Bibliographical References

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bibliographical References Bibliographical References Abbreviations employed for frequently mentioned journals. AHES Archive for History of Exact Sciences AM Acta Mathematica AMM American Mathematical Monthly AS Annals of Science DMV Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung FM Fundamenta Mathematica HM Historia Mathematica HPL History and Philosophy of Logic JrM Journal f'tir die reine und angewandte Mathematik (Crelle) JSL Journal of Symbolic Logic LMS Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society MA Mathematische Annalen NAS Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A. NG Nachrichten der K6nigliche Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu G/Sttingen NTM International Journal of History and Ethics of Natural Sciences, Technology and Medicine RHS Revue d'histoire des sciences et de leurs applications ACKERMANN, W. 1937 Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der allgemeinen Mengenlehre, MA 114, 305-15. 1938 Mengentheoretische Begrfindung der Logik, MA 115, 1-22. ALEKSANDROV, P.S. 1916 Sur la puissance des ensembles mesurables B, Comptes Rendus, Acad~mie des Sciences de Paris 162, 323-25. ARISTOTLE Organon, in J. Barnes, ed., The Complete Works of Aristotle, 2 vols., Princeton University Press, 1984. ARNAULD, A. & P. NICOLE 1662 La Logique ou l'Art de Penser, Paris, Flammarion, 1970. A USLEIHREGISTER Handwritten record of books and journals loaned to professors and students of the University of G6ttingen, kept at the Nieders~ichsische Staats- und Universit~itsbib- liothek (Handschriftenabteilung). BEKEMEIER, B. 1987 Martin Ohm (1792-1872): Universitiitsmathematik und Schulmathematik in der neuhumanistischen Bildungsreform, G6ttingen, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. 394 Bibliographical References BENACERRAF, P. & H. PUTNAM, eds. 1983 Philosophy of Mathematics: selected readings, Cambridge University Press. BENDIXSON, I. 1883 Quelques th6or6mes de la th6orie des ensembles, AM 2, 415--429. BENSAUDE-VINCENT, B. 1983 A Founder Myth in the History of Science? The Lavoisier Case, in L. Graham, W. Lepenies & P. Weingart, eds. Functions and Uses of Disciplinary Histories, Dor- drecht, Reidel, 53-78. BERNAYS, P. 1930 Die Philosophie der Mathematik und die Hilbertsche Beweistheorie, Bl~itter f~r Deutsche Philosophic 4, 326-67. References to [Bemays 1976], 17-61. 1935 Hilberts Untersuchungen fiber die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, in [Hilbert 1932/35], vol. 3, 196-216. 1935a Sur le platonisme dans les math6matiques, L 'Enseignement Mathdmatique 34, 52- 69. German trans, in [Bernays 1976], English in [Benacerraf & Putnam 1983], 258-71. 1937/42 A System of Axiomatic Set Theory, Parts I-III, JSL 2, 65-77, 6, 1-17, 7, 65- 89, 133-45. 1958 Axiomatic Set Theory, Amsterdam, North-Holland. 1976 Abhandlungen zur Philosophic der Mathematik, Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. BERNSTEIN, F. 1905 Untersuchungen aus der Mengenlehre, MA 61, 117-155. BIERMANN, K.R. 1959 Johann Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet. Dokumente )"fir sein Leben und Wirken, Berlin, Akademie-Verlag. 1966 Karl Weierstrass. Ausgew~ihlte Aspekte seiner Biographic, JrM 223, 191-220. 1966a Richard Dedekind im Urteil der Berliner Akademie, Forschungen und Fortschritte 40, 301-302. BOCHE/qSKI, I.M. 1956 Formale Logik, Mfinchen, Alber. DU BOIS-REYMOND, P. 1875 Versuch einer Classification der willkfirlichen Functionen reeller Argumente nach ihren Aenderungen in den kleinsten lntervallen, JrM 79, 21-37. 1880 Der Beweis des Fundamentalsatzes der Integralrechnung, MA 16, 115-128. BOLLING, R. 1997 Georg Cantor - Ausgew~ihlte Aspekte seiner Biographic, DMV 99, 49-82. BOLLINGER, M. 1972 Geschichtliche Entwicklung des Homologiebegriffs, AHES 9, 94-170. BOLZANO, B. 1817 Rein analytischer Beweis des Lehrsatzes dass zwischen je zwei Werten die ein entgegengesetztes Resultat gewiihren, wenigstens eine reelle Wurzel der Gleichung liege, Prag, Haase. Reprint in Ostwald's Klassiker no. 153. English trans, in [Ewald 1996, vol. 1]. 