<<

Œconomia 5-1 (2015) The of

......

Agnès Festré et Pierre Garrouste The ‘Economics of Attention’: A History of Economic Thought Perspective

......

Avertissement Le contenu de ce site relève de la législation française sur la propriété intellectuelle et est la propriété exclusive de l'éditeur. Les œuvres figurant sur ce site peuvent être consultées et reproduites sur un support papier ou numérique sous réserve qu'elles soient strictement réservées à un usage soit personnel, soit scientifique ou pédagogique excluant toute exploitation commerciale. La reproduction devra obligatoirement mentionner l'éditeur, le nom de la revue, l'auteur et la référence du document. Toute autre reproduction est interdite sauf accord préalable de l'éditeur, en dehors des cas prévus par la législation en vigueur en France.

Revues.org est un portail de revues en sciences humaines et sociales développé par le Cléo, Centre pour l'édition électronique ouverte (CNRS, EHESS, UP, UAPV).

......

Référence électronique Agnès Festré et Pierre Garrouste, « The ‘Economics of Attention’: A History of Economic Thought Perspective », Œconomia [En ligne], 5-1 | 2015, mis en ligne le 01 mars 2015, consulté le 10 avril 2015. URL : http:// oeconomia.revues.org/1139

Éditeur : Association Œconomia http://oeconomia.revues.org http://www.revues.org

Document accessible en ligne sur : http://oeconomia.revues.org/1139 Ce document est le fac-similé de l'édition papier. © Association Œconomia

The Economics of Attention/ L'économie de l'attention

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 1

The ‘Economics of Attention’: A History of Economic Thought Perspective

Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste*

This article takes stock of the increasing that the economic profes- sion has shown for the role of attention in our economies this last decade. It also highlights that the concept of attention is an old issue in social sci- ences and that it has been central for those of the past most in- terested in the relation between the functioning of the brain beyond mere economic rationality and economic decisions. This exercise provides then the opportunity to investigate today’s literature on the economics of atten- tion in comparative as well as critical terms. Finally, the article attempts to look ahead in the context of the rising influence of behavioural economics and address issues at stake in order to capture all the dimensions of hu- man attention and their implications for the understanding and analysis of economic phenomena. Keywords: economics of attention, rationality, economic , cog- nitive economics

« L’économie de l’attention » : une perspective d’histoire de la pensée économique Cet article s’intéresse à la littérature économique portant sur la notion d’attention qui s’est développée ces dernières années. Il retient une per- spective d’histoire de la pensée en retraçant l’origine de cette notion depuis la philosophie en passant par la psychologie cognitive et la théorie économique d’auteurs qui ont poussé la réflexion à propos de la rational- ité et de la prise de décision au-delà des frontières usuelles de la discipline économique. Cet exercice présente l’intérêt d’appréhender la littérature émergente sous un angle à la fois comparatif et critique. Finalement, l’article tente de proposer des pistes de réflexion et d’approfondissement de la littérature existante sur la notion d’attention à la lumière des dé- veloppements dans le domaine de l’économie comportementale. Mots-clés : économie de l'attention, rationalité, psychologie économique, économie cognitive JEL: B00, B4, D00

*University Nice-Sophia Antipolis and GREDEG, [email protected] and [email protected] We warmly thank Roger Koppl for his comments and suggestions on a first ver- sion of this paper presented at the Annual Conference of the Society for the De- velopment of Austrian Economics held in Washington DC, 19-21 November 2011. We also thank Dorian Jullien for his useful suggestions and comments on the last version presented at the conference of the European Association for the History of Economic Thought held in Lausanne (Switzerland), 29-31 May 2014. We are grateful to two anonymous referees.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 4 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

1. State of the Art The “economics of attention” increasingly gained importance in aca- demic research since the first appearance of the term in 1997 in a sem- inal on-line article by Michael Goldhaber where he defined it as a sub-field of the “Internet economics”, focusing on the time- consuming dimension of overflowing information. The rising activity of bloggers or the intense use of social networks (Facebook, Twitter, etc.) in the last decade is a clear indication of the fact that attention (rather than information or knowledge) has become a critical econom- ic resource for decision-making. Quite some economists have ad- dressed the problem of limited attention and its economic conse- quences. As anticipated by Camerer (2003), it has become one of the most important topics of behavioural economics1. Applied to macroe- conomic policy, this problem is coined as rational inattention2 and has been put forward by central bankers as one of the lessons to be drawn from the 2008 financial crisis (Trichet, 20103) and by some economists (Akerlof, Dickens and Perry, 2000; Sims, 2003; Shiller, 1997) as an al- ternative to the assumption of for fore- casts notably. In the field of financial theory, Hirschleifer and Teoh (2003) analyze the implications of investors’ limited attention for firms’ information policy and financial equilibrium. The notion of attention is however an old concept in social scienc- es. Originally a philosophical, then a psychological notion, it became popularized in economics thanks to Herbert Simon, whose work on information and in the 50s focused on the interference between information and cognitive capacities.

1 “Another interesting psychological concept, neglected in until recently, is limited attention. Attention is the ultimate scarce cognitive re- source. It is possible to learn to attend to many stimuli at the same time—as busy financial-market floor traders and cell-phone-using drivers do—but long-term suffers. Scarce attention might be useful for explaining economic phe- nomena like organizational structure (division of labor expands organizational attention but is constrained by the need to coordinate) and advertising (which ‘grabs’ attention).” (Camerer, 2003, 16) 2 Rational inattention deals with the issue of which parts of macroeconomic data should rational agents evaluate if limited-processing capacity forces them to dis- card part of the data. 3The following statement by Trichet in his opening address dedicated to “Les- sons from the crisis for and finance theory” at the ECB Central Banking Conference held in Frankfurt in November 2010 is exemplary: “When the crisis came, the serious limitations of existing economic and financial models immediately became apparent…we may need to consider a richer characteriza- tion of expectation formation. Rational expectations theory has brought macroe- conomic analysis a long way over the past four decades. But there is a clear need to reexamine this assumption. Very encouraging work is under way on new con- cepts, such as learning and rational inattention.” (Trichet, 2010)

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 5

The endeavor of this article is to look at the concept of attention from a history of economic thought perspective in order to evaluate the so-called ‘attention economics’ current literature. The paper will be organized as follows. Section 2 briefly reminds the reader of the philosophical and psychological roots of the notion of attention. Section 3 endeavors to trace back the process of diffusion of the concept of attention in economics from a history of economic thought perspective. Section 4 attempts to provide a critical account of the current liter- ature in ‘attention economics’ and suggests the range of questions still to be addressed by scholars in the area.

