Model Theory and the Cardinal Numbers P and T

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Model Theory and the Cardinal Numbers P and T COMMENTARY COMMENTARY Model theory and the cardinal numbers p and t Justin Tatch Moore1 fi Cornell University, Ithaca, NY 14853 Model Theory and Classi cation Model theory is a different branch of math- ematical logic that concerns itself with the Modern mathematical logic is a multifaceted Just as new models of geometry were dis- semantics and syntactics of abstract mathe- fi subject, which concerns itself with the covered and explored by Bolyani, Gauss, and matical structures, such as the eld of com- C; + ; · strengths and limitations of formal proofs Lobachevsky in the 19th century, modern set plex numbers ð Þ and linear orders Q;< and algorithms and the relationship between theory concerns itself with building and un- such as ð Þ. One of the results that ’ language and mathematical structure. Mod- derstanding models of the axioms of math- modernized the subject was Morley scate- ern mathematical logic also addresses foun- ematics. If the continuum hypothesis fails, goricity theorem (6). A fundamental result in dational issues that arise in mathematics. then there are orders of infinity that lie linear algebra is that any two vector spaces fi This commentary summarizes the ground- somewhere between ℵ1—the smallest un- that have the same dimension and same eld ℵ breaking results of Malliaris and Shelah countable cardinal—and 2 0 . Two examples of scalars are isomorphic. If the field of sca- (1), recently published in PNAS (2), relating are p and t.Thecardinalp is the minimum lars is the rational numbers, then the di- two branches of logic: model theory and cardinality of a collection F of infinite subsets mension of an uncountable vector space is set theory. the same as its cardinality. Thus, any two Malliaris and Shelah vector spaces over Q, which have the same fi Higher Orders of In nity outline a proof that uncountable cardinality, are in fact iso- At the end of the 19th century, Cantor made p t— morphic. The categoricity theorem is a vast the remarkable discovery that it was possible = a very rare generalization of this; it asserts that, for any to develop theory of the size or cardinality of T κ λ fi X Y instance of a provable theory and uncountable cardinals and , an in nite set. Two sets, and ,havethe if any two models of T of cardinality κ are same cardinality if there is a bijective corre- equality among orders fi isomorphic, then any two models of cardi- spondence between them: that is, there is a of in nity. nality λ are isomorphic. The proof proceeds pairing between the elements of X and Y N fi by showing that, even in this generality, so that each element of one corresponds of ,allofwhose nite intersections are theories that satisfy the hypothesis of the uniquely to an element of the other. Sets that fi fi in nite, such that there is no single in nite theorem admit an abstract notion of a basis, are either finite or have the same cardinality A⊆N , such that every element of F contains much as in the setting of vector spaces. as the natural numbers N = f0; 1; 2; ...g are A fi t except for a nite error. The cardinal is This rather extreme characteristic of a said to be countable; otherwise, they are un- fi fi de ned similarly, except one only quanti es theory is by no means typical. For example, countable. Cantor demonstrated that the ra- over families F which are totally ordered by ​ both R and Q∪ ð0; 1Þ are dense linear orders tional numbers are countable but the real containment modulo a finite error. Although of the same cardinality, but they are not numbers are uncountable: their cardinalities p ≤ t is immediate from the definitions, it ℵ isomorphic: every interval in R is uncount- are commonly denoted ℵ and 2 0 , respec- has been an open problem for over 50 years 0 able, whereas the interval of points between 2 tively. The distinction between the countable whether p = t is provable from the axioms ​ and 3 in Q∪ ð0; 1Þ is countable. Theories that and the uncountable is very important in of mathematics or whether, like the contin- are close to that of the algebraic structure mathematics. For example, the existence of uum hypothesis, it is undecidable based on C; + ; · a countable set of points in a manifold or the axioms. These cardinals, and p in par- ð Þ are generally regarded in model theory as being tame, whereas those similar Hilbert space, which can be used to arbi- ticular, arise in the study of more exotic to- R;< trarily approximate all other points, is cru- pological spaces in topology and analysis. For to the dense linear order ð Þ are regarded cially used in many places throughout mathe- p as being wild. In the 1970s, Shelah initiated example, is the cardinality of the smallest fi matical