1837 Wissenschaftslehre, 4 vols., Seidel, Sulzbach. Reprinted in 1937. Selections trans- lated as Theory of Science, Oxford, Blackwell, 1972. Bibliographical References 395 1851 Paradoxien des Unedlichen, Leipzig, Reclam. Reprint in Leipzig, Meiner, 1920, and Hamburg, 1975. English trans. London, Routledge, 1950. BOOLE, G. 1847 The mathematical analysis of Logic, Cambridge, Macmillan. References to the reprint Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1951. Reprinted in [Ewald 1996, vol.1]. BOOLOS, G. 1971 The Iterative Concept of Set, Journal of Philosophy 68, 215-31. Reprint in [Bena- cerraf & Putnam 1983]. BOREL, E. 1898 Lemons sur la theorie des fonctions, Paris, Gauthier-Villars. BORGA, M., P. FREGUGLIA & D. PALLADINO 1985 I contributi fondazionali della scuola di Peano, Milano, Angeli. BOS, H., H. MEHRTENS & I. SCHNEIDER, eds. 1981 Social history of nineteenth century mathematics, Boston, Birkh~iuser. BO'ITAZZINI, U. 1977 Riemanns Einfluss auf Betti und Casorati, AHES 18, 27-37. 1985 Dall'Analisi Matematica al Calcolo Geometrico: Origini Delle Prime Ricerche di Logica di Peano, HPL 6, 25-52. 1986 The Higher Calculus: A History of Real and Complex Analysis from Euler to Weierstrass, New York, Springer. BOURBAKI, N. 1949 Foundations of Mathematics for the Working Mathematician, JSL 14, 1-8. 1950 The Architecture of Mathematics, AMM 67, 221-32. Reprinted in [Ewald 1996], vol.2. 1954 Thdorie des ensembles, Pads, Hermann. 1994 Elements of the history of mathematics, Berlin, Springer (original edition 1969). BROUWER, L.E.J. 1910 Zur Analysis Situs, MA 68, 422-34. English trans, in [Brouwer 1975/76]. 1911 Beweis der Invarianz der Dimensionszahl, MA 70, 161-65. English trans, in [Brouwer 1975/76]. 1918 Begrtindung der Mengenlehre unabh~'agig vom logischen Satz vom ausgeschlosse- nen Dritten, I, Verhandelingen der Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Weten- schappen te Amsterdam 12. English trans, in [Brouwer 1975/76]. 1925 Zur Begrtindung der intuitionistischen Mathematik, I, MA 93, 244-57. English trans, in [Brouwer 1975/76]. 1975/76 Collected Works, A. Heyting and H. Fredenthal, eds., 2 vols., Amsterdam, North-Holland. BUNN, R. 1980 Developments in the Foundations of Mathematics from 1870 to 1910, in [Grattan- Guinness 1980]. BURALI-FORTI, C. 1896 Le classi finite, Atti della Academia delle Scienze di Torino 32, 34-52. 1897 Una questione sui numeri transfiniti, Rendiconti del Circolo Matematico di Pal- ermo 11, 154-64. References to the English trans, in [van Heijenoort 1967], 104- 11. 396 Bibliographical References BUTZER, P.L. 1987 Dirichlet and His Role in the Founding of Mathematical Physics, Archives interna- tionales d'histoire des sciences 37, 49-82. CANEVA, K.L. 1978 From Galvanism to Electrodynamics: The Transformation of German Physics and Its Social Context, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 9, 63-159. CANTOR, G. 1872 Ober die Ausdehnung eines Satzes aus der Theorie der trigonometrischen Reihen, MA 5, 123-32. References to [Cantor 1932], 92-101. 1874 Ober eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen, JrM 77, 258-62. References to [Cantor 1932], 115-118. English trans, in [Ewald 1996], vol.2. 1878 Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, JrM 84, 242-58. References to [Cantor 1932], 119-133. 1879/84 Ober unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten, MA 15, 1-7, 17, 355-58, 20, 113-21, 21, 51-58, 545-86, 23, 453-88. References to [Cantor 1932], 139- 244. 1883 Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, Leipzig, 1883 (separate edition of [Cantor 1879/84], part 5). References to [Cantor 1932], 165-208. Eng- lish trans, in [Ewald 1996], vol.2. 1886 Ober die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Unendliche, Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 88, 224-33. References to [Cantor 1932], 370-76. 1887/88 Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten, Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie und phi- losophische Kritik 91, 81-125, 252-70, 92, 250-65. References to [Cantor 1932], 378-439. 