Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade? Author(S): Michael Gagarin Source: Rhetorica: a Journal of the History of Rhetoric, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade? Author(S): Michael Gagarin Source: Rhetorica: a Journal of the History of Rhetoric, Vol Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade? Author(s): Michael Gagarin Source: Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric, Vol. 19, No. 3 (Summer 2001), pp. 275-291 Published by: University of California Press on behalf of the International Society for the History of Rhetoric Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1525/rh.2001.19.3.275 . Accessed: 04/03/2014 06:46 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of California Press and International Society for the History of Rhetoric are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Rhetorica: A Journal of the History of Rhetoric. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 147.52.233.137 on Tue, 4 Mar 2014 06:46:40 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions MichaelGagarin Didthe Sophists Aim to Persuade? Abstract: Ever since Plato,the Sophists have been seen asteaching “the artof persuasion”, particularlythe art(or skill) ofpersuasive speaking in the lawcourtsand the assembly on which success in life depended. Iargue thatthis view is mistaken. Although Gorgias describes logos asworking topersuade Helen, he does not present persuasion asthe goalof his own work, nor does any other Sophist see persuasion asthe primary aim ofhis logoi.Most sophistic discourse wascomposed in the form ofantilogies (pairsof opposed logoi),in which category Iinclude works like Helen where the other side—the poetictradition Gorgias explicitly cites ashis opponent— is implicitly present. The purpose ofthese works is primarily to display skill in intellectual argument, aswell astogive pleasure. Persuasion may beagoalof some sophistic works, butit is not their primary goal;and teaching the artof persuasion wasnot amajor concern ofthe Sophists. eallknow that for the Greeks rhetoricwas the artof W persuasion.Indeed, thisis so well knownthat George Kennedy’s standardhandbook is entitled not“ Rhetoricin Greece”, but TheArt ofPersuasion in Greece .1 Wecantrace the idea backto Aristotle’ s Rhetoric,where atthe beginning of 1.2we read (in Kennedy’s translation)“ Letrhetoric be [dened as]an ability , in each[particular] case, to see the availablemeans of persuasion”, 2 andwe canalso nd itin the earlier analysisof rhetoricin Plato’s Gorgias,where Gorgiasidenti es his techneˆ—his“ craft”or “ art”— as heˆrheˆtorikeˆtechneˆ (“the rhetoricalart” ) andde nes itas follows:“ Isay itis the power topersuade by speech ( peitheintois logois )jurorsin the 1 GeorgeA. Kennedy, TheArt of Persuasion inGreece (Princeton: Princeton Uni- versity Press, 1963). 2 Aristotle, Aristotle on Rhetoric:A Theoryof CivicDiscourse ,transGeorge A. Kennedy(New York:Oxford University Press, 1991)p. 36. ©TheInternational Society for the Historyof Rhetoric, Rhetorica, Volume XIX,Number 3 (Summer2001). Send requests forpermission to reprint to: Rights andPermissions, University of CaliforniaPress, JournalsDivision, 2000Center St, Ste 303,Berkeley ,CA94704-1223,USA 275 This content downloaded from 147.52.233.137 on Tue, 4 Mar 2014 06:46:40 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 276 R H E T O R I C A jury-court, councilorsin the council,assemblymen in the assembly, andin every othergathering” (452e). From this Socrates concludes thatrhetoric is a “craftsmanof persuasion”( peithous deˆmiourgos) and thatits power is “ toproduce persuasionin the mind ( psycheˆ) of the