d-18 The Cech–Stoneˇ compactifications of N and R 213 d-18 The Cech–Stoneˇ Compactifications of N and R

c It is safe to say that among the Cech–Stoneˇ compactifica- The proof that βN has cardinality 2 employs an in- tions of individual spaces, that of the space N of natural dependent family, which we define on the countable set numbers is the most widely studied. A good candidate for {hn, si: n ∈ N, s ⊆ P(n)}. For every subset x of N put second place is βR. This article highlights some of the most Ix = {hn, si: x ∩ n ∈ s}. Now if F and G are finite dis- striking properties of both compactifications. T S joint subsets of P(N) then x∈F Ix \ y∈G Iy is non-empty – this is what independent means. Sending u ∈ βN to the P( ) ∗ point pu ∈ N 2, defined by pu(x) = 1 iff Ix ∈ u, gives us a 1. Description of βN and N c continuous map from βN onto 2. Thus the existence of an independent family of size c easily implies the well-known The space β (aka βω) appeared anonymously in [10] as an N fact that the Cantor cube c2 is separable; conversely, if D is example of a compact without non-trivial c dense in 2 then setting Iα = {d ∈ D: dα = 0} defines an converging sequences. The construction went as follows: for ∗ ∈ independent family on D. Any closed subset F of N such every x (0, 1) let 0.a1(x)a2(x)... an(x)... be its dyadic c expansion (favouring the one that ends in zeros). This gives that the restriction to F of the map onto 2 is irreducible is (homeomorphic with) the absolute of c2. If a point u of ∗ us a countable set A = {an(x): n ∈ N} of points in the Ty- N chonoff cube [0, 1](0,1). The closure of A is the required belongs to such an F then every compactification of the space ∪ {u} contains a copy of β . space. To see that this closure is indeed βN one checks N N Next we prove that ∗ is very non-separable by working that the map n 7→ an induces a of β N N < onto cl A. Indeed, it suffices to observe that whenever X is on the tree 2 N of finite sequences of zeros and ones. For ∈ N = { : ∈ } { : ∈ N } a coinfinite subset of N one has an(x) = 1 iff n ∈ X, where every x 2 let Ax x n n N . Then Ax x 2 is an P −n { ∗: ∈ N } x = ∈ 2 . almost disjoint family of cardinality c and so Ax x 2 n X ∗ The present-day description of β is as the Stone space of is a disjoint family of clopen sets in N . N ∗ the Boolean algebra P(N). Thus the underlying set of βN is We can use this family also to show that N is not ex- S the set of all ultrafilters on N with the family {X: X ⊆ N} as tremally disconnected. Let Q denote the points in N2 that a base for the open sets, where XS denotes the set of all ultra- are constant on a tail (these correspond to the endpoints of filters of which X is an element. The space βN is a separable the in [0, 1]) and let P = N2 \ Q. Then OQ = S ∗ S ∗ ∗ and extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space and x∈Q Ax and OP = x∈P Ax are disjoint open sets in N , c ∗ its cardinality is the maximum possible, i.e., 2 . yet cl OQ ∩ cl OP 6= ∅, for if A is such that Ax ⊆ A for Most of the research on βN concentrates on its remain- all x ∈ P then the Baire Category Theorem may be applied \ ∗ ∗ ∗ der βN N, which, as usual, is denoted N . By extension to find x ∈ Q with Ax ⊆ A. This example shows that is ∗ S N one writes X = X \ N for subsets X of N. The family not basically disconnected: O is an open F -set whose ∗ Q σ B = {X : X ⊆ N} is precisely the family of clopen sets closure is not open. ∗ ∗ ⊆ ∗ \ B of N . Because X Y iff X Y is finite the algebra is The algebra P(N)/fin has two countable (in)completeness isomorphic to the quotient algebra P(N)/fin of P(N) by the h i ∗ properties. The first states that when bn n is a decreasing ideal of finite sets – hence N is the Stone space of P(N)/fin. ∗ sequence of non-zero elements there is an x with bn > x > Much topological information about comes from knowl- ∗ N 0 for all n; in topological terms: nonempty Gδ-sets on N edge of the combinatorial properties of this algebra. In prac- ∗ have nonempty interiors and N has no isolated points. The P tice one