1892 Ober eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, DMV 1, 75-78. References to [Cantor 1932], 278-280. English trans, in [Ewald 1996], vol.2. 1895/97 Beitr/age zur Begrtindung der transfiniten Mengenlehre, MA 46, 481-512, 49, 207-46. References to [Cantor 1932], 282-351. 1915 Contributions to the founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers, Chicago, Open Court. Reprint New York, Dover, 1955. 1932 Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen lnhalts, ed. E. Zermelo, Berlin, Springer. Reprint Hildesheim, G. Olms, 1966. 1970 Principien einer Theorie der Ordnungstypen, in [Grattan-Guinness 1970], 83-101. CANTOR, G. & R. DEDEKIND 1932 Aus dem Briefwechsel zwischen Cantor und Dedekind (1899 letters), in [Cantor 1932], 443-450. English trans, in [Ewald 1996], vol.2. 1937 Cantor-Dedekind Briefwechsel, ed. E. Noether and J. Cavaill~s, Paris, Hermann. French translation including the 1899 letters in [Cavaill~s 1962], 187-249. English trans, in [Ewald 1996], vol.2. 1976 Unverrffentlichter Briefwechsel, in [Dugac 1976], 223-262. CARNAP, R. 1929 Abriss der Logistik, mit besonderer Beriicksichtigung der Relationstheorie und ihrer Anwendungen, Wien, Springer, 1929. 1931 Die logizistische Grundlegung der Mathematik, Erkenntnis 2, 91-105. References to the English translation in [Benacerraf & Putnam 1983, 41-52]. 1937 The Logical Syntax of Language, New York, Harcourt, Brace. Bibliographical References 397 1963 Intellectual Autobiography, in P.A. Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy ofR. Carnap, La Salle, II1., Open Court, 1963. CAUCHY, A.L. 1821 Cours d'analyse algObrique, Paris. In Oeuvres completes, ser. 2, Paris, Gauthier- Villars, 1897-99, vol. 3. CAVAILLI~S, J. 1932 Sur
Recommended publications
  • Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L As the True, Noumenal Universe Of
    Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa CLASSE DI LETTERE Corso di Perfezionamento in Filosofia PHD degree in Philosophy Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L as the true, noumenal universe of mathematics Candidato: Relatore: Emanuele Gambetta Prof.- Massimo Mugnai anno accademico 2015-2016 Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L as the true noumenal universe of mathematics Emanuele Gambetta Contents 1. Introduction 7 Chapter 1. The Dream of Completeness 19 0.1. Preliminaries to this chapter 19 1. G¨odel'stheorems 20 1.1. Prerequisites to this section 20 1.2. Preliminaries to this section 21 1.3. Brief introduction to unprovable truths that are mathematically interesting 22 1.4. Unprovable mathematical statements that are mathematically interesting 27 1.5. Notions of computability, Turing's universe and Intuitionism 32 1.6. G¨odel'ssentences undecidable within PA 45 2. Transfinite Progressions 54 2.1. Preliminaries to this section 54 2.2. Gottlob Frege's definite descriptions and completeness 55 2.3. Transfinite progressions 59 3. Set theory 65 3.1. Preliminaries to this section 65 3.2. Prerequisites: ZFC axioms, ordinal and cardinal numbers 67 3.3. Reduction of all systems of numbers to the notion of set 71 3.4. The first large cardinal numbers and the Constructible universe L 76 3.5. Descriptive set theory, the axioms of determinacy and Luzin's problem formulated in second-order arithmetic 84 3 4 CONTENTS 3.6. The method of forcing and Paul Cohen's independence proof 95 3.7. Forcing Axioms, BPFA assumed as a phenomenal solution to the continuum hypothesis and a Kantian metaphysical distinction 103 3.8.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cardinal Sin: the Infinite in Spinoza's Philosophy