2. The Notion of Attention in Old and New Psychology The notion of attention was originally discussed by philosophers and closely linked to theories of knowledge. Among the issues considered was the role of attention on conscious awareness and thought, re- ferred to as apperception, defined as the process of understanding something or new ideas perceived in terms of previous experience or pre-existing ideas4. For instance, Leibniz (1704) suggested, using the metaphor of one’s loss of awareness of the constant sound of a water- fall that events could cease to be apperceived (i.e. represented in con- sciousness) without specific attention. He therefore claimed that at- tention determines both what is and what is not apperceived (that is, represented in consciousness). Incidentally, we may also refer to Ad- am Smith, who in his History of Astronomy (1775), referred to a notion, which he labels ‘wonder’ (or the effect of novelty as he states himself) and which is very much related to the concept of attention as later defined by psychologists5. According to him, ‘wonder’ plays a major role in the process of discovery by scientists to the extent that it per-

4 For a history of the notion of attention in philosophy, see Théodule Ribot (1889) and the introduction of Ribot (2007) by Serge Nicolas. Among the mentioned forerunners in philosophy that have been interested in the notion of apperception are Aristotle (300 B.C. [1984]), Malebranche (1675), Leibniz (1704), Condillac (1754) and Bonnet (1760). 5 Smith also referred to the notion of ‘surprise’, which he distinguished from ‘wonder’: “We wonder at all extraordinary and uncommon objects, at all the rarer phenomena of nature, at meteors, comets, eclipses, at singular plants and ani- mals, and at everything, in short, with which we have before been either little or not at all acquainted; and we still wonder, though forewarned of what we are to see.” By contrast, “we are surprised at those things which we have seen often, but which we least of all expected to meet with in the place where we find them; we are surprised at the sudden appearance of a friend, whom we have seen a thou- sand times, but whom we did not imagine we were to see then.” (Smith, [1795] 1975, 44)

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 6 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

mits to bring together distinct current and forgone events so as to make sense and form a consistent whole6. The term of apperception was still employed when psychology be- came a young autonomous science in the 18th century7 and even after. For instance, (1832-1920), one of the founders of ex- perimental psychology (through the development of psychophysical methods), uses the term in order to describe different concentric fields of awareness from general (Blickfeld) to focal (Blickpunkt) features of human awareness (Wundt, 1893, vol. 2., 267). More precisely, he dis- tinguished between , which was the entry into the field of attention, and apperception, which was responsible for entry in the inner focus (Blickpunkt) and assumed that the focus of attention could narrow or widen. At the end of the 19th century, Hermann von Helm- holz (1821-1894) also contributed to the development of the experi- mental perspective on attention, with emphasis on the role of ‘covert attention’ for visual perception (Helmholz, 1910). In particular, using himself as a subject and pages of briefly visible printed letters, he an- ticipated some later work in the 50s showing that attention could be directed in advance of the stimulus presentation to a particular region of the page, even though the eyes were kept fixed at a central point. Moreover, he found that attention was limited: some letters in the visual field, even in the vicinity of the fixation point, were not auto- matically perceived. Undoubtedly one of the most well-known works on attention in psychology is ’s Principles of Psychology (1890), where attention is defined as “…the taking possession by the mind, in clear and vivid form, of one out of what seem several simultaneously pos- sible objects or trains of thought. Focalization, concentration, of con- sciousness are of its essence. It implies withdrawal from some things in order to deal effectively with others, and is a condition which has a real opposite in the confused, dazed, scatterbrained state.” (James, 1890, 403-404) In James’ time, the method more commonly used to study atten- tion was introspection, except for isolate attempts to measure atten-

6 As Smith wrote: “Their [the scientists’] imagination, which accompanies with ease and delight the regular process of nature, is stopped and embarrassed by those seeming incoherencies; they excite their wonder, and seem to require some chain of intermediate events, which, by connecting them with something that has gone before, may thus render the whole course of the universe consistent and of a piece. Wonder, therefore, and not any expectation of advantage from its discover- ies, is the first principle which prompts mankind to the study of Philosophy.” (Smith, [1775] 1975, 26) 7 For a history of attention in psychology, see Hatfield (1995, 1998), Titchener (1908) and Neumann (1971). Hatfield (1995) claims that the notion of attention has been introduced in psychology in 1730s by Wolff (1738).

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 7

tion8, and one of the major debates of this period was whether it was possible to split attention (i.e., to attend to two things at a time) or to attend to something in a state of distraction. At the beginning of the XXth century, while methods to measure attention, which could have helped to resolve the debate, were devel- oping, the study of attention as a mental process became marginal- ized by the rise of behaviourism and positivism9. Behaviourism’s principal advocate, John Watson (1878-1958), was interested primarily in stimulus-response relations, and therefore, confined attention to an operational concept defined in terms of discriminative response to external stimuli10. Interest in attention revived during the cognitive revolution of the 1940s, when engineers and applied became involved in problems of man-machine interaction in various applied contexts. The research originated from concern about the performance of radar operators during the World War 2 and was mainly concerned with human information processing. It also draws on Shannon’s mathematical theory of communication11 (Shannon, 1940).

8 The empirical works in order to measure attention are due to Wolff (1738), Bonnet (1760) and Donders (1864), a Dutch ophthalmologist who was a precursor in using mental chronometry. Mental chronometry is studied using the meas- urements of reaction time (RT). Reaction time is the elapsed time between the presentation of a sensory stimulus and the subsequent behavioral response. In psychometric psychology it is considered to be an index of speed of processing. 9 This point is controversial. Lovie (1983), who compiled tables showing the numbers of papers on attention listed in Psychological Abstracts and its prede- cessors, Psychological Index, in five-year intervals from 1910 to 1960, showed that numerous studies on attention were conducted during this time periods: for in- stance, Jersild (1927) on the ability to shift attention or Telford (1931) on the psy- chological refractory period (PRP) effect. Moreover, Stroop published in 1935 what is certainly one of the most widely cited studies in the field of psychology, in which he demonstrated that stimulus information that is irrelevant to the task can have a major impact on performance (Stroop, 1935). This research has given rise to the famous Stroop Color-Word Task, widely used in psychology. In this cognitive task, participants are asked to name the color of the ink in which an incompatible color word is printed. This test evidences that, e.g., it takes longer to say “red” aloud in response to the stimulus GREEN printed in red ink than to say “red” to the stimulus XXXXX printed in red ink. 10 Note that previous experiments by the Russian physiologists Pavlov and Bekhterev on dogs and animals showed that the conditioned responses to stimuli included measureable signs of attention such as pricked-up ears, head turned towards the stimulus, increased muscular tension, etc. 11 A central notion of this theory is ‘Shannon capacity’, which is a measure of information flow rate that is inherently probabilistic. It uses the reduction in the entropy (which is a global measure of ) of a probability as the measure of information flow.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 8 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

During this period, Cherry (1953) conducted one of the seminal works on the problem of selective attention12 also known as “the cock- tail party phenomenon,13” as he himself called it. He used a proce- dure called dichotic listening in which he presented different messag- es to ear through headphones. This experiment showed that when subjects are told to listen to two streams of words in different ears, they selectively attend to one stream. Broadbent (1952) built on Cher- ry’s experiments and developed the first complete model of selective attention called Filter Theory (Broadbent, 1958). This model assumes that information selection occurs at a very early stage with no guaran- tee that the selected information is relevant to the task14. Anne Treis- man (1960), who is one of the most influential cognitive psychologist15 reformulated it into a more flexible version called the Filter-