analysis. number of nowhere dense subsets which his classi cation program in model theory in Set theory—one of the four main branches are needed to cover a separable compact an attempt to separate the tame from the wild of modern logic—concerns itself with foun- topological space. andtostratifywhatlayinbetween(7). dational issues relating to uncountable sets. Curiously, it has long been known that if One method of stratifying theories is Keisler’s order (8), which measures how One of the earliest, and surely the most fa- p = ℵ1, the smallest possible value it can take, mous, problems in set theory asked whether then p = t.Thus,ifp < t is true in a model of easily the models of the theory become sat- ℵ there was a cardinal number that was strictly mathematics, then necessarily 2 0 is at least urated by taking ultrapowers. The ultrapower ℵ0 between ℵ0 and 2 ; the assertion that no ℵ3, the third uncountable cardinal. This is construction is a useful tool by which a such intermediate cardinal exists is known as interestingbecausewehaveamuchmore the “continuum hypothesis.” In comple- limited understanding of models of math- ℵ0 Author contributions: J.T.M. wrote the paper. mentary results, Gödel (3) and Cohen (4, 5) ematics in which 2 > ℵ2 than those in ℵ0 The author declares no conflict of interest. demonstrated that the continuum hypothesis which 2 ≤ ℵ2. Still, it was widely believed is neither provable nor refutable based on the that p < t should consistent with the axioms See companion article 10.107/pnas.1306114110. standard axioms of mathematics. of mathematics. 1E-mail: [email protected]. www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1310920110 PNAS Early Edition | 1of2 Downloaded by guest on September 28, 2021 structure is enlarged while preserving its decades that followed, very little progress was this same analysis, Malliaris and Shelah theory. The logical properties of the ultra- made in this direction. show that even the weak presence of a de- power are obtained by integration via a cer- finable linear ordering in the structure— Recent Developments tain binary valued measure, known as an specifically Shelah’spropertySOP—exactly fi In a watershed moment in both model theory 3 ultra lter. Such enlargements have a greater characterize the maximal class of theories in and set theory, Malliaris and Shelah solved tendency to contain solutions to large sys- — Keisler’sorder.Thisfinding suggests a wealth tems of logical equations. Those structures both of these central and seemingly un- related problems—by realizing they are in of theories of intermediate complexity. The that have solutions to any consistent system analysis is also unique in proving that there of logical equations, which are smaller than fact closely connected. In their article in are theories more complex than the stable the structure itself, are said to be saturated. PNAS (2), Malliaris and Shelah outline a p = t— theories but less complex than the maximal The tamer the theory, the more likely its proof that a very rare instance of a fi — class in Keisler’s order, and opens the door ultrapowers are to be saturated. provable equality among orders of in nity fi It was long known that the theories of by a tour de force analysis of de nability for new interactions between set theory and fi ðC; + ; · Þ and ðR;<Þ provided examples at in ultraproducts of nite linear orders. Using model theory. the opposite ends of this spectrum, and that thepresenceofadefinable ordering in the structure was an indication of high com- 1 Malliaris M, Shelah S (2012) Cofinality spectrum problems in 5 Cohen PJ (1964) The independence of the continuum hypothesis. plexity. Shelah also characterized, in model model theory, set theory, and general topology. arxiv:math.LO/ II. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 51(1):105–110. 1208.5424. 6 Morley M (1965) Categoricity in power. Trans Am Math Soc theoretic terms, the smallest two classes in 2 Malliaris M, Shelah S (2013) General topology meets model theory, 114:514–538. Keisler’s order: these classes together are the on p and t. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA, 10.107/pnas.1306114110. 7 Shelah S (1978) Classification theory and the number of nonisomorphic “stable theories” (4). No model theoretic 3 Gödel K (1940) The consistency of the continuum hypothesis. Annals models. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics,vol of Mathematics Studies, no. 3 (Princeton Univ Press, Princeton, NJ). 92. (North-Holland Publishing, Amsterdam, The Netherlands). characterization was known, however, of the 4 Cohen PJ (1963) The independence of the continuum hypothesis. 8 Keisler J (1967) Ultraproducts which are not saturated. J Symbolic maximal theories in Keisler’s order. Over the Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 50(6):1143–1148.