audience”(453a). Thus, for Aristotle and Plato, and even (it appears) forGorgias, and by extensionfor the Sophistsin general, rhetoricis the artof persuading others,especially largegroups of people in the lawcourts or political forums. Onthe otherhand, given Plato’s well knownhostility to the Sophistsand to rhetoric in general, we maylegitimately wonder whether he isaccurately representing Gorgias’s views.So we must alsoexamine whatGorgias says in hisown words. He doesnot use the word“ rhetoric”( rhe ˆtorikeˆ)—indeed, noone doesbefore the fourth century (or,tobe moreprecise, the word rheˆtorikeˆ doesnot occur in anysurviving text before the fourthcentury andmost likely wasnot coined until then). 3 ButGorgias does include afamousdiscussion of logos (“word, speech, argument”) in his Encomium to Helen . Here we nd thatthe power of logos,which overwhelmed anypersonal will Helen mayhave had, comes directly from its association with persuasion,which isadded to logos (13).The persuasivenessof logos is alsolinked tomagic,which enchantsand persuades (10), to falsehood (11),to compulsion(12), to pleasure which isachieved throughskill (techneˆ),notthrough truth (13), to belief (13),and nally todrugs(14). In otherwords, Gorgias portrays logos asusing anarrayof toolsto persuade othersto do its bidding, andthe view thatrhetoric, or at least logos,isthe artof persuasionseems to be conrmed even by Gorgias’s ownwords. Since thisis the only sophisticdiscussion of logos thatsurvives, it iscommonto infer fromit that for the Sophistsin general, asforPlato andAristotle, rhetoric was primarily concerned withpersuasion. If further conrmation is needed, itcan be found in the widely acceptedtradition that rhetoric was invented by Coraxand Tisias afterthe overthrowof the tyrannyin Syracuse in 467,when the riseof democraticinstitutions including the assemblyand especially the lawcourts made it important to be able tospeak well—that is,to be able topersuade jurorsand assemblymen to accept one’ s arguments.T omeet thisneed Coraxand Tisias invented the art of rhetoric,wrote the rsthandbook or techneˆ onthe subject, and 3 See EdwardSchiappa, “ Did Plato Coin Rheˆtorikeˆ?”, American Journal of Philology 111(1990)pp. 457–70; Thomas Cole, TheOrigins of Rhetoricin Ancient Greece (Baltimore: JohnsHopkins University Press, 1991). This content downloaded from 147.52.233.137 on Tue, 4 Mar 2014 06:46:40 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Did the Sophists Aim toPersuade? 277 hadsuccessful careers teaching rhetoric to those seeking justice in courtor aspiring to political careers. And following their example the Sophistsbecame richand famous by teachingothers how to speak persuasively.In otherwords, not only wasrhetoric the art of persuasionfrom its very beginning but itcame into existence in responseto the need tospeak persuasively,andthe Sophists,teachers ofrhetoric, continued toserve thisneed. Thisaccount of sophistic rhetoric as the artof persuasionis ac- cepted, asSchiappa hasrecently noted,by virtuallyall scholars since Blass,more than a century ago. 4 And even recent scholarslike Cole, Poulakosand Swearingen, whoapproach sophistic rhetoric from new perspectives thatdownplay its connection to persuasion, have not di- rectlyquestioned the connectionbetween rhetoricand persuasion. 