12 Selective attention is often loosely defined. A few definitions from the literature are: “The differential processing of simultaneous sources of information” (John- son and Dark, 1986, 44); “A system of cognitive processes that manages the bur- den of having too much to do at once by prioritizing among stimuli to be pro- cessed” (Carr, 2004, 56); and “the generic term for those mechanisms which lead our experience to be dominated by one thing rather than another” (Driver, 2001, 53). Nowadays, one point of agreement is that selective attention is a broad con- cept covering many distinct mechanisms operating in a variety of brain systems, if not the entire system rather than one specific function or mechanism as some scientists maintained. For instance, Posner (2004) localized this function in the “attentional organ system”, LaBerge (1997) in the “triangular circuit” and McKnight (2007) in the synchronization of activity between prefrontal, parietal and mediotemporal cortex. 13 The illustrates the ability to focus our listening on a single talker among a mixture of conversations and background noises, and to pay at- tention to a stimulus that grabs our attention suddenly, such as our names. 14 Broadbent (1952) conducted an experiment of dichotic listening in which par- ticipants were instructed to answer a series of Yes-No questions about a visual display over a radio-telephone. For example, the participants would be asked “S- 1 from G.D.O. Is there a heart on Position 1? Over”, to which the participants should answer “G.D.O. from S-1. Yes, over.” The participants were assigned to five different groups and their ability to answer one of two messages delivered at the same time (but one of which was irrelevant) was tested under varying con- texts that manipulate information given by the instructor (through visual or audi- tory cues) concerning which of the two voices is to be answered. In the first four groups, participants heard two successive series of messages, in which two voices (G.D.O. and Turret) spoke simultaneously during some of the messages. In the fifth group, they heard two new recordings that permit to make simultaneous messages more distinct than for the other groups in addition to the recordings of group I, II, III and IV. Results indicate that visual cue to the correct voice is use- less, thus suggesting that process of discarding part of the information contained in the mixed voices has already taken place. 15 Anne Treisman did her PhD in Oxford, when she met and marry three years later Michel Treisman, another Oxford graduate student. She remarried in 1978 to . Shortly after, they accepted positions at the University of Brit- ish Columbia, Canada.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 9

Attenuation Theory. The working hypothesis of this theory is that processing of unattended information is attenuated or reduced, rather than completely filtered out, accounting for the fact that unattended information sometimes reaches consciousness. In brief, the development of information-processing cognitive psy- chology during this period was first punctuated by debates as to whether the selection filter operated before or after cognitive pro- cessing (early vs. late selection models of attention16). But modern psychology also evolved along two main paths that gave rise to the differentiation between filter and executive attention theories17. Executive attention18 theories can be best defined by referring to Kahneman’s (1973) famous model of attention. They emerged in the early 70s when a shift in the study of attention occurred: from exper- iments mainly based on auditory tasks towards experiments involv-

16 Broadbent (1958) and Treisman (1969) concluded in favor of early selection models, showing that attention shuts down or attenuates processing in the unat- tended ear before the mind can analyze its semantic content. At the opposite, Deutsch and Deutsch (1963) supported the late selection view by showing that the content in both ears is analyzed semantically, even if the words in the unat- tended ear cannot access consciousness. Results like that of MacKay (1973) posed problems for filters theories, by showing that even unconscious stimuli could be processed to a high degree. For a survey on the early literature on attention in psychology, see Kahneman and Treisman (1984). 17 Pashler (1998) summarizes the empirical evidence obtained in attention psy- chology and asserts that capacity limits and perceptual gating both characterize human perceptual processing (Pashler, 1998, 224). According to this author, many controversies in psychology research result from the fact that some re- searchers identify the concept of attention with the allocation of a limited pro- cessing capacity to a given set of items, while others relate attention to the selec- tion of this set by a gating mechanism. The gating mechanism implies that mental resources are allocated only to those items that have passed the perceptual filter, while the rest is ignored. Wickens (1980) refers to Kahneman’s model as an approach focusing on the ‘en- ergetic’ side of attention as compared to filter theories that focus on its ‘selective’ side. As summarized by Ruz, “whereas selection theories aimed at localizing the point in the processing chain (from perception to motor responses) at which irrel- evant stimuli were filtered out (i.e., the location of the ‘bottleneck’), energetic views investigated how resources were divided among tasks or the unitary or multiple nature of this ‘attentional energy’.” (Ruz, 2006, 499) 18 The notion of executive attention is even more loosely defined that the one of selective attention. It was defined by Posner and Rothbart (1998) as “the regula- tion of thought, emotion and behavior” (Posner and Rothbart, 1998, 1915). Nor- man and Shallice included planning, conflict resolution, decision-making, error correction, and overcoming habitual responses to perform novel or difficult tasks as executive processes (Norman and Shallice, 1986, 2-3). Nowadays, the consen- sus seems to be that executive attention involves centralized supervisory control, which requires two important functions 1) information about and 2) causal influ- ence over the things supervised and controlled.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 10 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

ing visual tasks. Contrary to filter theories that focused on selective attention, Kahneman’s model was based on the idea that there is one central resource capacity for attention (based in the frontal cortex) for which all activities requiring attention compete19. Research on atten- tion blossomed during the last quarter of the 20th century and many studies emanating from multiple source models corroborated the as- sumption that it is easier to perform two tasks together when the tasks use different stimulus or response modalities than when they use the same modalities. Treisman and Gelade (1980) published a seminal paper in which the very influential Feature Integration Theo- ry was propounded. This theory extended the Spotlight theory of vis- ual attention20, which assumed that it was possible to change the fo- cus . Attention is now viewed by some psychologists as functioning as networks connecting distributed areas of the brain, although these “networks support not only the general functions of attention com- mon to all people, but also the individual differences that relate to aspects of temperament and .” (Posner and Rothbart, 2007, 18) In a nutshell, in recent years, there has been extensive research aimed at supporting the production of mental taxonomy, with con- verging evidence coming from different domains (psychology, psy- chophysiology, cognitive sciences, , and so on). More- over, the idea of selective attention is now studied from different per- spectives in the social sciences21.

19 In passing, it is to be noted that this model derives from Kahneman’s dual-task system based on the differentiation between endogenous (voluntary) and exoge- nous (involuntary/automatic) control. In Kahneman’s (1973) words, voluntary attention means that the subject’s attention is driven towards because they are relevant to a task that he has chosen to perform (Kahneman, 1973, 4), whereas “involuntary attention is related to level of arousal, which is largely controlled by the properties of the stimuli to which an organism is exposed” (ibid., 3). Kahne- man’s model of executive attention has been criticized on the ground that it in- volves a “homunculus problem”: to wit, “a little man inside the brain” (Allport, 1980, 113) who directs attention. For Stinson (2009), this homunculus problem is attached to all theories of attention where executive attention is thought of as a cause rather than an effect. Moreover, Stinson argues that neither empirical evi- dences in neurosciences nor computational models purporting to support causal executive theories of attention can set down the issue in a satisfactory way. 20 Spotlight theory of visual attention (Posner et al., 1980) assumed that subjects are able to shift their spotlight of attention from location to location, independent- ly and prior to eye position, and adjust the size of the attended region like a zoom length. However, the theory assumed that the attentional spotlight cannot divide across multiple locations. 21 A an example, eye tracking is used to analyze the way individuals read and then learn to read (see for example, Just and Carpenter, 1980; Baccino and Ma- nunta, 2005) but also the effects of advertising (Pieters, Rosenberg and Wedel, 1999; Pieters, Wedel and Zhang, 2009) and more generally the relations between

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 11

Let us know investigate how the notion of attention penetrated the field of economics. Robert Lanham22 (2006), who attempts to trace the intellectual roots of what he calls the “economics of attention,” refers to Simon but also to Gregory Bateson and as fore- runners. For the sake of conciseness and homogeneity, we shall put aside the contribution of Gregory Bateson, which, albeit very interest- ing23, cannot be directly linked to the development of today’s eco- nomics. Besides, we will pay special attention to the contribution of Michael Polanyi, whose epistemological stance at the nature of knowledge is valuable for current economic analysis.

3. The Diffusion of the Notion of Attention in Economics: A History of Economic Thought Perspective The notion of attention penetrated the realm of economics and organ- izational sciences through various authors who can be characterized by a strong interest in multidisciplinary approaches and in particular, psychology, organization science as well as epistemology and philos- ophy of science.