Recommended publications
  • Georg Cantor English Version
    GEORG CANTOR (March 3, 1845 – January 6, 1918) by HEINZ KLAUS STRICK, Germany There is hardly another mathematician whose reputation among his contemporary colleagues reflected such a wide disparity of opinion: for some, GEORG FERDINAND LUDWIG PHILIPP CANTOR was a corruptor of youth (KRONECKER), while for others, he was an exceptionally gifted mathematical researcher (DAVID HILBERT 1925: Let no one be allowed to drive us from the paradise that CANTOR created for us.) GEORG CANTOR’s father was a successful merchant and stockbroker in St. Petersburg, where he lived with his family, which included six children, in the large German colony until he was forced by ill health to move to the milder climate of Germany. In Russia, GEORG was instructed by private tutors. He then attended secondary schools in Wiesbaden and Darmstadt. After he had completed his schooling with excellent grades, particularly in mathematics, his father acceded to his son’s request to pursue mathematical studies in Zurich. GEORG CANTOR could equally well have chosen a career as a violinist, in which case he would have continued the tradition of his two grandmothers, both of whom were active as respected professional musicians in St. Petersburg. When in 1863 his father died, CANTOR transferred to Berlin, where he attended lectures by KARL WEIERSTRASS, ERNST EDUARD KUMMER, and LEOPOLD KRONECKER. On completing his doctorate in 1867 with a dissertation on a topic in number theory, CANTOR did not obtain a permanent academic position. He taught for a while at a girls’ school and at an institution for training teachers, all the while working on his habilitation thesis, which led to a teaching position at the university in Halle.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis
    Mathematics As A Liberal Art Math 105 Fall 2015 Fowler 302 MWF 10:40am- 11:35am BY: 2015 Ron Buckmire http://sites.oxy.edu/ron/math/105/15/ Class 22: Monday October 26 Aleph One (@1) and All That The Continuum Hypothesis: Introducing @1 (Aleph One) We can show that the power set of the natural numbers has a cardinality greater than the the cardinality of the natural numbers. This result was proven in an 1891 paper by German mathematician Georg Cantor (1845-1918) who used something called a diagonalization argument in his proof. Using our formula for the cardinality of the power set, @0 jP(N)j = 2 = @1 The cardinality of the power set of the natural numbers is called @1. THEOREM Cantor's Power Set Theorem For any set S (finite or infinite), cardinality of the power set of S, i.e. P (S) is always strictly greater than the cardinality of S. Mathematically, this says that jP (S)j > jS THEOREM c > @0 The cardinality of the real numbers is greater than the cardinality of the natural numbers. DEFINITION: Uncountable An infinite set is said to be uncountable (or nondenumerable) if it has a cardinality that is greater than @0, i.e. it has more elements than the set of natural numbers. PROOF Let's use Cantor's diagonal process to show that the set of real numbers between 0 and 1 is uncountable. Math As A Liberal Art Class 22 Math 105 Spring 2015 THEOREM The Continuum Hypothesis, i.e. @1 =c The continuum hypothesis is that the cardinality of the continuum (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Relation to the Lusin Set
    THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS AND ITS RELATION TO THE LUSIN SET CLIVE CHANG Abstract. In this paper, we prove that the Continuum Hypothesis is equiv- alent to the existence of a subset of R called a Lusin set and the property that every subset of R with cardinality < c is of first category. Additionally, we note an interesting consequence of the measure of a Lusin set, specifically that it has measure zero. We introduce the concepts of ordinals and cardinals, as well as discuss some basic point-set topology. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Ordinals 2 3. Cardinals and Countability 2 4. The Continuum Hypothesis and Aleph Numbers 2 5. The Topology on R 3 6. Meagre (First Category) and Fσ Sets 3 7. The existence of a Lusin set, assuming CH 4 8. The Lebesque Measure on R 4 9. Additional Property of the Lusin set 4 10. Lemma: CH is equivalent to R being representable as an increasing chain of countable sets 5 11. The Converse: Proof of CH from the existence of a Lusin set and a property of R 6 12. Closing Comments 6 Acknowledgments 6 References 6 1. Introduction Throughout much of the early and middle twentieth century, the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) served as one of the premier problems in the foundations of math- ematical set theory, attracting the attention of countless famous mathematicians, most notably, G¨odel,Cantor, Cohen, and Hilbert. The conjecture first advanced by Cantor in 1877, makes a claim about the relationship between the cardinality of the continuum (R) and the cardinality of the natural numbers (N), in relation to infinite set hierarchy.