5 Explicitly orimplicitly mostscholars agree thatfor the Sophists,to speak well meantto speak persuasively andto teachrhetoric was to teachthe artof persuasion.Scholarly consensus is always comforting, but (asthe readermay suspect) my aimin thispaper isnot to reafrm the consensusbut ratherto reconsiderthe whole issue andask, did the Sophistsreally aimto persuade? The answer,Iwill suggest,is thatpersuasion was only one goalof sophistic logoi,andnot the most important.I will begin by consideringGorgias’ s Helen; I will then setthis work in the contextof sophistic Antilogiai,andwill conclude witha brief lookat whatother Sophists say about persuasion. Helen hasattracted considerable scholarly attention in recent years,especially since CharlesSegal’ s groundbreaking studyalmost fortyyears ago. 6 Accordingto Segal, “the Helen expressesa view of literatureand oratory which touchesclosely Gorgias’ s ownpractice andprobably hisown beliefs. Hence the speech mayeven have 4 EdwardSchiappa, TheBeginnings of RhetoricalTheory in Classical Greece (New Haven:Y ale University Press, 1999);cf. Friedrich Blass, Die attischeBeredsamkeit , vol. I, Von Gorgias biszu Lysias (Leipzig:Strauss & Cramer,1887). 5 Cole, Originsof Rhetoric ;JohnPoulakos, SophisticalRhetoric in Classical Greece (Columbia,SC: University of SouthCarolina Press, 1995);C. JanSwearingen, Rhetoric andIrony: Western Literacyand Western Lies (New York:Oxford University Press, 1991). Amore direct challenge to the role of persuasion is posed byJames Porter, “The Seductions of Gorgias”, Classical Antiquity 12(1993) pp. 267–99), though his picture of Gorgiasas “ seducing”is quite different frommine. 6 CharlesP .Segal,“ Gorgiasand the Psychologyof the Logos”, Harvard Studiesin Classical Philology 66(1962)pp. 99–155. The most scholarly edition of Helen is Thomas Buccheim ed., Gorgias vonLeontinoi: Reden, Fragmente undT estimonien (Hamburg:Felix Meiner, 1989),but MacDowell’s text, translationand commentary are ne forthe purpose of this paper (Douglas M.MacDowell ed., Gorgias, Encomiumof Helen (Bristol: Bristol Classical Press, 1982)). This content downloaded from 147.52.233.137 on Tue, 4 Mar 2014 06:46:40 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 278 R H E T O R I C A served asa kind of formalprofession of the aimsand methods of hisart” (Segal, p. 102).Segal’ s conclusion,that the descriptionof logos in Helen represents Gorgias’s ownview of logos,isnow widely accepted.But is it correct?
Recommended publications
  • An Athenian Law on Silver Coinage
    AN ATHENIAN LAW ON SILVER COINAGE (PLATES 25-27) AMONG the many remarkableepigraphic discoveries of the recent Agora Excava- -tions one of the most important for students of Greek numismatics and Athenian political institutions is the complete marble stele discussed in this paper. Valuable new evidence about the Nomothetai, the circulation of silver coins in Athens and Peirai- eus, and about a hitherto little-known official, the Dokimastes, is preserved in consider- able detail in this document. In addition to specific information about ancient counterfeit coins there are also no fewer than ten different public officials mentioned in this text which is fifty-six lines long and well-enough preserved to require very little restoration.' Agora Inventory I 7180 (Pls. 25-27). Complete stele of fine-crystaled, white marble mended from two pieces; crowned by a molding 0.082 m. in height consisting of an ovolo topped by a plain taenia. Back rough picked; sides and bottom 0.08 m. of front dressed with toothed chisel. Stele has a slight vertical taper. Found on August 4, 1970 built into the west wall of the Great Drain in front of the Royal Stoa, J 4,5. Height, 1.268 m.; width, at base, 0.457 m., below molding, 0.428 m.; thickness, 0.126 m. Height of letters, lines 1-2, 0.009 m., lines 3-56, 0.005-0.006 m. a. 37514 a. NON- 2TOIX. c'80oE T-roZ vojLo00ETatLS, Em' 'I7ro[8aLavros] dapXovTos: NLKO/-V EL7TEVW TO apyvpLov 8eXErOat TO ATTKoV 0oT[....... ]- TOIX. 39 at apyvpoy KatLEXrL TOV&8tlocr'toy xa[paKT7jpa.