3.1. Herbert Simon Regarding the topic of attention, Herbert Simon24 first observed the simple but fundamental connection between information and atten- tion: eye movements and individuals’ behavior: see, e.g. Arieli et al. (2011) who use eye tracking techniques in order to investigate how people choose between two lotteries. 22 Robert Lanham is Professor emeritus of English literature at UCLA. His book The Economics of Attention is about the move from an based on things and objects to an economics of attention where the central commodity is not stuff but style, i.e., what he labels fluff, for style is what competes for our at- tention amid the din and deluge of new media in order for us to make sense of overflowing information. 23 In particular, in Steps to an Ecology of Mind (1972), Gregory Bateson insisted on the of conscious attention, an economy he labelled ‘systemic awareness’, and focused on the cognitive and emotional aspects of ecological knowledge. The notion of ecological knowledge is related to the idea that socio-cultural and eco- logical relationships link any learning object with its context matter. Because rela- tionships transform both the knower and the known, individual minds may be disconnected from each other and from nature. 24 Herbert A. Simon, who was awarded the in Economics in 1978 for his pioneering research into the decision-making process within economic organ- izations, was an American and (with a Ph.D. in political science from the University of Chicago in 1942) whose research ranged across the fields of cognitive psychology, computer science, public administration, econom- ics, management, philosophy of science and sociology. He was the Richard King Mellon Professor of Computer Science and Psychology at Carnegie Mellon Uni-

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 12 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

What information consumes is rather obvious: it consumes the attention of its consumers. Hence a wealth of information creates a poverty of atten- tion and a need to allocate that attention efficiently among the overabun- dance of information sources that might consume it. (Simon, 1971, 40) Retrospectively, Simon’s contribution regarding attention may be characterized by a dual emphasis on cognition (limited attention ca- pacity) and structure (how organization shapes individual’s atten- tion). In his early work on administrative behaviour (1947), he empha- sized that the well-known ‘bounded rationality’ assumption hinges on the limited attentional capability of humans and serves as a justifi- cation for the existence of organizations and institutions as means of orienting attention. As Simon wrote, “organizations and institutions provide the general stimuli and attention-directors that channelize the behaviors of the members of the group, and that provide the members with the intermediate objectives that stimulate action” (Si- mon, 1947, 100-101). Later in The Science of the Artificial (1969) he emphasized the role played by , pointing out both its limits and its organi- zation. Borrowing from the work of the Dutch A. de Groot on chess, he explained that visual memory is related to the attention that chess players put on some emerging features of the arrangement of the pieces on the chess board that have been printed in their brain as a result of abstraction from previous play and experience. It is what Simon names intuition conceived as a process of subconscious pattern recognition25: Evidence about the nature of the of ‘visual’ images, pointing in the same direction as the example I have just given, is provided by the well- known experiments of A. de Groot [in the 40s] and others on chess percep- tion [see De Groot 1966]. De Groot put chess positions – taken from actual games – before subjects for, say five seconds; then he removed the posi- tions and asked the subjects to reconstruct them. Chess grandmasters and masters could reconstruct the positions (with perhaps 20 to 24 pieces on the board) almost without error, while duffers were able to locate hardly

versity in Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania, where he taught for 52 years. Simon was among the founding fathers of artificial , information processing, de- cision-making, problem-solving, attention economics, organization theory, com- plex systems, and computer simulation of scientific discovery. He was the first to analyze the architecture of complexity (Simon, 1962). As well as receiving the highest honor possible in economics, he was the recipient of the American Psy- chological Association’s Award for Outstanding Lifetime Contributions to Psy- chology in 1993, and the prestigious A. M. Turing Award for his work in com- puter science (1975). 25 “The process is subconscious pattern recognition based on experiences stored in memory and retrieved when necessary. While short term memory can store only small amount of information, long term memory is, metaphorically speak- ing, a large encyclopedia with an elaborated index in which information is cross- referenced.” (Frantz, 2003, 270)

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 13

any of the pieces correctly and the performance of players of intermediate skill fell somewhat between masters and duffers. But the remarkable fact was that, when masters and grandmasters where shown other chess boards with the same numbers of pieces arranged at random, their abilities to reconstruct the boards were only marginally better than the duffers’ with the boards from actual games, while the duffers performed as well or poorly as they had before. (Simon, [1969] 1996, 71-72) In other terms, previous experiments serve as a selection device that facilitates problem solving by focusing attention on a few characteris- tics only. Newell and Simon’s symbolic framework (1973) is based on the idea that information processing is about the manipulation of rep- resentations. For Simon, information processing psychology permits to explain what people really do when they have to take difficult de- cisions and solve complex problems: Information processing theories envisage problem solving as involving very selective search through problem spaces that are often immense. Se- lectivity, based on rules of thumb or ‘heuristics’, tends to guide the search into promising regions, so that solutions will generally be found after search of only a tiny part of the total space. Satisficing criteria terminate search when satisfactory problem solutions have been found. (Simon, 1978, 362) Therefore, problem solving is all about design and abstraction and requires mechanisms that permit to hierarchize and select from a vast array of information. The role of the near-decomposability of a prob- lem into sub-problems is a mean that facilitates problem-solving, that is, the search of solutions26. This has to be linked with Simon’s idea that social sciences have to borrow methods and tools that natural sciences have developed. It is the reason why he conceived the hu- man problem-solving process as similar to computer/software pro- gramming27. Those mechanisms are assimilated to pre-stored schemata or prior knowledge based on previous experience that attract our attention and permit to economize on trial-and-error search. As Simon wrote: We see this particularly clearly when the problem to be solved is similar to one that has been solved before. Then, by simply trying again the paths

26 “Recently the near-decomposability hypothesis has been renamed ‘modularity hypothesis’ and is pervading diverse disciplines, ranging from software design (where the object-oriented programming paradigm is nothing but a prescription of highly modular system) to management science (where largely the same prin- ciple are applied to the organization of firms and manufacturing systems).” (Egidi and Marengo, 2004, 342-343). Fodor (1983) is an attempt to apply the mod- ularity hypothesis to cognitive sciences. 27 “I have argued that an epistemology for computers is possible because com- puters do think.” (Simon, 1989, 19)

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 14 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

that led to the earlier solution, or their analogues, trial-and-error search is greatly reduced or altogether eliminated. (Simon [1969], 1996, 196-197)28 As we know, Simon’s influence first penetrated the field of organiza- tion theory, where the concept of attention has a long history and tra- dition. Different authors have stressed different aspects of attention allocation and structuring, but not in a unified perspective. In particu- lar, they have emphasized either attention as shaped by routines and bounded rationality (March and Simon, 1958; Cyert and March, 1963), or alternatively, as loosely coupled through enactment processes29 (Weick, 1979) and organized anarchy30 (Cohen, March and Olsen, 1972). More recently, there have been some developments in managerial sciences that borrow from Simon’s look at attentional problems in organizations. For instance Ocasio (1997) laments the lack of interest of scholars to study “the effects of the social structure on the channel- ling and distribution of decision-makers” (Ocasio, 1997, 188). He in- stead tries to develop an explanation for firm behaviour based on the structuring of organizational attention. Organization attention pro- cessing and regulation is shown to be the result of three principles: (1) At the level of individual cognition, the principle of focus of attention links attentional processing to individual cognition and behaviour; (2) at the level of social cognition, the principle of situated attention high- lights the importance of the situational context in explaining what decision-makers attend to; (3) at the organizational level, the principle of structural distribution of attention explains how the firm’s econom- ic and social structures regulate and channel issues, answers, and de- cision-makers into the activities, communications, and procedures that constitute the situational context of decision-making.

