98-44462 121.8’09—dc21 CIP ISBN 1-56518-114-X (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Preface vii Introduction 1 George F. McLean Part I. The Present Shift in Cultural Values 1. The Contemporary Transformation of Chinese Marxist Philosophy 15 Liu Fangtong 2. Process as a Basis for Philosophy in a Time of Change 35 Warayutha Sriewarakul 3. Freedom and Cultural Traditions: The Basis of Values in a Time of Change 63 George F. McLean 4. Aesthetic Culture: from Tradition to Modernity 87 Chen Chaonan Part II. Material Basis of Values 5. The Loss of the Subject and the Disorder of Values: 99 Critical Reflections on Present Cultural Research Yu Wujin 6. Economic and Ethical Values 111 Lu Xiaohe 7. An Approach to Business Ethics: Fact-based Value for Fair Trade 123 Charn Mayot 8. Sustainability and a New Civilization 139 Wang Miaoyang 9. The Basis of Economic Values in Chinese Traditional Culture 147 Xu Hongxing Part III. Spiritual Basis of Values 10. The Dignity of the Human Person as the Basis for Community: 155 Pope John Paul II’s Contemporary Catholic Anthropology James A. Loiacono 11. Being and Values 177 Andrew Woznicki 3 12. Making Religion Ethical: The Value Orientation of 193 Religion in Contemporary Society Huang Songjie 13. The Basis of Values in a Time of Change 203 R. Balasubramanian 14. Renewal of Thai Buddhist Belief in Kamma and Rebirth 227 Veerachart Nimanong Part IV. Values and Asian Cultural Traditions 15. Is There a Thai Philosophy? 259 Kirti Bunchua 16. The Prospects and Justification of Thai Philosophy 263 Soraj Hongladarom 17. Changes of Values during the Renovation Period in Vietnam 275 Nguyen Trong Chuan 18. The Modern Significance of Chinese Traditional Culture 283 Fang Songhua 19. Existential Relationships and Optimal Harmony: 291 Philosophical Foundations for Valuesin a Times of Changes Vincent Shen Part V. Communication Between Cultures 20. The Change of Society and the Exchange of Values 317 Zhang Qingxiong 21. Lifeworld and the Possibility of Intercultural Understanding 327 Zhang Rulun 22. On the Unity of Pluralistic Values 339 Yu Xuanmeng Index 353 Acknowledgements 4 Preface Kirti Bunchua It has been a great honor for Assumption University and especially its School of Philosophy and Religious Studies to host this Symposium with the teams of distinguished scholars from the Institute of Philosophy of Shanghai Academy of Social Sciences and Department of Philosophy of Fudan University, Shanghai. This is part of a series cosponsored by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy (RVP) with the Chinese philosophers since 1997. Assumption University continues to promote the study of values and philosophy, especially the foundations of social life and civil society, with special attention to the way in which Buddhism and Christianity may jointly contribute over time. It is our hope, beginning with this work, to share the results of the research with philosophers in all parts of the world. Assumption University now has close collaboration with the scholars from mainland China. This project is surely not the last; we look forward to more such a collaboration in the future. Last but not least, I would like to thank Dr. George F. McLean for facilitating this precious opportunity for our School of Philosophy and Religious Studies to engage in cooperative world and effort of The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy (RVP) for the restoration of civil society in our times. Assumption University Bangkok, Thailand 5 Introduction George F. McLean This turn of the millennia promises to be not only a change in numbers or even an incremental development along familiar paths. Far beyond this, we are living a profound vertical deepening of human awareness to new levels of human life and sacred meaning. This, in turn, enables us to engage horizontally a broadened, even global, diversity of peoples and cultures. This expansion of the dynamism of human awareness both in depth and in breadth opens new dimensions and creates new challenges for the work of philosophy. To appreciate the extent to which this is true it is important to keep in mind the history of the last millennium. If we turn to Western philosophy we find it to be characterized by the emergence of human reflection and its logical systematization, traced archetypically from Plato and his student, Aristotle. Philosophy in the first half of the present millennium was characterized above all by the rediscovery of the work of Aristotle and