    [Show full text]
  • Tokyo University Seminar
    Philosophy Seminar at Komaba, 5 February, 2008 Who is the Sophist? Problems and Approaches Noburu Notomi (Keio University) "Sophist" is the name of professional intellectuals and teachers active in ancient Greece (and Rome). I have discussed in my book Who is the Sophist? (Jinbun-shoin, 2006) whether, and how, the sophist matters to philosophy. Aren't the sophists historical figures who no longer existed after the Middle Ages? I argue that confronting the sophist is an essential way of doing philosophy, and also that the sophist challenges philosophy in an essential way. The tension between the two has been lying at the very basis of Western philosophy. I demonstrate the significance of the sophist as a philosophical problem in the contemporary world. In the seminar I will introduce some of the main topics treated in my book. Those interested in this issue might also like to read my The Unity of Plato's Sophist: Between the Sophist and the Philosopher (Cambridge University Press, 1999; Japanese translation, Nagoya University Press, 2002). In the Who is the Sophist?, I translate and analyze three works of Gorgias and one treatise of Alcidamas. For the European translations of these sophists, see T. Buchheim, Gorgias von Leontini, Reden, Fragmente und Testimonien, Felix Meiner, 1989 (Greek Text, German translation, and commentary); J. V. Muir, Alcidamas: The Works & Fragments, Bristol Classical Press, 2001 (Greek Text, English translation, and commentary). Table of Contents: Who is the Sophist? Introduction: Challenging the sophist (1)
    [Show full text]
  • THE MYTH of ORPHEUS and EURYDICE in WESTERN LITERATURE by MARK OWEN LEE, C.S.B. B.A., University of Toronto, 1953 M.A., Universi
    THE MYTH OF ORPHEUS AND EURYDICE IN WESTERN LITERATURE by MARK OWEN LEE, C.S.B. B.A., University of Toronto, 1953 M.A., University of Toronto, 1957 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OP PHILOSOPHY in the Department of- Classics We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA September, i960 In presenting this thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study. I further agree that permission for extensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the Head of my Department or by his representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. Department of The University of British Columbia Vancouver 8, Canada. ©he Pttttrerstt^ of ^riitsl} (Eolimtbta FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES PROGRAMME OF THE FINAL ORAL EXAMINATION FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY of MARK OWEN LEE, C.S.B. B.A. University of Toronto, 1953 M.A. University of Toronto, 1957 S.T.B. University of Toronto, 1957 WEDNESDAY, SEPTEMBER 21, 1960 AT 3:00 P.M. IN ROOM 256, BUCHANAN BUILDING COMMITTEE IN CHARGE DEAN G. M. SHRUM, Chairman M. F. MCGREGOR G. B. RIDDEHOUGH W. L. GRANT P. C. F. GUTHRIE C. W. J. ELIOT B. SAVERY G. W. MARQUIS A. E. BIRNEY External Examiner: T. G. ROSENMEYER University of Washington THE MYTH OF ORPHEUS AND EURYDICE IN WESTERN Myth sometimes evolves art-forms in which to express itself: LITERATURE Politian's Orfeo, a secular subject, which used music to tell its story, is seen to be the forerunner of the opera (Chapter IV); later, the ABSTRACT myth of Orpheus and Eurydice evolved the opera, in the works of the Florentine Camerata and Monteverdi, and served as the pattern This dissertion traces the course of the myth of Orpheus and for its reform, in Gluck (Chapter V).
    [Show full text]
  • Out of Style: Reanimating Stylistic Study in Composition and Rhetoric
    Utah State University DigitalCommons@USU All USU Press Publications USU Press 2008 Out of Style: Reanimating Stylistic Study in Composition and Rhetoric Paul Butler Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/usupress_pubs Part of the Rhetoric and Composition Commons Recommended Citation Butler, Paul, "Out of Style: Reanimating Stylistic Study in Composition and Rhetoric" (2008). All USU Press Publications. 162. https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/usupress_pubs/162 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the USU Press at DigitalCommons@USU. It has been accepted for inclusion in All USU Press Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@USU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 6679-0_OutOfStyle.ai79-0_OutOfStyle.ai 5/19/085/19/08 2:38:162:38:16 PMPM C M Y CM MY CY CMY K OUT OF STYLE OUT OF STYLE Reanimating Stylistic Study in Composition and Rhetoric PAUL BUTLER UTAH STATE UNIVERSITY PRESS Logan, Utah 2008 Utah State University Press Logan, Utah 84322–7800 © 2008 Utah State University Press All rights reserved. ISBN: 978-0-87421-679-0 (paper) ISBN: 978-0-87421-680-6 (e-book) “Style in the Diaspora of Composition Studies” copyright 2007 from Rhetoric Review by Paul Butler. Reproduced by permission of Taylor & Francis Group, LLC., http:// www. informaworld.com. Manufactured in the United States of America. Cover design by Barbara Yale-Read. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Library of Congress Cataloging-in- Publication Data Butler, Paul, Out of style : reanimating stylistic study in composition and rhetoric / Paul Butler. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index.