28 Interestingly the ideas of memory and similarity are at the basis of the Cased- Based (CBDT) developed by Gilboa and Schmeidler (1995). “CBDT has some common features with the notion of ‘satisficing’ decisions of Simon (1957) and March and Simon (1958), and may be viewed as formalizing this idea.” (612). 29 Weick describes the term enactment as representing the notion that when peo- ple act they bring structures and events into existence and set them in action. Weick uses this term in the context of ‘sensemaking’ by managers or employees. He also describes how they can enact ‘limitations’ upon the system to avoid is- sues or experiences. It is also seen as a form of social construction. To date enact- ment is related to organizations and their environment and strategic manage- ment. 30 Organized anarchies are associated with the so-called “garbage can model” of decision making. They correspond to organizations, such as universities, which fail to adhere to the conditions of more classical models of decision making in some or all of three important ways: preferences are problematic, technology is unclear, or participation is “fluid”, i.e., it involves formal and informal groups at all levels, all interacting at various levels of the organization, all increasing vari- ous levels of complexity.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 15

Rerup (2010) extends Ocasio’s framework by focusing not only on top-down senior management processes in directing attention but also on their synchronization with bottom-up processes, which are ignored by Ocasio’s approach. According to Rerup, “an attention de- lay denotes the time it takes to make a non-salient issue salient to top management.” His approach consists in combining “theories of or- ganizational attention and coordination to propose that attention de- lays can be mitigated when organizations develop designs that gen- erate ‘synchronized prospective attention’, through which an organi- zation’s different hierarchical levels proactively and iteratively con- sider the future impact that non-salient issues might have.” (Rerup, 2010, 4) This “synchronized prospective attention” is of prime im- portance when non-salient but potentially very damaging threats are involved in organizations. These situations are characteristic of the health care sector (Madsen et al. 2006), of military or intelligence ac- tivities (Baker and Hulse, 2009), or of air traffic control, were organi- zations need to swiftly allocate attention to emerging issues. To sum up, one of the major contributions of Simon is to have stressed the dual – cognitive (individual) and structural (organiza- tional) –aspect of human decision-making. This led him to consider attention, conceived as a device highly related to abstraction and simplification in the context of overabundance of information, as a key device in problem solving. He also explored the overwhelming theoretical and empirical implications of the interplay between cogni- tion and structure in a vast array of fields such as information pro- cessing, organizational design or scientific research in general. As will be developed next, Friedrich Hayek was also deeply interested in the attentional aspects of human cognition, though from a different per- spective.

3.2. Friedrich Hayek Friedrich Hayek can also be considered as a major forerunner of the economics of attention. His interest for the role of attention is highly related to his conception of knowledge, as developed in The Sensory Order (1952), a contribution to theoretical cognitive psychology he wrote in the 20s but only published in the 50s31. Hayek contempora-

31 The curious context in which Hayek developed his ideas is worth to be re- minded. In the winter of 1919-1920 a fuel and forced closure of the Uni- versity of Vienna presented Hayek with an opportunity to spend a few weeks in Zurich working in the laboratory of the brain anatomist Constantin von Mona- kow, tracing fiber bundles of the brain (cf. Hayek, 1994, 63-64). A few months later, Hayek wrote the initial working material for The Sensory Order, a student paper manuscript entitled “Beiträge zur Theorie der Entwicklung des Bewusst- seins”. As emphasized by Caldwell (2004), Hayek’s endeavor was to challenge the dominant doctrine in psychology known as the “doctrine of psycho- physiological parallelism” endorsed by Ernst Mach and few others in Vienna.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 16 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

neously described The Sensory Order as “the most important thing I have ever done.” (letter to John Nef, dated 6 November 1948, cited from Caldwell, 1997, 1856) Unfortunately, as noted by Butos and Koppl (2007), despite the recognition Hayek’s cognitive theory has received from outside economics by scholars such as Gerald Edel- man32, Joaquin Fuster and Edward Boring, its influence for research- ers in economics and the social sciences must be described at best tangential (Butos and Koppl, 2007, 35). Hayek’s innovative idea at the core of The Sensory Order is that mind functions as a classification system which permits to connect, though not in a one-to-one mapping, the order of physical stimuli or objects with the order of mental states or categories. This process of classification involves what Hayek will later refer in his 1978 paper “The Primacy of the Abstract” as “specification by superimposition” (Hayek, 1978, 48). In The Sensory Order, he used the analogy of a topo- logical ‘map’ and explains how different vertically sub-systems of neural connexions form a pyramid of partial maps operating at dif- ferent levels of abstraction or generality33: Every sub-system of this kind will constitute a partial map of the envi- ronment, and the maps formed at the lower levels will serve for the guid- ance of merely a limited range of responses, and at the same time act as fil- ters or preselectors for the impulses sent on the higher centers, for which in turn, the maps of the lower levels constitute a part of the environment. (Hayek, 1952, 111)

Hayek is indeed very skeptical of the existence of one-to-one correspondence between an external stimulus and the experience of a sensation (Caldwell, 2004, 140). Hayek’s interest in the role of knowledge in economics is also illustrated by two famous articles: “Economics and Knowledge” (1937) and “The use of infor- mation in society” (1945). 32 Gerald Edelman who won the Nobel Prize in Physiology in 1972 confesses that he has been inspired by some of Hayek’s ideas on neuronal selection: “I must say that I have been deeply gratified by reading a book [Hayek’s The Sensory Order] of which I had not been aware when I wrote my little essay on group selection theo- ry…I was deeply impressed…I recommend this book to your attention [i.e. The American Academy of Arts and Sciences], as an exercise in profound thinking by a man who simply considers knowledge for its own sake. What impressed me most is his understanding that the key to the problem of perception is to compre- hend the nature of classification. Taxonomists have struggled with this problem many times, but I think Hayek considered this problem in a broader sense.” (Gerald Edelman, “Through a Computer Darkly: Group Selection and Higher Brain Function”, Bulletin — The American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Vol. XXXVI, No. 1, Oct. 1982, 24). Other scientists outside economics have praised Hayek’s contribution. According to Steele (2002), Hayek’s Sensory Order also fore- shadows Henry Potkin’s evolutionary epistemology. 33 “As the classification becomes…more ‘general’ and less ‘specific’, the classify- ing event also becomes more and more definitely a central process while the rela- tions to any particular peripheral response become at the same time more remote and round-about.” (Hayek, 1952, 113).

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 17

This semi-permanent structure provides an apparatus for classifica- tion and orientation of the impulses from neuron to neuron, which derives from past experience and exists “independently of the partic- ular impulses proceeding in it at a given moment” (Hayek, 1952, 115). The map is partly innate, partly related to previous experience, which implies that it has a certain degree of autonomy vis-à-vis the neural impulses. Moreover, it is specific to each individual. What Hayek re- fers to as “the model” by contrast is made by “the flow of impulses which at any moment trace a further pattern which will have signifi- cance only by its position in that structural framework [the map, add- ed by us] within which it moves” (Hayek, 1952, 116) and with regard to the “attitudes”, “sets” or “dispositions” that follow from certain “emotions”, “needs” or “drives” (Hayek, 1952, 96-97). The combina- tion of the map and the model determines behaviour and action: “It is only through the superimposition of many classifications and disposi- tions that a particular action is specified.” (Hayek, 1978, 40) A logical consequence of this conception of the mind is that it en- tails some fundamental limitations of knowledge: “We shall never be able to achieve more than an explanation of the principle, on which mind operates, and shall never succeed in fully explaining any par- ticular mental act.” (Hayek, 1952, 35) This is so because sensory per- ception must be viewed as an act of classification that abstracts from the physical world and “always precede[s] the more abstract mental contents.” (Hayek, 1952, 137) As Hayek stated it: “What we perceive are never unique properties which the objects have in common with other objects. Perception is thus always an interpretation, the placing of something into one or several classes of objects.” (Hayek, 1952, xviii)34 From this it results that consciousness is nothing else in natura that a classification system which distinctive feature is that it is “associat- ed with the highest degree of generality of classification or evalua- tion.” (Hayek, 1952, 137) Moreover, it is impossible to define it properly or to have a precise recognition of the mental facts it entails, due to the limits of knowledge the classification systems inherently entails. This is why Hayek thinks that, in order to discriminate be- tween consciousness and unconsciousness, it is more useful to con- centrate on what consciousness does rather than on what conscious- ness is (ibid., 133). Hayek explains that one of the criteria of con- sciousness is its unity, i.e., a close connexion between all conscious events (ibid., 136), while unconsciousness which occurs at different strata of decreasing abstraction is characterized by its diversity. The