works in (N) with all relations taken modulo fi- second property says that when hb i is as above and, in nite. We use, e.g., X ⊆∗ Y to denote that X \ Y is finite, n n addition, ha i is an increasing sequence with a < b for X ⊂∗ Y to denote that X ⊆∗ Y but not Y ⊆∗ X, and so on. n n n n all n there is an x with a < x < b for all n; in topological In this context the word ‘almost’ is mostly used in place of n n terms: disjoint open F -sets in ∗ have disjoint closures, ‘modulo finite’, thus ‘A and B are almost disjoint’ means σ N i.e., ∗ is an F-space. A ∩ B =∗ ∅. N We now turn to sets A and B where no interpolating x can be found, that is, we look for A and B such that W A0 < V B0 ∗ 0 <ω 0 <ω 2. Basic properties of N whenever A ∈ [A] and B ∈ [B] but for which there is no x with a 6 x 6 b for all a ∈ A and b ∈ B. The minimum ∗ Many results about N are found by constructing special cardinalities of sets like these are called cardinal character- families of subsets of N, although the actual work is often istics of the continuum and these cardinal numbers play an ∗ done on a suitable countable set different from N. important role in the study of βN and N .

Reprinted from Encyclopedia of General Topology K. P. Hart, J. Nagata and J. E. Vaughan, editors © 2004 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved 214 Section D: Fairly general properties

We have already seen such a situation with a countable A By the Axiom of Choice every almost disjoint family can ∗ ∗ and a B of cardinality c: the families {Ax }x∈Q and {N \ be extended to a Maximal Almost Disjoint family (a MAD ∗ ∗ S ∗ Ax }x∈P . However, this case, of a countably infinite A, is best family). If A is a MAD family then N \ {A : A ∈ A} is visualized on the countable set N × N. For n ∈ N put an = nowhere dense and every nowhere dense set is contained in ∗ ∗ (n×N) and for f ∈ NN put b f = {hm, ni: n > f (m)} ; then such a ‘canonical’ nowhere dense set. The minimum num- ∗ A = {an: n ∈ N} and B = {b f : f ∈ NN} are as required: if ber of nowhere dense sets whose union is dense in N is de- an < x for all n then one readily finds an f such that b f < x noted h and is called the weak Novák number. It is equal to (make sure {n} × [ f (n), ∞) ⊂ x). A pair like (A, B) above the minimum number of MAD families without a common is called an (unfillable) gap; gap, because, as in a Dedekind MAD refinement – in Boolean terms, it is the minimum κ gap, one has a < b whenever a ∈ A and b ∈ B, and unfillable for which P(N)/fin is not (κ, ∞)-distributive. because there is no x such that a 6 x 6 b for all a and b. Interestingly [1], one can find a sequence hAα: α < hi of Because unfillable gaps are the most interesting one drops MAD families, without common refinement and such that the adjective and speaks of gaps. (1) Aβ refines Aα whenever α < β; (2) if A ∈ Aα then {B ∈ N ∗ One does not need the full set N to create a gap; it Aα+1: B ⊆ A} has cardinality c; and (3) the family T = suffices to have a subset U such that for all g ∈ N there S ∗ N α Aα is dense in P(N)/fin – topologically: {A : A ∈ T } is f ∈ U such that {n: f (n) > g(n)} is infinite. The mini- is a π-base. This all implies that, with hindsight, there is an mum cardinality of such a set is denoted b. increasing sequence of closed nowhere dense sets of length h The properties of b and its bigger brother d are best ex- whose union is dense and that h is a regular cardinal; also ∗ plained using the relation < on NN where, in keeping note that T is a tree under the ordering ⊃∗. ∗ with the notation established above, f < g means that One can use such a tree, of minimal height, in induc- {n: f (n) g(n)} is finite. The definition of b given above ∗ > tive constructions, e.g., as in [2] to show that N is very identifies it as the minimum cardinality of an unbounded – ∗ non-extremally disconnected: every point is a c-point, which with respect to < – subset of NN; unbounded is not the means that one can find a family of c many disjoint open sets same as dominating (cofinal), the minimum cardinality of a