    [Show full text]
  • Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: the Medium As
    Isocrates & Europe - 1 Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: The Medium as Message I. Introduction: Overview The idea that Isocrates helped create the concept of transnationalism that fostered Europe both as an idea and as an eventual political union is common fare in rhetorical studies. De Romilly (1992) writes that “Isocrates was perhaps the first in antiquity to focus his political theories on the idea of Europe” (p. 2). Isocrates anticipated “the idea of Europe” (Hariman, 2004, p. 231) and used the words Europen and Europes 13 times in his essays. But, to date, critical exploration of Isocrates’ role in developing the idea of Europe has primarily dealt with the content of his works – with his eloquent and relentless focus on panhellenism and the related conflict between Europe and Asia. This paper, however, will focus on medium rather than message. It will focus on Isocrates’ pioneering use of a new medium – written documents/syggrammata – and the role that the new rhetorical medium played in forming Europe. The most famous passage in the Isocratean canon, the so-called Hymn to Logos (Jaeger, 1944/1971), which first appeared in Nicocles (5-9) and was repeated in Antidosis (253-257), holds that speech/logos is a civic and political unifier, by means of which “we have come together and founded cities and made laws and invented arts” (Nicocles 6). Yet before Isocrates, who was “the first individual who could be termed a ‘writer’ in the modern sense of the term” (Lentz, 1989), logos and its community-building powers Isocrates & Europe - 2 traveled primarily orally: Cities, alliances, arts, and laws were built through face-to-face communication.
    [Show full text]
  • Homer and Hesiod
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Departmental Papers (Classical Studies) Classical Studies at Penn 1-1-1997 Homer and Hesiod Ralph M. Rosen University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Rosen, R. M. (1997). Homer and Hesiod. Retrieved from https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers/7 Postprint version. Published in A New Companion to Homer, edited by Barry Powell and Ian Morris, Mnemosyne: Bibliotheca classica Batava, Supplementum 163 (New York: Brill, 1997), pages 463-488. The author has asserted his right to include this material in ScholarlyCommons@Penn. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers/7 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Homer and Hesiod Abstract One of the most frustrating aspects of Homeric studies is that so little literary material outside the Homeric corpus itself survives to enhance our understanding of the cultural landscape of the period. Recent scholarship suggests that a large and diverse poetic tradition lay behind the figure we refer to as "Homer," but little of it survives. Indeed we have little continuous written Greek for another century. The one exception is Hesiod, who composed two extant poems, the Theogony and Works and Days, and possibly several others, including the Shield of Heracles and the Catalogue of Women. As we shall see, while Hesiodic poetry was not occupied specifically with heroic themes, it was part of the same formal tradition of epic, sharing with Homer key metrical, dialectal, and dictional features.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prohibition of Just and Unjust Homicide in Antiphon's Tetralogies Michael Gagarin
    The Prohibition of Just and Unjust Homicide in Antiphon's "Tetralogies" Gagarin, Michael Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Jan 1, 1978; 19, 4; Periodicals Archive Online pg. 291 The Prohibition of Just and Unjust Homicide in Antiphon's Tetralogies Michael Gagarin THE END of the last century serious doubts were raised, A especially by Dittenberger,l concerning the legal accuracy of the Tetralogies ascribed to Antiphon. A rebuttal by Lipsius2 explained several of the alleged discrepancies between the Tetralogies and Athenian law, but in his reply to Lipsius Dittenberger3 stuck firmly to one point above all: that the prohibition /L~7"€ oLKaLwc /L~7"€ &OLKWC &1TOK'TELVELV, which is quoted four times in the Second and Third Tetralogies (3.2.9,4 3.3.7, 4.2.3, 4.4.8), is clearly inconsistent with Athenian homicide law, which from the time of Drakon recognized that certain cases of homicide were lawful and went unpunished.s Following Dittenberger some critics6 have accepted this inconsistency and taken it as part of the evidence for the 'sophistic', non-legal and non-Antiphontic nature of the Tetralogies. Others have sought to ex­ plain the inconsistency and to reconcile the prohibition of just and unjust homicide with Athenian law. PaolF argued that as the city magistrates gradually assumed the legal tasks originally left to self-help, individuals were no longer allowed to kill a criminal themselves except in their own homes but had to bring him (by the process of apagoge) to a magistrate for execu­ tion. This change, he argues, was reflected in the law prohibiting all homicides, even those previously considered just.
