D-18 Theˇcech–Stone Compactifications of N and R

D-18 Theˇcech–Stone Compactifications of N and R

d-18 The Cech–Stoneˇ compactifications of N and R 213 d-18 The Cech–Stoneˇ Compactifications of N and R c It is safe to say that among the Cech–Stoneˇ compactifica- The proof that βN has cardinality 2 employs an in- tions of individual spaces, that of the space N of natural dependent family, which we define on the countable set numbers is the most widely studied. A good candidate for {hn, si: n ∈ N, s ⊆ P(n)}. For every subset x of N put second place is βR. This article highlights some of the most Ix = {hn, si: x ∩ n ∈ s}. Now if F and G are finite dis- striking properties of both compactifications. T S joint subsets of P(N) then x∈F Ix \ y∈G Iy is non-empty – this is what independent means. Sending u ∈ βN to the P( ) ∗ point pu ∈ N 2, defined by pu(x) = 1 iff Ix ∈ u, gives us a 1. Description of βN and N c continuous map from βN onto 2. Thus the existence of an independent family of size c easily implies the well-known The space β (aka βω) appeared anonymously in [10] as an N fact that the Cantor cube c2 is separable; conversely, if D is example of a compact Hausdorff space without non-trivial c dense in 2 then setting Iα = {d ∈ D: dα = 0} defines an converging sequences. The construction went as follows: for ∗ ∈ independent family on D. Any closed subset F of N such every x (0, 1) let 0.a1(x)a2(x)... an(x)... be its dyadic c expansion (favouring the one that ends in zeros). This gives that the restriction to F of the map onto 2 is irreducible is (homeomorphic with) the absolute of c2. If a point u of ∗ us a countable set A = {an(x): n ∈ N} of points in the Ty- N chonoff cube [0, 1](0,1). The closure of A is the required belongs to such an F then every compactification of the space ∪ {u} contains a copy of β . space. To see that this closure is indeed βN one checks N N Next we prove that ∗ is very non-separable by working that the map n 7→ an induces a homeomorphism of β N N < onto cl A. Indeed, it suffices to observe that whenever X is on the tree 2 N of finite sequences of zeros and ones. For ∈ N = { : ∈ } { : ∈ N } a coinfinite subset of N one has an(x) = 1 iff n ∈ X, where every x 2 let Ax x n n N . Then Ax x 2 is an P −n { ∗: ∈ N } x = ∈ 2 . almost disjoint family of cardinality c and so Ax x 2 n X ∗ The present-day description of β is as the Stone space of is a disjoint family of clopen sets in N . N ∗ the Boolean algebra P(N). Thus the underlying set of βN is We can use this family also to show that N is not ex- S the set of all ultrafilters on N with the family {X: X ⊆ N} as tremally disconnected. Let Q denote the points in N2 that a base for the open sets, where XS denotes the set of all ultra- are constant on a tail (these correspond to the endpoints of filters of which X is an element. The space βN is a separable the Cantor set in [0, 1]) and let P = N2 \ Q. Then OQ = S ∗ S ∗ ∗ and extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space and x∈Q Ax and OP = x∈P Ax are disjoint open sets in N , c ∗ its cardinality is the maximum possible, i.e., 2 . yet cl OQ ∩ cl OP 6= ∅, for if A is such that Ax ⊆ A for Most of the research on βN concentrates on its remain- all x ∈ P then the Baire Category Theorem may be applied \ ∗ ∗ ∗ der βN N, which, as usual, is denoted N . By extension to find x ∈ Q with Ax ⊆ A. This example shows that is ∗ S N one writes X = X \ N for subsets X of N. The family not basically disconnected: O is an open F -set whose ∗ Q σ B = {X : X ⊆ N} is precisely the family of clopen sets closure is not open. ∗ ∗ ⊆ ∗ \ B of N . Because X Y iff X Y is finite the algebra is The algebra P(N)/fin has two countable (in)completeness isomorphic to the quotient algebra P(N)/fin of P(N) by the h i ∗ properties. The first states that when bn n is a decreasing ideal of finite sets – hence N is the Stone space of P(N)/fin. ∗ sequence of non-zero elements there is an x with bn > x > Much topological information about comes from knowl- ∗ N 0 for all n; in topological terms: nonempty Gδ-sets on N edge of the combinatorial properties of this algebra. In prac- ∗ have nonempty interiors and N has no isolated points. The P tice one works