    Macalester College DigitalCommons@Macalester College Philosophy Honors Projects Philosophy Department Spring 2014 A Cardinal Sin: The nfinitI e in Spinoza's Philosophy Samuel H. Eklund Macalester College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Eklund, Samuel H., "A Cardinal Sin: The nfinitI e in Spinoza's Philosophy" (2014). Philosophy Honors Projects. Paper 7. http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors/7 This Honors Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at DigitalCommons@Macalester College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Macalester College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Cardinal Sin: The Infinite in Spinoza’s Philosophy By: Samuel Eklund Macalester College Philosophy Department Honors Advisor: Geoffrey Gorham Acknowledgements This thesis would not have been possible without my advisor, Professor Geoffrey Gorham. Through a collaborative summer research grant, I was able to work with him in improving a vague idea about writing on Spinoza’s views on existence and time into a concrete analysis of Spinoza and infinity. Without his help during the summer and feedback during the past academic year, my views on Spinoza wouldn’t have been as developed as they currently are. Additionally, I would like to acknowledge the hard work done by the other two members of my honors committee: Professor Janet Folina and Professor Andrew Beveridge. Their questions during the oral defense and written feedback were incredibly helpful in producing the final draft of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Infinite in Leibniz's Philosophy
    On the Infinite in Leibniz's Philosophy Elad Lison Interdisciplinary Studies Unit Science, Technology and Society Ph.D. Thesis Submitted to the Senate of Bar-Ilan University Ramat-Gan, Israel August 2010 This work was carried out under the supervision of Dr. Ohad Nachtomy (Department of Philosophy), Bar-Ilan University. Contents א.……………………………….…………………………………………Hebrew Abstract Prologue…………………………………………………………...………………………1 Part A: Historic Survey Methodological Introduction…………………………………………………………..15 1. Aristotle: Potential Infinite………………………………………………………….16 2. Thomas Aquinas: God and the Infinite………………………………………..…….27 3. William of Ockham: Syncategorematic and Actual Infinite……………………..….32 4. Rabbi Abraham Cohen Herrera: Between Absolute Unity and Unbounded Multitude………………………………………………………………………..….42 5. Galileo Galilei: Continuum Constructed from Infinite Zero's………………………49 6. René Descartes: Infinite as Indefinite…………………………………………….…58 7. Pierre Gassendi: Rejection of the Infinite…………………………………………...69 8. Baruch Spinoza: Infinite Unity…………………………………………………...…73 9. General Background: Leibniz and the History of the Infinite……………………....81 Summary…………………………………………………………………………….…94 Part B: Mathematics Introduction…………………………………………………………………………….99 1. 'De Arte Combinatoria' as a Formal Basis for Thought: Retrospective on Leibniz's 1666 Dissertation………………………………………………………………....102 2. Leibniz and the Infinitesimal Calculus……………………………………….……111 2.1. Mathematical Background: Mathematical Works in 16th-17th Centuries…..111 2.2. Leibniz's Mathematical Development…………………………………….…127
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind
    Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind Anne Newstead Abstract. The mathematician Georg Cantor strongly believed in the existence of actually infinite numbers and sets. Cantor’s “actualism” went against the Aristote- lian tradition in metaphysics and mathematics. Under the pressures to defend his theory, his metaphysics changed from Spinozistic monism to Leibnizian volunta- rist dualism. The factor motivating this change was two-fold: the desire to avoid antinomies associated with the notion of a universal collection and the desire to avoid the heresy of necessitarian pantheism. We document the changes in Can- tor’s thought with reference to his main philosophical-mathematical treatise, the Grundlagen (1883) as well as with reference to his article, “Über die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Unendliche” (“Concerning Various Perspec- tives on the Actual Infinite”) (1885). I. he Philosophical Reception of Cantor’s Ideas. Georg Cantor’s dis- covery of transfinite numbers was revolutionary. Bertrand Russell Tdescribed it thus: The mathematical theory of infinity may almost be said to begin with Cantor. The infinitesimal Calculus, though it cannot wholly dispense with infinity, has as few dealings with it as possible, and contrives to hide it away before facing the world Cantor has abandoned this cowardly policy, and has brought the skeleton out of its cupboard. He has been emboldened on this course by denying that it is a skeleton. Indeed, like many other skeletons, it was wholly dependent on its cupboard, and vanished in the light of day.1 1Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (London: Routledge, 1992 [1903]), 304.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor-Von Neumann Set-Theory Fa Muller