its elaboration into the great medieval systems of Aquinas and Scotus, Avicenna and Averroes, Moses Mamonides and others. There, one finds reason in the service of humankind, clarifying and systematically coordinating ideas and relating them to the sources, goals and virtues of human life. But the history of humankind and of philosophy is also tragic in its destiny, for the capabilities of reason can be the key to progress which bears the needs of its own frustration. Thus, at the end of the Renaissance in a series of delimiting strokes reason was wrenched out of the pattern of integral human life. Francis Bacon went about destroying the “idols” which bore the symbols of cultural traditions as the accumulation of creative human freedom; John Locke would erase the content of the mind and reduce it to a blank tablet, Descartes would bracket by doubt all but clear and distinct ideas — which meant all but the self and what could be built thereupon. This radicalization of reason and philosophy made it possible to work with clearly defined ideas and to develop correspondingly clear structures for science and philosophy. Most thinkers were fascinated by the new achievements made possible by this radical surgery. Only a few, such as Pascal and J.B. Vico, noted from the beginning the costs to be paid for this reductionist approach of rationalism. What characterizes the depth of the transformation now taking place is the new recognition of how restrictive, and indeed destructive, this reductionism has been. This awareness is made possible negatively by the experience of the violent tragedies of the recent century, the wars hot and cold, the pogroms and holocausts, and the rise of nationalist ideologies. In the first chapter, “The Contemporary Transformation of Chinese Marxist Philosophy,” Professor Liu Fangtong magisterially delineates this situation by contrasting modern with contemporary thought. In the former, reason as restricted to clear ideas is apt for attending to what is universal, i.e. to the natures or essences of things. But these are abstracted from what is unique and especially from the freedom of human persons and peoples. Corresponding to this is the restriction of reason to what is distinct; indeed the criterion of clarity is the ability to distinguish one idea as distinct from all others. This entailed, however, a decided turn to analysis which progressed precisely by dividing realities for purposes of conceptual clarity. What was left unattended was the synthetic appreciation of the unity and integrity of reality. There resulted a pattern of dualisms between mind and matter, subject and object, individual and community. This has constituted the destabilizing fault line of modern thought and generated not 7 only continual tremors, but the vicious extremes expressed in exploitation, oppression and war. Moreover, marked by this fascination with reason, modern thought neglected the practical and the aesthetic. This attempt to restrict human awareness to the sciences suggests the extent of the constructive project which lies ahead if philosophy is to retain modern achievements while expanding the structure of reason, recognizing additional dimensions of the person, and making possible authentic growth. The modern-contemporary schema of Professor Liu Fangtong allows him to rethink the fate of Marxism, to see its humane concerns and to project their retention and development. Indeed he sees Marx primarily as attempting to transcend modernity and its rationalism in order to free the subject from oppression. In that sense Liu Fangtong interprets Marx essentially as a contemporary philosopher. Unfortunately his efforts became bogged down in the very rationalism he intended to transcend. He was entrapped by the scientistic overlays of Engels who, in attempting to make this thought into a science like others, subjected it to universal and necessary laws which suppressed the freedom and creativity of people. Hence, in the late 70s and 80s in central Europe the great battle was to free the younger humanistic Marx from the later Marx. This is the great shared enterprise of most peoples today. The central importance of the paper of Professor Liu Fangtong to this volume and indeed to our times is to raise the question of just what developments in epistemology, metaphysics and philosophical anthropology are required in order for such a project to succeed and hence to allow for a progressive and transformative view of values in a time of change.