    [Show full text]
  • Certamen Homeri Et Hesiodi: Introduction, Critical Edition and Commentary
    Durham E-Theses Certamen Homeri et Hesiodi: Introduction, Critical Edition and Commentary BASSINO, PAOLA How to cite: BASSINO, PAOLA (2013) Certamen Homeri et Hesiodi: Introduction, Critical Edition and Commentary, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/8448/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk Certamen Homeri et Hesiodi: Introduction, Critical Edition and Commentary Paola Bassino Ustinov College This thesis is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics and Ancient History University of Durham 2013 Abstract Paola Bassino Certamen Homeri et Hesiodi: Introduction, Critical Edition and Commentary. This dissertation provides an up-to-date introduction to the Certamen Homeri et Hesiodi, a critical edition of the text, and the first commentary in English on it. The Certamen is an anonymous work composed around the second century AD.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle-Rhetoric.Pdf
    Rhetoric Aristotle (Translated by W. Rhys Roberts) Book I 1 Rhetoric is the counterpart of Dialectic. Both alike are con- cerned with such things as come, more or less, within the general ken of all men and belong to no definite science. Accordingly all men make use, more or less, of both; for to a certain extent all men attempt to discuss statements and to maintain them, to defend themselves and to attack others. Ordinary people do this either at random or through practice and from acquired habit. Both ways being possible, the subject can plainly be handled systematically, for it is possible to inquire the reason why some speakers succeed through practice and others spontaneously; and every one will at once agree that such an inquiry is the function of an art. Now, the framers of the current treatises on rhetoric have cons- tructed but a small portion of that art. The modes of persuasion are the only true constituents of the art: everything else is me- rely accessory. These writers, however, say nothing about en- thymemes, which are the substance of rhetorical persuasion, but deal mainly with non-essentials. The arousing of prejudice, pity, anger, and similar emotions has nothing to do with the essential facts, but is merely a personal appeal to the man who is judging the case. Consequently if the rules for trials which are now laid down some states-especially in well-governed states-were applied everywhere, such people would have nothing to say. All men, no doubt, think that the laws should prescribe such rules, but some, as in the court of Areopagus, give practical effect to their thoughts 4 Aristotle and forbid talk about non-essentials.