    Logique & Analyse 213 (2011), x–x CANTOR-VON NEUMANN SET-THEORY F.A. MULLER Abstract In this elementary paper we establish a few novel results in set the- ory; their interest is wholly foundational-philosophical in motiva- tion. We show that in Cantor-Von Neumann Set-Theory, which is a reformulation of Von Neumann's original theory of functions and things that does not introduce `classes' (let alone `proper classes'), developed in the 1920ies, both the Pairing Axiom and `half' the Axiom of Limitation are redundant — the last result is novel. Fur- ther we show, in contrast to how things are usually done, that some theorems, notably the Pairing Axiom, can be proved without invok- ing the Replacement Schema (F) and the Power-Set Axiom. Also the Axiom of Choice is redundant in CVN, because it a theorem of CVN. The philosophical interest of Cantor-Von Neumann Set- Theory, which is very succinctly indicated, lies in the fact that it is far better suited than Zermelo-Fraenkel Set-Theory as an axioma- tisation of what Hilbert famously called Cantor's Paradise. From Cantor one needs to jump to Von Neumann, over the heads of Zer- melo and Fraenkel, and then reformulate. 0. Introduction In 1928, Von Neumann published his grand axiomatisation of Cantorian Set- Theory [1925; 1928]. Although Von Neumann's motivation was thoroughly Cantorian, he did not take the concept of a set and the membership-relation as primitive notions, but the concepts of a thing and a function — for rea- sons we do not go into here. This, and Von Neumann's cumbersome nota- tion and terminology (II-things, II.I-things) are the main reasons why ini- tially his theory remained comparatively obscure.
    [Show full text]
  • Lost in the Labyrinth: Spinoza, Leibniz and the Continuum Lost in the Labyrinth: Spinoza, Leibniz and the Continuum
    LOST IN THE LABYRINTH: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ AND THE CONTINUUM LOST IN THE LABYRINTH: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ AND THE CONTINUUM By PATRICK RIESTERER, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies In Partial Fulfillment ofthe Requirements For the Degree Master ofArts McMaster University © Copyright by Patrick Riesterer, August 2006 MASTER OF ARTS (2006) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Lost in the Labyrinth: Spinoza, Leibniz and the Continuum AUTHOR: Patrick Riesterer, B.A. (Trinity Western University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Richard Arthur NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 110 ii Abstract In this thesis, I address the extent ofSpinoza's influence on the development of Leibniz's response to the continuum problem, with particular emphasis on his relational philosophy oftime and space. I expend the first chapter carefully reconstructing Spinoza's position on infinity and time. We see that Spinoza developed a threefold definition ofinfinity to explain the difference between active substance and its passive modes. Spinoza advances a syncategorematic interpretation ofinfinity, and founds a causal theory oftime directly on this conception ofinfinity. In the second chapter, I examine the changes Leibniz's understanding ofthe continuum problem underwent during 1676 and immediately thereafter. During this period, Leibniz's interacted extensively with Spinoza's ideas. We see that several fundamental features ofLeibniz's philosophy oftime take shape at this time. Leibniz adopts a Spinozistic definition ofdivine eternity and immensity, he reevaluates several analogies in an attempt to understand how the attributes ofa substance interrelate, and he develops the notion ofthe law of the series that will become an essential feature ofmonadic appetition. Leibniz synthesizes several ofthese discoveries into a first philosophy ofmotion.