Recommended publications
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Aquinas' Argument from Motion & the Kalām Cosmological
    University of Central Florida STARS Honors Undergraduate Theses UCF Theses and Dissertations 2020 Rethinking Causality: Thomas Aquinas' Argument From Motion & the Kalām Cosmological Argument Derwin Sánchez Jr. University of Central Florida Part of the Philosophy Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the UCF Theses and Dissertations at STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Undergraduate Theses by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Sánchez, Derwin Jr., "Rethinking Causality: Thomas Aquinas' Argument From Motion & the Kalām Cosmological Argument" (2020). Honors Undergraduate Theses. 858. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses/858 RETHINKING CAUSALITY: THOMAS AQUINAS’ ARGUMENT FROM MOTION & THE KALĀM COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT by DERWIN SANCHEZ, JR. A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Arts and Humanities and in the Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Fall Term 2020 Thesis Chair: Dr. Cyrus Zargar i ABSTRACT Ever since they were formulated in the Middle Ages, St. Thomas Aquinas’ famous Five Ways to demonstrate the existence of God have been frequently debated. During this process there have been several misconceptions of what Aquinas actually meant, especially when discussing his cosmological arguments. While previous researchers have managed to tease out why Aquinas accepts some infinite regresses and rejects others, I attempt to add on to this by demonstrating the centrality of his metaphysics in his argument from motion.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy As a Path to Happiness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Philosophy as a Path to Happiness Attainment of Happiness in Arabic Peripatetic and Ismaili Philosophy Janne Mattila ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII, University main building, on the 13th of June, 2011 at 12 o’clock. ISBN 978-952-92-9077-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-7001-3 (PDF) http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/ Helsinki University Print Helsinki 2011 2 Abstract The aim of this study is to explore the idea of philosophy as a path to happiness in medieval Arabic philosophy. The starting point is in comparison of two distinct currents within Arabic philosophy between the 10th and early 11th centuries, Peripatetic philosophy, represented by al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā, and Ismaili philosophy represented by al-Kirmānī and the Brethren of Purity. These two distinct groups of sources initially offer two contrasting views about philosophy. The attitude of the Peripatetic philosophers is rationalistic and secular in spirit, whereas for the Ismailis philosophy represents the esoteric truth behind revelation. Still, the two currents of thought converge in their view that the ultimate purpose of philosophy lies in its ability to lead man towards happiness. Moreover, they share a common concept of happiness as a contemplative ideal of human perfection, merged together with the Neoplatonic goal of the soul’s reascent to the spiritual world. Finally, for both happiness refers primarily to an otherworldly state thereby becoming a philosophical interpretation of the Quranic accounts of the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • The Function of the Trinity in Moltmann's Ecological Doctrine of Creation Paul D
    Theological Studies 51 (1990) THE FUNCTION OF THE TRINITY IN MOLTMANN'S ECOLOGICAL DOCTRINE OF CREATION PAUL D. MOLNAR St. John's University, Jamaica, N.Y. CCORDING TO Jürgen Moltmann, "In the 1930's, the problem of the AL doctrine of creation was knowledge of God. Today the problem of the doctrine of God is knowledge of creation. The theological adversary then was the religious and political ideology of 'blood and soil', 'race and nation'. Today the theological adversary is the nihilism practised in our dealings with nature. Both perversions have been evoked by the unnatural will to power "* Moltmann's ecological doctrine of creation sees God's Spirit "in all created beings." To understand this, Moltmann has interwoven the first three articles of the Apostles' Creed in a trinitarian sense in order to "develop a pneumatological doctrine of creation. This doctrine of creation ... takes as its starting point the indwelling divine Spirit of creation."2 This thinking, Moltmann hopes, will provide a more holistic philosophy of nature. The word "ecology" means "the doctrine of the house." Molt­ mann's point is that if we see creation only as God's "work," such a doctrine will make little sense, but "if we understand the Creator, his creation, and the goal of that creation in a trinitarian sense, then the Creator through his Spirit dwells in his creation as a whole, and in every individual created being, by virtue of his Spirit holding them together and keeping them in life."3 As the inner secret of creation is this indwelling of God, the purpose of Shekinah (God's indwelling) is "to make the whole creation the house of God."4 To this theological side of 1 Jürgen Moltmann, God in Creation: A New Theology of Creation and the Spirit of God (New York: Harper and Row, 1985) xi; hereafter abbreviated Creation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysics of Jonathan Edwards's End of Creation
    JETS 59/2 (2016): 339–59 THE METAPHYSICS OF JONATHAN EDWARDS’S END OF CREATION WALTER SCHULTZ* Abstract: In his dissertation ConcernIng the End for which God Created the World, the American theologian and philosopher, Jonathan Edwards (1703–1758), argues precisely and validly for a particular view of God’s purpose and motive in creating and sustain- ing the world on the substantive assumptions that creation is ex nihilo and that only God is absolutely independent and self-sufficient. He asserts that his is the only conceptually possible counterexample to Baruch Spinoza’s contention that no specific position on God’s end and mo- tive in creation combined with a commitment to God’s aseity and creatio ex nihilo can escape incoherence. His argumentation entails a complex metaphysics, which—with careful qualifica- tion—may be referred to by the following terms: dispositionalism, emanationism, idealism, panentheism, anti-platonism, continuous creationism, and occasionalism. This paper briefly de- scribes Edwards’s argumentation for God’s end and motive in creation, summarizes each of these seven positions, and shows how they logically follow. Key Words: emanation, disposition, idealism, platonism, panentheism, continuous creation- ism, occasionalism. Jonathan Edwards’s argumentation in his 1765 dissertation Concerning the End for which God Created the World entaIlS a partIcular verSIon of emanatIonISm, dISpoSI- tionalism, Idealism, antiplatonism, panentheism, continuous creationism, and occa- sionalism.1 ThIS paper brIefly deScrIbeS Edwards’s argumentation for God’s end and motive in creation then Summarizes each of these seven positions and how they logically follow.2 My aImS are to preSent a précIS of EdwardS’S theory of God and creation only in so far as it is expressed in End of Creation.