each of which has the point in its closure. An important open dominating subset is denoted d and it is called the dominat- problem, at the time of writing, is whether this can be proved ing number. for every nowhere dense set, i.e., if for every nowhere dense × If one identifies N and N N, as above, then one recog- subset of ∗ one can find a family of c disjoint open sets = S ∗ N nizes d as the character of the closed set F cl n An and each of which has this set in its boundary – in short, whether b as the minimum number of clopen sets needed to create every nowhere dense set is a c-set. ∗ \ an open subset of N F whose closure meets F. In either The latter problem is equivalent to a purely combina- characterization of b the defining family can be taken to be torial one on MAD families: for every MAD family A well-ordered. the family I+(A) should have an almost disjoint refine- In case where A is finite one can simplify matters by let- ment. Here I(A) is the ideal generated by A and I+(A) = ting A = {0}. If B is an ultrafilter then there is no x with P( ) \ I(A); an almost disjoint refinement of a fam- 0 < x < b for all b ∈ B, hence there are filters whose only N ily B is an indexed almost disjoint family {A : B ∈ B} with lower bound is 0; the minimum cardinality of a base for such B A ⊆∗ B for all B. Another characterization asks for enough a filter is denoted p. Alternatively one can ask for chains B (on even one) MAD families of true cardinality c, i.e., if without positive lower bound: the minimum length of such a X ∈ I+(A) then X ∩ A 6=∗ ∅ for c many members of A. chain is denoted t – it is called the tower number. A defin- If the minimum size of a MAD family, denoted a, is equal ing family for the cardinal t can be used to create a sepa- to c then this is clearly the case, however there are various rable, normal, and sequentially compact spaces that is not models with a < c. compact. When we let A become uncountable we encounter two important types of objects of cardinality ℵ1: Hausdorff gaps and Lusin families. A Hausdorff gap [5] is a pair of se- 3. Homogeneity quences A = haα: α < ω1i and B = hbα: α < ω1i of ele- ments such that aα < aβ < bβ < bα whenever α < β but for Given that the algebra P(N)/fin is homogeneous it is some- ∗ which there is no x with aα < x < bα for all α.A Lusin what of a surprise to learn that the space N is not a homo- family [7] is an almost disjoint family A of cardinality ℵ1 geneous space, i.e., there are two points x and y for which ∗ such that no two uncountable and disjoint subfamilies of A there is no autohomeomorphism h of N with h(x) = y. can be separated, i.e., if B and C are disjoint and uncount- The first example of this phenomenon is from [9]: the ∗ ∗ ∗ able then there is no set X such that B ⊆ X and X ∩C = ∅ Continuum Hypothesis (CH) implies that N has P-points; for all B ∈ B and C ∈ C. One can parametrize the F-space a P-point is one for which the family of neighbourhoods is ∗ property: an Fκ -space is one in which disjoint open sets that closed under countable intersections. Clearly N has non-P- are the union of fewer than κ many closed sets have dis- points (as does every infinite ), so CH implies ∗ ∗ joint closures. The two families above show that N is not N is not homogeneous. To construct P-points one does not = an Fℵ2 -space. need the full force of CH, the equality d c suffices. d-18 The Cech–Stoneˇ compactifications of N and R 215

∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ In [4] one finds a proof of the non-homogeneity of N that P-set in N , viz. (N × {ω}) , that is homeomorphic to N ∗ avoids CH; it uses the Rudin–Frolík order on N , which itself. ∗ is defined by: u @ v iff there is an embedding f : βN → N Parovicenko’sˇ ‘other theorem’ states that every compact ∗ such that f (u) = v. If u @ v then there is no autohomeomor- space of weight ℵ1 (or less) is a continuous image of N , ∗ ∗ phism of N that maps u to v. This proof works to show that whence under CH the space N is a universal compactum of no compact F-space is homogeneous: if