    [Show full text]
  • Aaboe, Asger Episodes from the Early History of Mathematics QA22 .A13 Abbott, Edwin Abbott Flatland: a Romance of Many Dimensions QA699 .A13 1953 Abbott, J
    James J. Gehrig Memorial Library _________Table of Contents_______________________________________________ Section I. Cover Page..............................................i Table of Contents......................................ii Biography of James Gehrig.............................iii Section II. - Library Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘A’...................1 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘B’...................3 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘C’...................7 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘D’..................10 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘E’..................13 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘F’..................14 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘G’..................16 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘H’..................18 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘I’..................22 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘J’..................23 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘K’..................24 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘L’..................27 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘M’..................29 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘N’..................33 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘O’..................34 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘P’..................35 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘Q’..................38 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘R’..................39 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘S’..................41 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘T’..................45 Author’s Last Name beginning with ‘U’..................47 Author’s Last Name beginning
    [Show full text]
  • 2.5. INFINITE SETS Now That We Have Covered the Basics of Elementary
    2.5. INFINITE SETS Now that we have covered the basics of elementary set theory in the previous sections, we are ready to turn to infinite sets and some more advanced concepts in this area. Shortly after Georg Cantor laid out the core principles of his new theory of sets in the late 19th century, his work led him to a trove of controversial and groundbreaking results related to the cardinalities of infinite sets. We will explore some of these extraordinary findings, including Cantor’s eponymous theorem on power sets and his famous diagonal argument, both of which imply that infinite sets come in different “sizes.” We also present one of the grandest problems in all of mathematics – the Continuum Hypothesis, which posits that the cardinality of the continuum (i.e. the set of all points on a line) is equal to that of the power set of the set of natural numbers. Lastly, we conclude this section with a foray into transfinite arithmetic, an extension of the usual arithmetic with finite numbers that includes operations with so-called aleph numbers – the cardinal numbers of infinite sets. If all of this sounds rather outlandish at the moment, don’t be surprised. The properties of infinite sets can be highly counter-intuitive and you may likely be in total disbelief after encountering some of Cantor’s theorems for the first time. Cantor himself said it best: after deducing that there are just as many points on the unit interval (0,1) as there are in n-dimensional space1, he wrote to his friend and colleague Richard Dedekind: “I see it, but I don’t believe it!” The Tricky Nature of Infinity Throughout the ages, human beings have always wondered about infinity and the notion of uncountability.
    [Show full text]
  • Set.1 the Power of the Continuum