    [Show full text]
  • TABLE of CONTENTS PROLEGOMENA I. the Term 'World'
    TABLE OF CONTENTS PROLEGOMENA PREPARATION FOR NATURAL PHILOSOPHY I. The Term 'World'. - II. Three Senses of 'World'. - III. Christ, the Perfect World. - IV. The World of Which we Shall Here Speak. - V. On the Object of Cosmology, or Natural Philosophy. - VI. It is Clear that Natural Philosophy is a Science. - VII. Division of Natural Philosophy. - VIII. On the fortune/history of Natural Philosophy - IX. Where the study of Natural Philosophy should be Treated. - X. Authors who have Written about Natural Philosophy. - XI. On the Method to be Followed in studying Natural Philosophy 34 FIRST TREATISE ON THE WORLD WITH RESPECT TO ITS EFFICIENT CAUSE FIRST QUESTION On the Peculiar Characters of the World FIRST ARTICLE Whether the world is simple and something perse one or something composed http://d-nb.info/1034270907 I. Monism. - II. Defenders of Monism. - III. The Three Forms of Monism. - IV. - First Conclusion: Monism, in whichever form it be proposed, is self-contradictory." - V. Objections. - VI. Second Conclusion: "All possible composition is to be ascribed to the world." 44 SECOND ARTICLE Whether the world is a contingent being I. Meaning of the Question. - II. Errors. - III. The First System is Refuted Easily. - IV. Uncaused Matter. - V. Conclusion: "Uncreated matter existing eternally is intrinsically contradictory." - VI. On the Fortuitous Coinciding of Atoms. - VII. The System of Active Evolution. - VIII. Active Evolution in many ways results in absurdity. - IX. The System of Hylozoism. - X. The System of Logical Evolution. - XI. What Kind of Necessity is Found in the World: on the law of inertia and the indestructibility of matter.
    [Show full text]
  • Ten PROBLEMS with AQUINAS' THIRD
    Ten PROBLEMS WITH AQUINAS' THIRD WAY Edward Moad 1. Introduction Of Thomas Aquinas’ five proofs of the existence of God, the Third Way is a cosmological argument of a specific type sometimes referred to as an argument from contingency. The Aristotelian argument for the existence of the First Unmoved Mover was based on the observation that there is change (or motion), coupled with the principle that nothing changes unless its specific potential to change is actualized by an actual change undergone by some other thing. It then arrives at the conclusion that there exists something in a constant state of pure activity, which is not itself moved but sets everything else in motion. The operative sense of contingency this argument turns on, then, is that of motion. That is, things have the potential to change in certain ways (depending on the kind of things they are), but may or may not do so; whether they actually do being contingent on whether they are acted on in the right way by something else. For this reason, Aristotle’s argument delivers a first mover, which brings about the motion in all that exists, but not a being that brings about the very existence of everything else. The argument referred to specifically as the argument from contingency, by contrast, turns on the idea of the contingency of the very existence of anything at all. That is, if something exists which may not have existed, and the fact that it does exist rather than not is contingent on the action of other existing things which are themselves contingent, then the existence of the whole lot of contingent things, taken together, is also contingent.