X is such a space weight c, in the mapping onto sense. ∗ then one can embed βN into it, no autohomeomorphism of X Virtually everything known about N under CH follows can map (the copy of) u to (the copy of) v. from Parovicenko’sˇ theorems. To give the flavour we show That this proof avoiding CH was really necessary be- that a compact zero-dimensional space can be embedded ∗ ∗ came clear when the consistency of “N has no P-points” into N if (and clearly only if) it is an F-space of weight c was proved. In [6] the P-point proof was salvaged partially: (or less). Indeed, let X be such a space and take a P-set A ∗ ∗ ∗ N has weak P-points, i.e., points that are not accumulation in N that is homeomorphic to N and a continuous onto points of any countable subset. map f : A → X. This induces an upper-semi-continuous de- ∗ ∗ Though not all points of N are P-points one may still composition of N whose quotient space, the adjunction try to cover ∗ by nowhere dense P-sets. Under CH this ∗ N space N ∪ f X, can be shown to have all the properties that ∗ ∗ cannot be done but it is consistent that it can be done. The characterize N , hence it is N and we have embedded X ∗ ∗ principle NCF implies that N is the union of a chain, of into N , even as a P-set. length d, of nowhere dense P-sets. The principle NCF (Near In the absence of CH very few of the consequences of Coherence of Filters) says that any two ultrafilters on N are Parovicenko’sˇ theorems remain true. The characterization ∗ nearly coherent, i.e., if u, v ∈ N then there is a finite-to- theorem is in fact equivalent to CH and for many concrete one f : → such that β f (u) = β f (v). ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ N N spaces, like N ×N , R , (N×(ω+1)) and the Stone space This in turn implies that the Rudin–Keisler order is of the measure algebra it is not a theorem of ZFC that they downward directed; we say u ≺ v if there is some f : → ∗ N N are continuous images of N . It is also consistent with ZFC = ∗ such that u f (v). This is a preorder on βN and a partial that all autohomeomorphisms of are trivial, i.e., induced ≺ ≺ N order on the types of βN: if u v and v u then there is by bijections between cofinite sets. This is a far cry from the a permutation of N that send u to v. The Rudin–Frolík and 2c autohomeomorphisms that we got from CH. It is also con- Rudin–Keisler orders are related: u v implies u ≺ v, so ∗ @ @ sistent that N cannot be homeomorphic to a nowhere dense is a partial order on the types as well. P-subset of itself; this leaves open a major question: is there Both orders have been studied extensively; we mention ∗ a non-trivial copy of N in itself, i.e., one not of the form some of the more salient results. There are -minimal ∗ @ cl D \ D for some countable discrete subset of N . points in ∗: weak P-points are such. Points that are ≺- N A good place to start exploring β is van Mill’s survey minimal in ∗ are called selective ultrafilters; they exist if N N [KV, Chapter 11]. CH holds but they do not exist in the random real model. There are ≺-incomparable points (even a family of 2c many ≺-incomparable points) but it is not known whether for ev- ery point there is another point ≺-incomparable to it. The 5. Cardinal numbers order @ is tree-like: types below a fixed type are linearly ordered. The cardinal numbers mentioned above are all uncountable and not larger than c, so the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) im- plies that all are equal to ℵ1. More generally, Martin’s Ax- 4. The continuum hypothesis and βN iom implies all are equal to c. One can prove certain inequal- ities between the characteristics, e.g., ℵ1 6 p 6 t 6 h 6 b 6 ∗ = The behaviour of βN and, especially, N under the assump- d. Intriguingly it is as yet unknown whether p t is prov- tion of the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) is very well un- able, what is known is that p = ℵ1 implies t = ℵ1. derstood. The principal reason is that the Boolean algebra One proves b 6 a but neither a 6 d nor d 6 a is provable P(N)/fin