34 This quotation can be paralleled with Edelman’s one: “A closed universal de- scription of objects is not available to an adaptive creature, even to one with con- cepts; there is no “voice in the burning bush” telling that animals what the world description should be.” (Edelman, 1989, 32)

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 18 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

unity of consciousness means that consciousness deals with a com- mon space-time framework, which is only the emerged part of the iceberg, apparently separate from the foundations, i.e., the different levels of neural connexions that gave rise to it: “Conscious experienc- es have in this respect justly been compared to mountain tops rising above the clouds which, while alone visible, yet presuppose an invis- ible substructure determining their position relative to each other.” (ibid., 33)35 Now, it is interesting to emphasize how Hayek distinguishes at- tention from consciousness. At first sight, and judging by his refer- ence to Boring’s view that “consciousness is attentive, attention is se- lective, consciousness is selective” (Boring, 1933, 231-232; quoted by Hayek, 1952, 139), Hayek seems to conceive attention as almost syn- onymous to consciousness. But on the other hand, he made clear that attention slightly differs from consciousness for being concerned mainly with events that are in some sense expected or anticipated: It is a “characteristic of attention that it has these effects” of greater dis- crimination “only with regards to events which are in some sense ex- pected or anticipated”: Attention “is thus always directed, or con- fined to a particular class of events for which we are on the look-out and which, in consequence, we perceive with greater distinctness when one of them occurs.” (Hayek, 1952, 139) From this perspective, attention is most correctly described by its anticipatory character or by being a “state of excitatory prepared- ness”, which is not confined to the conscious level (ibid., 140). For in- stance, hypnotic practices can illustrate this feature of attention (in this case, involuntary attention) occurring at remote level of uncon- sciousness. Another characteristic of attention is provided by its complemen- tarity with abstractness: perception based on abstraction, namely on general or generic attributes, of the perceived objects may be supple- mented by “directing our attention to more specific or particular fea- tures” (ibid., 145). Therefore it is as if attention permitted to highlight some of the patterns involved in the model directing behavior and therefore made us more aware of the mental events resulting from them. Attention is therefore a special instance of the more general category that Hayek labels “the model”, which is linked to the “dis- positions” or the “sets” of individuals (Hayek, 1952, 140).

35 In passing, this is one of the reasons why Hayek has some difficulty to deal with intentionality and has recourse to the idea of spontaneous order, being the result of human action and not of human design. But this argument should be qualified by taking into account the plasticity and mutability of the classification structure of the brain. The cognitive process, according to Hayek, despite being constrained by tacit rules and its own physiology, has “the capacity for self- conscious and reflective activity” since it is an “active, input-transforming knowledge generating adaptive system.” (Butos and Koppl, 2006, 39)

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 19

Moreover, and interestingly enough for the diffusion of knowledge and inter-individual coordination, this individual apti- tude to focus on special events and trace back the process of abstrac- tion that gave rise to them “also provides the condition for the indi- vidual to participate in a social or conventional representation of the world which he shares with his fellows.” (Hayek, 1952, 142) This leads us to endorse the view that The Sensory Order is of great interest not only as a piece of per se but also because it captures Hayek’s conception of knowledge. The latter, in turn, is essential in order to reach a synthetic view of his overall con- tribution, and in particular to understand how he characterized mar- ket mechanisms36. As emphasized by Butos and Koppl (2006) and contrary to other commentators of Hayek who endorse the disconti- nuity thesis37, the Sensory Order perspective can be applied, not only to the problem of (discovery and use) of knowledge – as it often re- duced to – but also to the understanding and “analysis of different social arrangements and structures” which produce orders that are “not simply aggregations of agents and their capacities” but involve “a transformation of knowledge into a unique kind of social knowledge that could not have been otherwise produced.” (Butos and Koppl, 2006, 40) Contrary to many interpretations, neither the idea of division of knowledge among individuals (i.e., the knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and space), nor the distinction between theoret- ical knowledge and the knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and space (Hayek, 1945, 521) are sufficient to explain why Hayek

36 In this perspective, it is interesting to note that Simon praised Hayek for his way to characterize market mechanisms: “No one has characterized market mechanisms better than Friedrich Hayek.” (Simon, The Sciences of the Artificial, 2nd Edition, Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1981, 41). The idea of an analogy be- tween the brain and the organization of markets has been a source of inspiration for many researchers in social sciences, and has valuable implications for eco- nomic analysis even if, in economics, the interest for cognition and psychology has experiences several setbacks. 37 Early interpretations (see Machlup, 1974 or Runde, 1988) view The Sensory Order as ancillary to the rest Hayek’s work on philosophy, politics, and econom- ics. More recent interpretations (see Birner, 1999 or Vanberg, 2004) consider Hay- ek’s writings on cognitive psychology mostly as a methodological contribution disconnected from his economics. This is surprising, judging from the central role played by and expectations in Hayek’s theory. As Birner puts it: “Contrary to what might expect, however, none of the mental mechanisms of his earlier theory on perception and cognition play a part in his economics.” (Birner, 1999, 43). At the opposite, Caldwell (2004) or Butos and Koppl (2006) seem to consider that The Sensory Order is foundation work in Hay- ek’s economics. D’Amico and Boettke (2010) endorse a more qualified view, by inversing the causality: “It is Hayek’s vision of the working economy that is the key to understand his theoretical psychology” and not the other way around (D’Amico and Boettke, 2010, 360).

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 20 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

considers that socialist planning is not an efficient coordination mechanism. As rightly pointed out by Butos and McQuade (2002), “it is strictly incorrect to say that the market gathers up ‘divided’ indi- vidual knowledge and makes the information available to many oth- ers…Instead, the market takes, as input knowledge in the initial sense…and classifies this, producing a totally different kind of knowledge.” (Butos and McQuade, 2002, 128) As Hayek claims: “Knowledge which any individual mind consciously manipulates is only a small part of the knowledge which at any one time contributes to the success of his action.” (Hayek, 1960, 24) In retrospect, Hayek’s concern for the economics of attention is conceptually-related to his conception of the nature of knowledge. This lead him to consider attention as a way to circumvent the limits of knowledge due to its fragmented nature (1) by permitting a higher degree of awareness on the causality between peculiar circumstances and the specific outcome they give rise to in a context of excitatory preparedness and (2) by providing the conditions for individuals to communicate between each other since they are conscious to share the same cognitive structures in particular abstracting abilities. As will be developed in the next sub-section, Michael Polanyi also focused on the limits of knowledge in many of his writings. It is therefore quite natural to consider him as another forerunner of the economics of attention.