    [Show full text]
  • A Mathematical Model of Divine Infinity
    A Mathematical Model of Divine Infinity Prof. Eric Steinhart, Department of Philosophy, William Paterson University, Wayne NJ 07470. Email: <[email protected]>, <[email protected]>. Published in 2009 in Theology and Science 7 (3), 261 – 274. ABSTRACT: Mathematics is obviously important in the sciences. And so it is likely to be equally important in any effort that aims to understand God in a scientifically significant way or that aims to clarify the relations between science and theology. The degree to which God has any perfection is absolutely infinite. We use contemporary mathematics to precisely define that absolute infinity. For any perfection, we use transfinite recursion to define an endlessly ascending series of degrees of that perfection. That series rises to an absolutely infinite degree of that perfection. God has that absolutely infinite degree. We focus on the perfections of knowledge, power, and benevolence. Our model of divine infinity thus builds a bridge between mathematics and theology. KEYWORDS: God; mathematics; perfection; infinity; Cantor; transfinite recursion. 1. Introduction All will agree that science makes extensive use of mathematics. At least in physics, scientific progress seems to go hand in hand with increasing formalization. More sophisticated physical theories are also more highly mathematical. And the correlation of progress with increasing formalization also appears sciences like chemistry and biology as well. Mathematics is obviously important in the sciences. And so it is likely to be equally important in any effort that aims to understand God in a scientifically significant way or that aims to clarify the relations between science and theology. Nevertheless, mathematics has seen little application in theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Pictures of the Iterative Hierarchy
    TWO PICTURES OF THE ITERATIVE HIERARCHY by Ida Marie Myrstad Dahl Thesis for the degree of Master in Philosophy Supervised by Professor Øystein Linnebo Fall 2014 Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas University of Oslo Two pictures of the iterative hierarchy ©2014 Two pictures of the iterative hierarchy Ida Marie Myrstad Dahl http://www.duo.uio.no Print: OKPrintShop iii Contents Acknowledgements . v Abstract . vi Introduction 1 1 The iterative conception of set 4 1.1 What it is . 4 1.2 Why the iterative conception? . 8 2 Actualism and potentialism on the iterative conception 15 2.1 The actualist picture . 16 2.2 The potentialist picture . 19 3 From the ancient to the contemporary concept of infinity 24 3.1 Aristotle on infinity . 24 3.2 Three important developments . 30 3.3 Cantor’s theory of the infinite . 31 3.4 A tension between actualism and potentialism . 34 4 Two tenable pictures? 40 4.1 (1) An actual conception . 41 4.2 (2) An intuitive conception . 47 4.3 (3) Explaining paradox . 50 4.4 Two tenable interpretations . 53 Conclusion 56 iv Acknowledgements I owe special thanks to Øystein Linnebo, for helpful supervision of my project, but also for introducing me to the philosophical ideas about the infinite in a phi- losophy of language seminar, at the University of Oslo, autumn, 2012. His ideas and teaching has been of great inspiration. Also, attending the PPP-seminars (Plurals, Predicates and Paradox), led by Linnebo, in 2013, was of great interest, and helped me single out the topic I wanted to write about.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul M. Livingston
    C ABSTRACT: C R R I Partially following Gilles Deleuze, I articulate six criteria for a strong I S variety of critique: one which affirms the power of thought in going all S I I How do we S the way to the limit of existing societies, situations, institutions and S practices. The form of this strong critique is a complex unity of thought & & and life that can be indicated, as I argue, on the basis of a twofold C C R condition: a contemporary repetition of the classical structuralism R I that Deleuze develops in the 1967 article “How do we recognize I recognize strong T T I structuralism?” and a formally based reflection on the properly infinite I Q dimension of structure and sense. I develop the implications of this Q U U E strong critique under contemporary conditions, distinguishing it E from various alternative current forms of sociopolitical critique and critique? # # 3 non-critique. In particular I argue that through its articulation of the 3 consequences of constitutive paradox, the structure of the situationally undecidable, and the ineffectivity characteristic of the constitution of sense, strong critique offers appropriate forms of response in thought and action to the structural problems and antagonisms characteristic of contemporary global capitalism. Keywords: Paul M. Critique, Deleuze, infinite, paradoxico-critical, undecidable, ineffective Livingston In his 1965 short monograph Nietzsche, Gilles Deleuze indicates the complex condition of a strong variety of critique: The philosopher of the future is the explorer of ancient worlds, of peaks and caves, who creates only inasmuch as he recalls something that has been essentially forgotten.