    [Show full text]
  • A Round Generation in the Timaeus
    AROUND GENERATION IN THE TIMAEUS By JONATHAN WRIGHT, M.D. PLEASANTVILLE, NEW YORK N turning to a former issue of pupil derived from his master. Aristotle Annals of Medical History I repeatedly calls himself a Platonist. A find that I began an essay on the modern commentator2 on Aristotle has “Timaeus” of Plato with a refer­ recorded references to a number of passages ence to Aristotle.1 In the present article, in his works where the younger man pays a Owhich will find its mainspring also in the tribute of respect to Plato and acknowledges “Timaeus,” but which deals largely with himself as his follower. the subject of some of the modern ideas on In reading Galen the medical historian the birth of man, we shall again have to take perceives how much more he was inspired by up some of the ideas of Aristotle, as well as Plato than by Aristotle. He places Plato and those of Plato, on the birth of matter. It is not Aristotle side by side with Hippocrates this which leads us into the “Timaeus” in his treatise on their dogmas.3 Robin4 points again. I presume without the criticism of out that Plato gave birth scarcely less to Aristotle on the “Timaeus,” especially of Aristotle than to Plotinus. In the former all his master’s books, subsequent commen­ paper I referred to the very dark corner in tators would less frequently, certainly less the “Timaeus” which deals with generation intelligently, have made a study of it. For and which Plato calls the Receptacle. This many of the formative years of his life Robin regards5 as “the nurse of generation.” Aristotle was a pupil of Plato, for seventeen It is the place where not only the birth of years of his youth, it is said.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Aristotle's Unmoved Mover Causally Redundant?
    Bridget Brasher IS ARISTOTLE’S UNMOVED MOVER CAUSALLY REDUNDANT? On dunamis in the heavenly bodies I. Introduction: understanding the redundancy problem That Aristotle believes an unmoved mover both enables and brings about motion in the universe is taken as basic by interpreters. Throughout Physics VIII and Metaphysics Lambda 6–10, Aristotle assigns a superlative importance to this eternal, imperceptible substance. It is uniquely pure energeia, is absolutely prior, and is ultimately, indirectly responsible in some way for all generation and destruction and change throughout the celestial and sublunar realms. Aristotle considers the unmoved mover, in this way, to be a kind of primordial necessary condition. Moreover, the unmoved mover is said to maintain this role by directly exerting some sort of causal influence on the heavenly spheres, such that the spheres thereby move eternally, and in turn transmit changes downward through the celestial and sublunar realms. Upon getting the spheres to move, then, the unmoved mover’s vast influence is mediated by and transmitted through the spheres’ own motion.1 The problem that I will address in this paper is that, it seems, the spheres are apparently bound to move in any case—for it seems that, in virtue of a fact about themselves, they can never stop moving. And thus, Aristotle’s primordial necessary condition appears to be little more than a mere redundancy. 1 That the unmoved mover’s alleged causal influence is exhaustively mediated by the heavenly spheres is not uncontroversial. For some interpreters have read a kind of cosmic teleology directed towards the unmoved mover in Aristotle (See Kahn, 1985, Lear, 1988).