3.3. Michael Polanyi Michael Polanyi was an eclectic scientist (from medicine to research in physical chemistry, economics, social and political analysis) but also a philosopher with strong in theology and aesthetics. He was the brother of the well-known economist Karl Polanyi and the father of John Polanyi who won the Nobel Prize in chemistry in 1986. As Hayek, Michael Polanyi focused on the tacit dimension of knowledge and related it to the concept of integration. For Polanyi, tacit knowledge is a key component of all kind of knowledge, scien- tific, artistic or religious. He emphasizes that “all knowledge is either tacit or rooted in tacit knowledge. A wholly explicit knowledge is un- thinkable” (Polanyi, 1966a, 7). This is the main reason why he con- stantly insisted on the fundamental indeterminacy of science: “Scien- tific discovery cannot be achieved by explicit inference, nor can its true claims be explicitly stated. Discovery must be arrived at by the tacit powers of the mind and its content, so far as it is indeterminate, can be only tacitly known.” (Polanyi, 1966, 1) The intellectual roots of Michael Polanyi’s thought can be traced back to both Gestalt psychol- ogy38 and Piaget’s theory of intellectual development. Accordingly,

38 is a theory of mind and brain, which considers that the brain is holistic, parallel and analog, with self-organizing tendencies. This suggests that

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 21

tacit knowledge is conceived as the result of a process of integration or “tacit inference” (Polanyi, 1966a) that involves two kinds of cogni- tive systems: one which he describes as the “proximal term of tacit knowing” and the other, described as the “distal term of tacit know- ing”: [The] act of integration, which we can identify both in the visual percep- tion of objects and in the discovery of scientific theory, is the tacit power we have been looking for. I shall call it tacit knowing. It will facilitate my discussion of tacit knowing if I speak of the clues or parts that are subsidi- arily known as the proximal term of tacit knowing and of that which is fo- cally known as the distal term of tacit knowing.” (Polanyi, 1966a, 73)39 What is original in Polanyi is that he uses seeing as a paradigm for knowing. A basic element in Polanyi’s account of tacit knowledge is indeed the distinction between two kinds of awareness (subsidiary vs. focal awareness), inspired from stereoscopic pictures40, which ex- emplify this dual process of cognition. Focal awareness is the ordinary kind of full awareness we have in focusing attention on a specifiable object. Subsidiary awareness, in contrast, refers to the more remote pe- ripheral noticing of the features of an object that are not attended to in themselves but seen as pointers or clues to the object of focal atten- tion. Polanyi also refers to subsidiary awareness as from-awareness since he says that we attend from subsidiary particulars to an entity under scrutiny, and calls the relation between the particulars and the whole entity the “from to relation” (Polanyi, 1966a, 146). In a nutshell, the two kinds of awareness are linked by a logical re- lation (the relation between clues and the image to which the clues are pointing), which is similar to the relation between body and mind41 and explain both the roots and the dynamic features of our personal knowledge: “The tracing of personal knowledge to its roots in the subsidiary awareness of our body as merged in our focal the human beings see objects in their entirety before perceiving their component parts. 39 In The Body-Mind Relation, Polanyi writes: “When I point my finger at a wall and call out: ‘Look at this!’ all eyes turn to wall, away from my finger. You are clearly attending to my pointing finger, but only in order to look at something; namely the point to which my finger is directing your attention.” (Polanyi, 1968, 85) The finger is the proximal term although the wall is the distal one. 40 Stereoscopy refers to the techniques used by 3D imaging for creating or en- hancing the illusion of depth in an image by means of stereopsis for binocular vision. Most stereoscopic methods present two offset images separately to the left and right eye of the viewer (a metaphor for subsidiary awareness). These two- dimensional are then combined in the brain to give the perception of 3D depth (a metaphor for focal awareness). 41 “The purpose of this paper is to show that the relation between body and mind has the same logical structure as the relation between clues and the image to which the clues are pointing. I suggest that the body is a subsidiary thing which bears on the mind which is its meaning.” (Polanyi, 1968, 90; italics in the original)

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 22 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

awareness of external objects, reveal not only the logical structure of our personal knowledge but also its dynamic sources.” (Polanyi, 1962, 60) Moreover, focal and subsidiary awareness are mutually exclusive relative to sense making. As Polanyi states it in Personal Knowledge, “…in our from-awareness of a thing we see it as having a meaning, a meaning which is wiped out when we focus our attention [focal awareness] on the thing of which we have only had a from- awareness.” (Polanyi, 1975, 39) In other terms, the specificity of from- awareness is that it is sense making, whereas the functional character- istic of focal awareness lies in it being sense depriving. But for Po- lanyi, attention is sense depriving not due to cognitive limitations. We may be able to specify all the items or subsidiary clues that are enter- ing into an integrated meaning. But when focal attention is directed on a subsidiary clue, “it turns into a different thing deprived of the meaning it had while serving as a subsidiary” (Polanyi, 1975, 39). For this reason subsidiary clues are “essentially unspecifiable”: “We must distinguish…between two types of unspecifiability of subsidiar- ies. One type is due to the difficulty of tracing the subsidiaries – a condition that is widespread but not universal; the other type is due to a sense deprivation which is logically necessary and in principle absolute.” (ibid., 39) In other words, Polanyi distinguishes between two kinds of irre- versibility and shows why the process of tacit inference is not sym- metrical. The first one, i.e., contingent irreversibility, is due to our likely impossibility to identify all the clues we have integrated. The second one, i.e., logical irreversibility, on the other hand, always holds, and refers to the fact that when we go back to the subsidiaries we loose their joint meaning. This means that “a process of logical dis- integration has reduced a comprehensive entity to its entirely meaningless fragments.” (Polanyi, 1965, 800) This is the reason why, for Polanyi, “the process of formalizing all knowledge to the exclusion of tacit knowledge is self-defeating.” (Polanyi, [1966b], 2009, 20) and may have subversive implications since it may destroy the subject matter itself. Finally, the distinction between focal awareness and subsidiary awareness is not reducible to the distinction between consciousness and unconsciousness. For Polanyi, focal awareness is always fully conscious, while subsidiary awareness “can exist at any level of con- sciousness, ranging from the subliminal to the fully conscious”. Po- lanyi adds: “What makes awareness subsidiary is its functional char- acter…” (Polanyi, 1975, 39) To sum up, Polanyi’s account of attention is also related to the problem of knowledge but more focused on the process of tacit infer- ence, which logically goes from subsidiary to focal awareness, and its properties (sense depriving, not symmetrical, involving different lev-

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 23

els of consciousness). Polanyi also warns us against the of attention, i.e., its non-reversible sense depriving character.

4. The Economics of Attention Today: Taking Stock and Looking Ahead In this last section, we put the nowadays literature on the so-called ‘economics of attention’ in perspective with the insights of the previ- ous section. The main objective of this exercise is to suggest new di- rections of research that still need to be developed. Two of the fore- runners of economics of attention, Hayek and Polanyi do not inspire recent literature dealing with attention. As for Hayek (see below) his conception of information and knowledge seems to be the main ex- planation of this lack of descent. Polanyi’s case is due, first to his ec- lecticism and, second to the fact that his conception of ‘awareness’ has been underrated as compared with his notion of ‘tacit knowledge’ that has been highly popularized by the economics of innovation and economics of knowledge as well. Very briefly there are two different approaches in economics that deal with attention economies. According to the first approach, attention economics is considered as a ramification of information economics, which derives from Shannon’s mathematical theory of communication (Shannon, 1948). From this perspective, attention is conceived, in compliance with the principles of the mathematical theory of communication (Shannon, 1948), as a function of the unlikelihood of an event to happen and of the frequency of similar past events (which provides a measure of the surprise or the degree of novelty). Consequently, an event that has never been experienced before is supposed to have a high sur- prise value and therefore to attract attention, even if it lacks any spe- cific associations or consequences. This seems however at odds with the diffused idea in cognitive psychology that attention depends on both the unexpectedness of events and of their familiar association. This drawback, together with the recognition of the incalculable effect of past experience on the information carried by any binary digit ul- timately led them to abandon information theory42. If cognitive psychology abandoned this direction, the information- economics approach instead adopted it. As well-known, this ap- proach assumes full rationality and considers sub-optimalities caused by asymmetric information and . Key empirical issues relate to information pollution and its solutions (technological tools, market-based mechanisms, or institutional arrangements and regulatory devices).