    set.1 The Power of the Continuum sol:set:pow: In second-order logic we can quantify over subsets of the domain, but not over explanation sec sets of subsets of the domain. To do this directly, we would need third-order logic. For instance, if we wanted to state Cantor's Theorem that there is no injective function from the power set of a set to the set itself, we might try to formulate it as \for every set X, and every set P , if P is the power set of X, then not P ⪯ X". And to say that P is the power set of X would require formalizing that the elements of P are all and only the subsets of X, so something like 8Y (P (Y ) $ Y ⊆ X). The problem lies in P (Y ): that is not a formula of second-order logic, since only terms can be arguments to one-place relation variables like P . We can, however, simulate quantification over sets of sets, if the domain is large enough. The idea is to make use of the fact that two-place relations R relates elements of the domain to elements of the domain. Given such an R, we can collect all the elements to which some x is R-related: fy 2 jMj : R(x; y)g is the set \coded by" x. Conversely, if Z ⊆ }(jMj) is some collection of subsets of jMj, and there are at least as many elements of jMj as there are sets in Z, then there is also a relation R ⊆ jMj2 such that every Y 2 Z is coded by some x using R.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis
    Gauge Institute Journal, Volume 4, No 1, February 2008, H. Vic Dannon The Continuum Hypothesis H. Vic Dannon [email protected] September 2007 1 Gauge Institute Journal, Volume 4, No 1, February 2008, H. Vic Dannon Abstract We prove that the Continuum Hypothesis is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. Thus, the Negation of the Continuum Hypothesis, is equivalent to the Negation of the Axiom of Choice. The Non-Cantorian Axioms impose a Non-Cantorian definition of cardinality, that is different from Cantor’s cardinality imposed by the Cantorian Axioms. The Non-Cantorian Theory is the Zermelo-Fraenkel Theory with the Negation of the Axiom of Choice, and with the Negation of the Continuum Hypothesis. This Theory has distinct infinities. Keywords: Continuum Hypothesis, Axiom of Choice, Cardinal, Ordinal, Non-Cantorian, Countability, Infinity. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification 03E04; 03E10; 03E17; 03E50; 03E25; 03E35; 03E55. 2 Gauge Institute Journal, Volume 4, No 1, February 2008, H. Vic Dannon Contents Preface……………………………………………………...... 4 1 Hilbert’s 1st problem: The Continuum Hypothesis...6 Preface to 2…………………………………………………...14 2 Non-Cantorian Cardinal Numbers………………….......16 Preface to 3……………………………………………………38 3 Rationals Countability and Cantor’s Proof....................39 Preface to 4……………………………………………………50 4 Cantor’s Set and the Cardinality of the Reals............ 52 Preface to 5……………………………………………………75 5 Non-Cantorian Set Theory…………………………….....76 Preface to 6…………………………………………………....86 6 Cardinality, Measure, Category………………………....87 Preface to 7…………………………………………………...100 7 Continuum Hypothesis, Axiom of Choice, and Non- Cantorian Theory………….……………………………....101 3 Gauge Institute Journal, Volume 4, No 1, February 2008, H. Vic Dannon Preface The Continuum Hypothesis says that there is no infinity between the infinity of the natural numbers, and the infinity of the real numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis and Forcing
    The Continuum Hypothesis and Forcing Connor Lockhart December 2018 Abstract In this paper we introduce the problem of the continuum hypothesis and its solution via Cohen forcing. First, we introduce the basics of first order logic and standard ZFC set theory before elaborating on ordinals, cardinals and the forcing concept. The motivation of this paper is exposi- tory and should be approachable for anyone familiar with first order logic and set theory. Contents 1 Introduction and the Continuum Hypothesis 2 2 First Order Logic 2 2.1 Formal Languages . 2 2.2 Model Theory . 3 3 Set Theory and the ZFC axioms 6 3.1 List and Motivation of the Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms . 6 4 Ordinals and Cardinals 9 4.1 Orderings and Ordinal numbers . 9 4.2 Ordinal Arithmetic . 10 4.3 Cardinal Numbers . 11 5 Forcing 11 5.1 Tools of Forcing . 12 5.2 Useful Forcing Lemmas . 15 6 Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis 16 7 Acknowledgments 17 1 1 Introduction and the Continuum Hypothesis The continuum hypothesis (also referred to as CH) was first formulated in 1878 by Georg Cantor following his work on the foundations of set theory. Its for- mulation is often stated as There is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. This can also be reformulated to state that the successor cardinal to @0 is the cardinality of the reals. Such was suspected, but not proven, by Cantor and his contemporaries. The first major advance on the problem was presented by G¨odelin 1940 showing its consistency with ZFC axioms, and independence was finally shown in 1963 by Cohen.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis: How Big Is Infinity?