in (N) with all relations taken modulo fi- second property says that when hb i is as above and, in nite. We use, e.g., X ⊆∗ Y to denote that X \ Y is finite, n n addition, ha i is an increasing sequence with a < b for X ⊂∗ Y to denote that X ⊆∗ Y but not Y ⊆∗ X, and so on. n n n n all n there is an x with a < x < b for all n; in topological In this context the word ‘almost’ is mostly used in place of n n terms: disjoint open F -sets in ∗ have disjoint closures, ‘modulo finite’, thus ‘A and B are almost disjoint’ means σ N i.e., ∗ is an F-space. A ∩ B =∗ ∅. N We now turn to sets A and B where no interpolating x can be found, that is, we look for A and B such that W A0 < V B0 ∗ 0 <ω 0 <ω 2. Basic properties of N whenever A ∈ [A] and B ∈ [B] but for which there is no x with a 6 x 6 b for all a ∈ A and b ∈ B. The minimum ∗ Many results about N are found by constructing special cardinalities of sets like these are called cardinal character- families of subsets of N, although the actual work is often istics of the continuum and these cardinal numbers play an ∗ done on a suitable countable set different from N. important role in the study of βN and N . Reprinted from Encyclopedia of General Topology K. P. Hart, J. Nagata and J. E. Vaughan, editors © 2004 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved 214 Section D: Fairly general properties We have already seen such a situation with a countable A By the Axiom of Choice every almost disjoint family can ∗ ∗ and a B of cardinality c: the families {Ax }x∈Q and {N \ be extended to a Maximal Almost Disjoint family (a MAD ∗ ∗ S ∗ Ax }x∈P . However, this case, of a countably infinite A, is best family). If A is a MAD family then N \ {A : A ∈ A} is visualized on the countable set N × N. For n ∈ N put an = nowhere dense and every nowhere dense set is contained in ∗ ∗ (n×N) and for f ∈ NN put b f = {hm, ni: n > f (m)} ; then such a ‘canonical’ nowhere dense set. The minimum num- ∗ A = {an: n ∈ N} and B = {b f : f ∈ NN} are as required: if ber of nowhere dense sets whose union is dense in N is de- an < x for all n then one readily finds an f such that b f < x noted h and is called the weak Novák number. It is equal to (make sure {n} × [ f (n), ∞) ⊂ x). A pair like (A, B) above the minimum number of MAD families without a common is called an (unfillable) gap; gap, because, as in a Dedekind MAD refinement – in Boolean terms, it is the minimum κ gap, one has a < b whenever a ∈ A and b ∈ B, and unfillable for which P(N)/fin is not (κ, ∞)-distributive. because there is no x such that a 6 x 6 b for all a and b. Interestingly [1], one can find a sequence hAα: α < hi of Because unfillable gaps are the most interesting one drops MAD families, without common refinement and such that the adjective and speaks of gaps. (1) Aβ refines Aα whenever α < β; (2) if A ∈ Aα then {B ∈ N ∗ One does not need the full set N to create a gap; it Aα+1: B ⊆ A} has cardinality c; and (3) the family T = suffices to have a subset U such that for all g ∈ N there S ∗ N α Aα is dense in P(N)/fin – topologically: {A : A ∈ T } is f ∈ U such that {n: f (n) > g(n)} is infinite. The mini- is a π-base. This all implies that, with hindsight, there is an mum cardinality of such a set is denoted b. increasing sequence of closed nowhere dense sets of length h The properties of b and its bigger brother d are best ex- whose union is dense and that h is a regular cardinal; also ∗ plained using the relation < on NN where, in keeping note that T is a tree under the ordering ⊃∗. ∗ with the notation established above, f < g means that One can use such a tree, of minimal height, in induc- {n: f (n) g(n)} is finite. The definition of b given above ∗ > tive constructions, e.g., as in [2] to show that N is very identifies it as the minimum cardinality of an unbounded – ∗ non-extremally disconnected: every point is a c-point, which with respect to < – subset of NN; unbounded is not the means that one can find a family of c many disjoint open sets same as dominating (cofinal), the minimum cardinality of a each of which has the point in its closure.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    5 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us