    [Show full text]
  • Antiphon the Sophist the Fragments
    ANTIPHON THE SOPHIST THE FRAGMENTS EDITED WITH INTRODUCTION, TRANSLATION, AND COMMENTARY BY GERARD J. PENDRICK published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb22ru,UK 40 West 20th Street, New York ny 10011-4211, USA 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia Ruiz de AlarcoÂn 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 2002 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2002 Reprinted 2003 Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeset in Baskerville and New Hellenic Greek [ao] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Antiphon, of Athens. The fragments / Antiphon the Sophist ; edited with introduction, translation and commentary by Gerard J. Pendrick. p. cm. Ð DCambridge classical texts and commentaries ; 39) Includes bibliographical references and indexes. isbn 0521651611 1. Sophists DGreek philosophy) 2. Philosophy, Ancient. i.Title: Antiphon the Sophist. ii. Pendrick, Gerard J. iii. Title. iv. Series. pa3870. a22001 1830.1Ðdc21 2001035690 isbn 0521651611 CONTENTS Preface page ix INTRODUCTION 1 I The identity of Antiphon 1 II Division of works 26 III On Truth 32 IV On Concord 39 V Politicus 47 VI Dream-book 49 VII Antiphon's thought in its ®fth-century context 53 TEXTS AND TRANSLATIONS 69 COMMENTARY 225 WORKS CITED 431 INDEXES 458 vii INTRODUCTION I THE IDENTITY OF ANTIPHON Among the plethora of Antiphons known from the later ®fth andthe fourth centuries bc, particularly at Athens, are several who have often been confused, in antiquity as well as in modern scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • Appropriation of Language Some Value-Terms in the Oratory of Aeschines
    APPROPRIATION OF LANGUAGE SOME VALUE-TERMS IN THE ORATORY OF AESCHINES EÖTVÖS LORÁND UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF ANCIENT HISTORY H-1088 Budapest, Múzeum krt. 4/A SERIES ISTVÁN HAHN LECTURERS (IHL) Edited by GYÖRGY NÉMETH Vol. VI Redaction ÁDÁM SZABÓ ISSN 2061-7348 2019 Dániel Bajnok APPROPRIATION OF LANGUAGE SOME VALUE-TERMS IN THE ORATORY OF AESCHINES Budapest Cover plan ÁDÁM SZABÓ IHL VI Supported by NON OMNIS MORIAR Foundation ISBN 978-963-489-108-6 © Publisher; © Author Print: Kódex Könyvgyártó Kft. Budapest Contents Foreword to proceeding IHL............................7 1. Introduction..................................................9 2. Research methods......................................13 2.1. Calibrating corpora.............................14 2.2. Frequency of terms.............................18 2.3. Defining key terms..............................23 3. Value-terms concerning decency................30 3.1. Decency for self-positioning...............35 3.2. Decency as political ideal...................39 3.3. Lack of decency: deterrent examples..........................................42 4. Comments on further value-terms..............50 4.1. Courage..............................................50 4.2. Education............................................51 4.3. Democracy.........................................53 4.4. Law.....................................................54 5. Conclusion..................................................57 5 Bibliography...................................................59 Abbreviations.............................................59
    [Show full text]
  • The Speech Against Leocrates. Edited by A. Petrie
    LYCURGUS The Speech against Leocrates Pitt Press Series LYCURGUS THE SPEECH AGAINST LEOCRATES CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS C. F. CLAY, MANAGER LONDON : FETTER LANE, E. C. 4 NEW YORK t THE MACMILLAN CO. BOMBAY ) CALCUTTA [ MACMILLAN AND CO., LTD. MADRAS ) TORONTO : THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, LTD. TOKYO ! MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA ALL RIGHTS RESERVED LYCURGUS THE SPEECH AGAINST LEOCRATES EDITED BY A. PETRIE, M.A. PROFESSOR OF CLASSICS, NATAL UNIVERSITY COLLEGE s. (UNIVERSITY OF AFRICA) ; FORMERLY LECTURER IN GREEK IN THE UNIVERSITY OF ABERDEEN ; SOMETIME SCHOLAR OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE CAMBRIDGE AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 1922 U PRINTED IN ENGLAND PREFACE Leocrates of Lycurgus has remained, in THEEngland, in comparative obscurity, not having 1 attracted an editor since John Taylor edited it at Cambridge, along with the Midias of Demosthenes, in 1743. Yet the speech is by no means without its merits. It forms, in many ways, an excellent introduction to Attic oratory for younger students. It is easier than Demosthenes, and there is no complex political situation to expound: the issue is simple and direct. And it has a greater variety of interest than either Demosthenes or Lysias. Its very fault of diffuseness, from the purely forensic standpoint, becomes, from an educative point of view, its great virtue. Lycurgus' excursions into ancient history, legend, and the poets, provide, in Livy's phrase, so many deverticula amoena where the student finds refreshment with instruction. The text of the present edition will be found to adhere, in the main, to that of Blass, whose critical commentary I have supplemented with those of Scheibe, Rehdantz and Thalheim.
    [Show full text]