    [Show full text]
  • Thevirginthat Became Male: Feminine Principles in Platonic And
    chapter 14 The Virgin That Became Male: Feminine Principles in Platonic and Gnostic Texts John D. Turner It is indeed an honor to contribute to this anthology of studies on the subject of Women and Knowledge in Early Christianity in recognition of our esteemed col- league Antti Marjanen—to my knowledge the only Professor of Gnostic Studies in the modern academic world—who has taught us so much on the subject of gender and the role of women in antiquity and the early Christian world. Although he has dealt extensively with real women as intellectual leaders in these contexts, I would like to explore a more abstract topic, namely the ways in which wisdom (σοφία) and (spiritual) knowledge (γνῶσις) are frequently per- sonified as female entities. Of course one must bear in mind that there is a distinction between functional femininity and merely grammatical femininity in ancient Greek, Latin, and Coptic sources, in which various significant nouns and pronouns in the philosophical and mythological schemes can appear in the feminine gender, sometimes for good and substantial reasons, and sometimes for reasons that are purely grammatical and lexicographic.1 In this chapter, I survey the phenomenon of feminine principles in the meta- physics of selected Platonic and gnostic literature. The Platonic sources will include Plato’s later dialogues and oral teaching, and continue with some sub- sequent Platonist sources, including Speusippus, Philo of Alexandria, Moder- atus, Plutarch, Numenius, the Chaldaean Oracles and Plotinus. I will limit the treatment of gnostic sources to texts commonly referred to as “classic gnos- tic” or “Sethian.” These will include the theogony that Irenaeus in his Adver- sus Haereses 1.29–30 attributes to certain “gnostics” later identified as Ophites, Sethians and Barbeloites, and the related Nag Hammadi treatises Eugnostos the Blessed, Apocryphon of John, Holy Book of the Great Invisible Spirit (Gospel of the Egyptians), Trimorphic Protennoia, Allogenes, Zostrianos, and Marsanes.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Argument's for God's Existence Kant's Criticisms O
    Kant’s Arguments for God’s Existence Introduction Background: Three Argument’s for God’s Existence Kant’s criticisms of these three arguments Ground vs. Cause: Kant’s reason for rejecting constructive proofs of God’s existence Kant’s first argument for God’s existence: God’s existence as the foundation of causal explanation Kant’s second argument for God’s existence: Natural orderliness as being grounded in the coherence of God’s mind Kant’s third argument for God’s existence: morality as grounded in the coherence of God’s mind Kant’s arguments for God as transcendental arguments Introduction Kant puts forth three arguments for God’s existence---or, what might be more accurate, three very different versions of a single such argument. Each is original and none has any obvious flaws. This is not to say that they prove what they are meant to prove, only that, if they fail to do so, it is not immediately clear why. Background: Three Argument’s for God’s Existence When philosophers try to prove God’s existence, it is almost always by way of one of the following three arguments: the ontological argument, the cosmological argument, and the teleological argument. Kant rejects each of these arguments, and his own arguments are to be understood in terms of this fact. Right now, I will state and evaluate these arguments, and then I will state and evaluate Kant’s arguments. The ontological argument: God is by definition perfect; failure to exist is an imperfection; therefore, God must exist. Analysis: This argument is a total failure, since all it shows is the truism is that if God existed, then, having as he would every conceivable perfection, he would exist— since, in other words, all it shows is that if God existed, then God would exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Rational Vs. Mystical Readings of Aristotle's Nous
    #0# „Analiza i Egzystencja” 39 (2017) ISSN 1734-9923 DOI: 10.18276/aie.2017.39-02 SONIA KAMIŃSKA* RATIONAL VS. MYSTICAL READINGS OF ARISTOTLE’S NOUS POIETIKOS. INTRODUCTION TO THE SUBJECT AND OVERVIEW OF CENTRAL POSITIONS Keywords: nous poietikos, mystical and rational readings, Aristotle, psychology, God/Deity, immortality, intellectual soul, unio mystica Słowa kluczowe: nous poietikos, interpretacje mistyczne i racjonalistyczne, Arystote- les, psychologia, Bóg/Bóstwo, nieśmiertelność, dusza rozumna, unio mystica Introduction Nous poietikos, introduced by Aristotle in De Anima 3.5, has always been one of the central issues of philosophical reflection. It is vital not only to understand Aristotle, but also his pupils (both immediate and the ones who came later), as well as his predecessors (see: the manifold analogies to * Sonia Kamińska, Ph.D. – Jagiellonian University, Institute of Philosophy. Funding: My research (2015/19/D/HS1/00969) was financed from the assets awarded by The Na- tional Science Centre, Poland upon the decision no. DEC-2015/19/D/HS1/00969. Current project: Mystical and rational readings of Aristotle’s psychology, and especially of nous poietikos, National Science Centre, Poland, 2016–2019. Address for correspondence: Jagiellonian University, Institute of Philosophy, Grodz- ka 52, 31-044 Kraków. E-mail: [email protected]. 20 Sonia Kamińska Anaxagoras and his ruling nous, for instance). The urge to grasp the essence of intellectual soul has always driven our civilisation towards new ques- tions and theories. It was vital even in the age of retreat from Aristotelian thought. Despite all this unflagging interest, the question of its true nature is still far from being solved.
    [Show full text]