is characterized by the properties of being atom- in ZFC. less, countably saturated and of cardinality c = ℵ1. Topo- Two more characteristics have received a fair amount of ∗ logically, N is, up to homeomorphism, the unique com- attention, the splitting number s is the minimum cardinal- pact zero-dimensional without isolated points, which is an ity of a splitting family, that is, a family S such that for every F-space in which nonempty Gδ-sets have non-empty inte- infinite X there is S ∈ S with X ∩ S and X \ S infinite; and rior and which is of weight c. This is known as Parovicenko’sˇ its dual, the reaping number r, which is the minimum car- ∗ characterization of N and it implies that whenever X is dinality of a family that cannot be reaped (or split), that is, a compact zero-dimensional and of weight c (or less) the family R such that for every infinite X there is R ∈ R such ∗ ∗ remainder (N × X) is homeomorphic to N . This pro- that one of X ∩ R and X \ R is not infinite. ∗ c ∗ κ vides us with many incarnations of N , e.g., as (N × 2) , Topologically s is the minimum κ for which 2 is not se- which immediately provides us with 2c many autohomeo- quentially compact and r is equal to the minimum π-cha- ∗ ∗ ∗ morphisms of N , or as (N × (ω + 1)) , which gives us a racter of points in N . 216 Section D: Fairly general properties

∗ Further inequalities between these characteristics are, e.g., cut point (i.e., cut point of some subcontinuum) of H . Al- h 6 s 6 d and b 6 r. though the continuum Iu is an irreducible continuum, i.e., These ‘small’ cardinals are the subject of ongoing re- no smaller continuum contains its end points au and bu , it search; good introductions are [KV, Chapter 3] and [vMR, is definitely not an ordered continuum. It is an F-space so Chapter 11]. the closure of an increasing sequence of points in the ultra- product is homeomorphic to βN (in an ordered continuum it would have to be ω+1). The ‘supremum’ of such a sequence 6. Properties of β R of points in Iu is an irreducibility layer of Iu ; this layer is ∗ non-trivial (it contains N ) and indecomposable. Adding all Instead of βR one usually considers βH, where H is the these facts together we can deduce that a maximal chain of positive half line [0, ∞). This is because x 7→ −x induces ∗ indecomposable subcontinua of H has a one-point inter- an autohomeomorphism of β that shows that β[0, ∞) and ∗ R section; such a point is not a weak cut point of H . Thus β(−∞, 0] are the same thing. ∗ H is shown to be not homogeneous by purely continuum- In a sense βH looks like βN in that it is a thin locally theoretic means. There is a natural quasi-order on an irre- compact space with a large compact lump at the end; this re- ducible continuum: in the present case x 6 y means “every mainder ∗ has some properties in common with ∗: both H N continuum that contains au and y also contains x”. An irre- are F-spaces in which nonempty Gδ-sets have nonempty in- ducibility layer is an equivalence class for the equivalence terior, both have tree π-bases and neither is an Fℵ2 -space. ∗ ∗ relation “x 6 y and y 6 x”. Under CH the spaces H and N have homeomorphic dense The weak cut points constructed above are near points sets of P-points. That is where the superficial similarities ∗ and, in fact, every near point is a weak cut point of . Un- end because β and ∗ are connected and β and ∗ most H H H N N der CH one can construct different kinds of weak cut points: certainly are not. far but not remote and even remote. Under CH it is also pos- A deeper similarity is a version of Parovicenko’sˇ univer- sible to map a remote weak cut point to a near point by an sality theorem: every continuum of weight ℵ (or less) is a 1 autohomeomorphism of ∗. On the other hand it is consis- continuous image of ∗, so that, under CH, the space ∗ is a H H H tent that all weak cut points are near points and hence that universal continuum of weight c. A version of Parovicenko’sˇ ∗ ∗ the far points are topologically invariant in H . A similar characterization theorem for H is yet