    The Continuum Hypothesis: how big is infinity? When a set theorist talks about the cardinality of a set, she means the size of the set. For finite sets, this is easy. The set f1; 15; 9; 12g has four elements, so has cardinality four. For infinite sets, such as N, the set of even numbers, or R, we have to be more careful. It turns out that infinity comes in different sizes, but the question of which infinite sets are \bigger" is a subtle one. To understand how infinite sets can have different cardinalities, we need a good definition of what it means for sets to be of the same size. Mathematicians say that two sets are the same size (or have the same cardinality) if you can match up each element of one of them with exactly one element of the other. Every element in each set needs a partner, and no element can have more than one partner from the other set. If you can write down a rule for doing this { a matching { then the sets have the same cardinality. On the contrary, if you can prove that there is no possible matching, then the cardinalities of the two sets must be different. For example, f1; 15; 9; 12g has the same cardinality as f1; 2; 3; 4g since you can pair 1 with 1, 2 with 15, 3 with 9 and 4 with 12 for a perfect match. What about the natural numbers and the even numbers? Here is a rule for a perfect matching: pair every natural number n with the even number 2n.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I, Volume 48, Number 6
    fea-woodin.qxp 6/6/01 4:39 PM Page 567 The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I W. Hugh Woodin Introduction of these axioms and related issues, see [Kanamori, Arguably the most famous formally unsolvable 1994]. problem of mathematics is Hilbert’s first prob- The independence of a proposition φ from the axioms of set theory is the arithmetic statement: lem: ZFC does not prove φ, and ZFC does not prove ¬φ. Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis: Suppose that Of course, if ZFC is inconsistent, then ZFC proves X ⊆ R is an uncountable set. Then there exists a bi- anything, so independence can be established only jection π : X → R. by assuming at the very least that ZFC is consis- tent. Sometimes, as we shall see, even stronger as- This problem belongs to an ever-increasing list sumptions are necessary. of problems known to be unsolvable from the The first result concerning the Continuum (usual) axioms of set theory. Hypothesis, CH, was obtained by Gödel. However, some of these problems have now Theorem (Gödel). Assume ZFC is consistent. Then been solved. But what does this actually mean? so is ZFC + CH. Could the Continuum Hypothesis be similarly solved? These questions are the subject of this ar- The modern era of set theory began with Cohen’s ticle, and the discussion will involve ingredients discovery of the method of forcing and his appli- from many of the current areas of set theoretical cation of this new method to show: investigation. Most notably, both Large Cardinal Theorem (Cohen). Assume ZFC is consistent. Then Axioms and Determinacy Axioms play central roles.
    [Show full text]
  • [Math.AG] 19 Sep 2002 Ceremony
    GEORG CANTOR AND HIS HERITAGE1 Yu. I. Manin God is no geometer, rather an unpredictable poet. (Geometers can be unpredictable poets, so there could be room for compromise.) V. Tasi´c[T], on the XIXth century romanticism Introduction Georg Cantor’s grand meta-narrative, Set Theory, created by him almost single- handedly in the span of about fifteen years, resembles a piece of high art more than a scientific theory. Using a slightly modernized language, basic results of set theory can be stated in a few lines. Consider the category of all sets with arbitrary maps as morphisms. Isomorphism classes of sets are called cardinals. Cardinals are well–ordered by the sub–object relation, and the cardinal of the set of all subsets of U is strictly larger than that of U (this is of course proved by the famous diagonal argument). This motivates introduction of another category, that of well ordered sets and monotone maps as morphisms. Isomorphism classes of these are called ordinals. They are well–ordered as well. The Continuum Hypothesis is a guess about the order structure of the initial segment of cardinals. Thus, exquisite minimalism of expressive means is used by Cantor to achieve a sublime goal: understanding infinity, or rather infinity of infinities. A built–in self– referentiality and the forceful extension of the domain of mathematical intuition (principles for building up new sets) add to this impression of combined artistic violence and self–restraint. Cantor himself would have furiously opposed this view. For him, the discovery of the hierarchy of infinities was a revelation of God–inspired Truth.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis
    The Continuum Hypothesis Peter Koellner September 12, 2011 The continuum hypotheses (CH) is one of the most central open problems in set theory, one that is important for both mathematical and philosophical reasons. The problem actually arose with the birth of set theory; indeed, in many respects it stimulated the birth of set theory. In 1874 Cantor had shown that there is a one-to-one correspondence between the natural numbers and the algebraic numbers. More surprisingly, he showed that there is no one- to-one correspondence between the natural numbers and the real numbers. Taking the existence of a one-to-one correspondence as a criterion for when two sets have the same size (something he certainly did by 1878), this result shows that there is more than one level of infinity and thus gave birth to the higher infinite in mathematics. Cantor immediately tried to determine whether there were any infinite sets of real numbers that were of intermediate size, that is, whether there was an infinite set of real numbers that could not be put into one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers and could not be put into one-to-one correspondence with the real numbers. The continuum hypothesis (under one formulation) is simply the statement that there is no such set of real numbers. It was through his attempt to prove this hypothesis that led Cantor do develop set theory into a sophisticated branch of mathematics.1 Despite his efforts Cantor could not resolve CH. The problem persisted and was considered so important by Hilbert that he placed it first on his famous list of open problems to be faced by the 20th century.
    [Show full text]