    [Show full text]
  • Gödel's Cantorianism
    Gödel’s Cantorianism Claudio Ternullo KGRC, University of Vienna* “My theory is rationalistic, idealistic, optimistic, and theological”. Gödel, in Wang (1996), p. 8 “Numeros integros simili modo atque totum quoddam legibus et relationibus compositum efficere” Cantor, De transformatione formarum ternariarum quadraticarum, thesis III, in Cantor (1932), p. 62 1. Introductory remarks There is no conclusive evidence, either in his published or his unpublished work, that Gödel had read, meditated upon or drawn inspiration from Cantor’s philosophical doctrines. We know about his philosophical “training”, and that, since his youth, he had shown interest in the work of such philosophers as Kant, Leibniz and Plato. It is also widely known that, from a certain point onwards in his life, he started reading and absorbing Husserl’s thought and that phenomenology proved to be one of the most fundamental influences he was to subject himself to in the course of the development of his ideas. 1 But we do not know about the influence of Cantor’s thought. In Wang’s book containing reports of the philosophical conversations the author had with Gödel, one can find only a few remarks by Gödel concerning Cantor’s philosophical conceptions. Not much material do we get from the secondary literature either. For instance, if one browses through the indexes of Dawson’s fundamental biography of Gödel (Dawson 1997), or those of Wang’s three ponderous volumes (1974, 1987, 1996) one finds that all mentions of Cantor in those works either refer to specific points of Cantorian set theory, as discussed by the authors of these books, or, more specifically, to Gödel’s paper on Cantor’s continuum problem, 2 wherein * The writing of this article has been supported by the JTF Grant ID35216 (research project “The Hyperuniverse.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory: Taming the Infinite
    This is page 54 Printer: Opaque this CHAPTER 2 Set Theory: Taming the Infinite 2.1 Introduction “I see it, but I don’t believe it!” This disbelief of Georg Cantor in his own creations exemplifies the great skepticism that his work on infinite sets in- spired in the mathematical community of the late nineteenth century. With his discoveries he single-handedly set in motion a tremendous mathematical earthquake that shook the whole discipline to its core, enriched it immea- surably, and transformed it forever. Besides disbelief, Cantor encountered fierce opposition among a considerable number of his peers, who rejected his discoveries about infinite sets on philosophical as well as mathematical grounds. Beginning with Aristotle (384–322 b.c.e.), two thousand years of West- ern doctrine had decreed that actually existing collections of infinitely many objects of any kind were not to be part of our reasoning in philosophy and mathematics, since they would lead directly into a quagmire of logical con- tradictions and absurd conclusions. Aristotle’s thinking on the infinite was in part inspired by the paradoxes of Zeno of Elea during the fifth century b.c.e. The most famous of these asserts that Achilles, the fastest runner in ancient Greece, would be unable to surpass a much slower runner, provided that the slower runner got a bit of a head start. Namely, Achilles would then first have to cover the distance between the starting positions, dur- ing which time the slower runner could advance a certain distance. Then Achilles would have to cover that distance, while the slower runner would again advance, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate
    SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2011 Committee: Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor Juan Bes Rieuwert Blok i Abstract Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor This manuscript was to show the equivalency of the Axiom of Choice, Zorn's Lemma and Zermelo's Well-Ordering Principle. Starting with a brief history of the development of set history, this work introduced the Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel, common applications of the axioms, and set theoretic descriptions of sets of numbers. The book, Introduction to Set Theory, by Karel Hrbacek and Thomas Jech was the primary resource with other sources providing additional background information. ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Warren Wm. McGovern for his assistance and guidance while working and writing this thesis. I also want to thank Reiuwert Blok and Juan Bes for being on my committee. Thank you to Dan Shifflet and Nate Iverson for help with the typesetting program LATEX. A personal thank you to my husband, Don, for his love and support. iii Contents Contents . iii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Naive Set Theory . 2 1.2 The Axiom of Choice . 4 1.3 Russell's Paradox . 5 2 Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel 7 2.1 First Order Logic . 7 2.2 The Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel . 8 2.3 The Recursive Theorem . 13 3 Development of Numbers 16 3.1 Natural Numbers and Integers . 16 3.2 Rational Numbers . 20 3.3 Real Numbers .
    [Show full text]