to be found. ∗ consistency result for remote points is still wanting. The structure of H as-a-continuum is very interesting. ∗ ∗ The composant of a point x of H meets N in the ul- Most references for what follows can be found in [HvM, S ∗ trafilter {U: x ∈ cl n∈U [n, n + 1]} and two points from N Chapter 9]. ∗ are in the same composant of H iff they are nearly coher- The following construction is crucial for our understand- ∗ ∗ ent. Therefore, the structure of the set of composants of ing of the structure of the continuum H : take a discrete se- H is determined by the family of finite-to-one maps of to it- quence h[an, bn]in of non-trivial closed intervals and an ul- N self. This implies that the number of composants may be 2c trafilter u on N. The intersection (e.g., if CH holds), 1 (this is equivalent to the NCF principle) \  [  or 2 (in other models of set theory); whether other numbers I = cl [a b ] n, n are possible is unknown. U∈u n∈U The number of (homeomorphism types of) subcontinua ∗ is a continuum, often called a standard subcontinuum of H is as yet a function of Set Theory: in ZFC one can ∗ establish the lower bound of 14. Under CH there are ℵ of H . What is striking about this construction is not its sim- 1 plicity but that these (deceptively) simple continua govern types even though in one respect CH act as an equalizer: ∗ the continuum-theoretic properties of H . Every proper sub- CH is equivalent to the statement that all standard subcon- continuum (in particular every point) is contained in a stan- tinua are mutually homeomorphic. Most of the ZFC continua dard subcontinuum – it is in fact the intersection of some are found as intervals in an Iu with points and non-trivial family of standard subcontinua. From this one shows that layers at their ends and with varying cofinalities. ∗ H is hereditarily unicoherent – every finite intersection of standard subcontinua is a standard subcontinuum or a point – and indecomposable – standard subcontinua are nowhere References dense. From the other direction every subcontinuum is also the [1] B. Balcar, J. Pelant and P. Simon, The space of ultrafil- union of a suitable family of standard subcontinua. Thus, no ters on N covered by nowhere dense sets, Fund. Math. ∗ subcontinuum of H is hereditarily indecomposable, as stan- 110 (1980), 11–24. dard subcontinua have cut points. Indeed, Iu contains the [2] B. Balcar and P. Vojtáš, Almost disjoint refinement of Q ultraproduct n[an, bn]/u, as a dense set: the equivalence families of subsets of N, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 79 class of a sequence hxnin corresponds to its own u-limit, de- (1980), 465–470. noted xu . The subspace topology of this ultraproduct coin- [3] W.W. Comfort and S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ul- cides with its order topology and every point of the ultra- trafilters, Grundlehren Math. Wiss. Einzeldarstellun- product (except au and bu ) is a cut point of Iu and so a weak gen, Band 211, Springer, Berlin (1974). d-18 The Cech–Stoneˇ compactifications of N and R 217

[4] Z. Frolík, Sums of ultrafilters, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. inal: Ob odnom universal’nom bikompakte vesa ℵ, 73 (1967), 87–91. Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 150 (1963), 36–39. [5] F. Hausdorff, Summen von ℵ1 Mengen, Fund. Math. 26 [9] W. Rudin, Homogeneity problems in the theory of Cechˇ (1936), 241–255. compactifications, Duke Math. J. 23 (1956), 409–419, ∗ [6] K. Kunen, Weak P-points in N , Topology, Vol. II, 633. Proc. Fourth Colloq., Budapest, 1978, Á. Császár, ed., [10] A. Tychonoff, Über einen Funktionenraum, Math. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1980), 741–749. Ann. 111 (1935), 762–766. [7] N.N. Luzin, O chastyakh natural’nogo ryada, Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR. Ser. Mat. 11 (1947), 403–410. [8] I.I. Parovicenko,ˇ A universal bicompact of weight ℵ, Alan Dow and Klaas Pieter Hart Soviet Math. Dokl. 4 (1963), 592–595, Russian orig- Charlotte, NC, USA and Delft, The Netherlands