42 See for example Garrouste (2001).

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 24 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

Note that there is an alternative strand of formal approach to in- formation, which builds on Aumann’s seminal “Agreeing to disa- gree” theorem. This algebraic approach has become prominent in the economic literature and has given rise to recent developments dedi- cated to awareness43. But there is a second approach of economics of attention, which focuses on expectations and predictions and considers that cognitive limits of attention constitute behavioral foundations of bounded ra- tionality. Not surprisingly, the first approach of the literature on the eco- nomics of attention, as exemplified by Shapiro and Varian 1999’s Handbook Economics of Information and Networks considers attention as a scarce economic resource and discusses its empirical conse- quences for information users. More precisely, the literature analyses the various business strategies ( or product discrimination in the presence of network , switching costs, product sharing, etc.) to particularize information in order to catch users’ attention and increase their by providing them with more relevant infor- mation. But usually attention scarcity has an asymmetric impact on information users and providers. This explains that an important part of the literature is concerned with the problem of spamming. This problem is a typical case of or information pollution in a context of asymmetric information between the e-mail sender, who knows the contents of the message, and the receiver, who does not. It is a case of externality or information pollution the sender of the mes- sage imposes to the receiver. Three main solutions have been pro- posed, the technological, the institutional and the market-based one44. From our history of economic thought perspective, it is very interest- ing to note that Hotelling as soon as 1938 warned against the harmful effect of excess demand for attention on behalf of media and advertis- ing businesses, as the following quotation strikingly exemplifies: Another thing of limited quantity for which the demand exceeds the sup- ply is the attention of people. Attention is desired for a variety of commer- cial, political, and other purposes, and is obtained with the help of bill- boards, newspaper, radio, and other advertising. Expropriation of the at- tention of the general public and its commercial sale and exploitation con- stitute a lucrative business. From some aspects this business appears to be of a similar character to that of the medieval robber barons, and therefore to be an appropriate subject for prohibition by a state democratically con- trolled by those from whom their attention is stolen. But attention attract- ing of some kinds and in some degree is bound to persist; and where it

43 For the sake of brevity, we shall not review this literature. Cf. the website at http://www.econ.ucdavis.edu/faculty/schipper/unaw.htm for a bibliography. 44 See Kraut et al. (2002 2005), Van Alstyne, Loder, and Wash (2004), Zandt (2001) and Loder, Van Alstyne and Wash (2004) for a comparison of these alternative solutions.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 25

does, it may appropriately be taxed as a utilization of a limited resource. Taxation of advertising on this basis would be in addition to any taxation imposed for the purpose of diminishing its quantity with a view to restor- ing the property of attention to its rightful owners. (Hotelling, 1938, 257) To sum up, the economics of attention seen as a ramification of in- formation theory conveys two conflicting rationales for economic agents, depending on whether it focuses on the user or the provider of information: on one side we find economic and management mod- els that analyze how it is possible for firms to capture the attention of customers or audiences in order to make from it; on the other side there are analyses that focus on the overload of information from the viewpoint of consumers and provide solutions in order to protect the attention of users from information overload and pollution. Kessous, Mellet and Zouinar (2010) adopt an per- spective and interpret current innovations in the digital economy as attempts to reconcile customer relationship (CRM45) and vendor rela- tionship (VRM46) management practices. The literature on attention economics belonging to the second ap- proach borrows more explicitly from Simon, although, as we will de- velop, it can be split into two strands, which corroborates the tradi- tional dividing line between two distinct interpretations of Simon’s conception of bounded rationality: on one hand, the pars destruens, criticizing neoclassical view; on the other hand, the pars construens, consisting of an attempt to model behavior in a more realistic way (cf. Rizzello, 1999). According to the first interpretation, bounded ration- ality is seen as a limitation to human rationality. By contrast, the se- cond interpretation conceives bounded rationality as an adaptive ca- pacity. This conception is endorsed by the stream of ‘ecological ra- tionality’ (Smith, Nobel Lecture, 2002; Gigerenzer and Todd, 1999)

45 CRM is a widely implemented model for managing a company’s interactions with customers, clients, and sales prospects. It involves using technology to or- ganize, automate, and synchronize business processes—principally sales activi- ties, but also those for marketing, customer , and technical support. The overall goals are to find, attract, and win new clients; nurture and retain those the company already has; entice former clients back into the fold; and reduce the costs of marketing and client service. 46 Attentiontrust is an example of VRM practices. It consists of a set of principles to govern the attention economy on the self-ownership of the data we create, and specialized software to regulate their use. Specifically, AttentionTrust believes that we all have the right 1) to own at least a copy of our data, 2) to store that data where we want and move it when we want, 3) to exchange it for something of value to us, and 4) to know what others intend to do with our data, so that we can make informed decisions about who should have access to it. (http://www.attentiontrust.org/blog). More generally, VRM is a category of business activity made possible by software tools that provide customers with both independence from vendors and better means for engaging with vendors and is conceived as the necessary complement of CRM.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 26 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

according to which fast, information-economizing and frugal heuris- tics based on salient rules can be efficient means of reasoning. In par- ticular, the assumption that individuals neither look up nor integrate all information conveys a context-dependent conception of rationali- ty. In a nutshell, rationality is contingent to the institutional environ- ment and can only be measured in an evolutionary perspective. To be sure, the emerging macroeconomic literature on rational in- attention we have hinted at in the introduction is clearly to be related to the first interpretation, which acknowledges that attention is lim- ited, but restricts this limitation to a noise, which does not impair economic rationality. As emphasized by Sims (2003), the assumption of limited attention (or rational inattention) provides a microfounda- tion for economic behavior that looks enough like the familiar ration- al expectation assumption to ensure usefulness and tractability, even though the implications for policy are different enough to be interest- ing (Sims 2003, 1). Similarly, Akerlof, Dickens and Perry (2000) show that assuming near-rational and price setting in macroeconomic modeling on the ground that experimental observations show that agents have some cognitive biases in macroeconomic does not impair the robustness of the results, and is consistent with some empirical findings. In the same vein, Falkinger (2008) develops a general equi- librium model where agents are conceived as passive signal receivers characterized by limited attention and information providers are seeking to catch their attention by sending messages. The ability of agents to process an additional signal depends on the spared capacity left after the load imposed by exposure to other signals. Moreover, there exists a minimum (marginal) strength of a message in order for it to be perceived by the consumers. When total signal exposure lies below a certain level (this is the case of information-poor economies), there is no interference between different signals. Beyond this point (this is the case of information-rich economies) capacity limits lead to such interference. Falkinger concludes that information-rich econo- mies reach an inefficient equilibrium –and therefore faces some wel- fare losses– due to attention-seekers engaging in wasteful signalling in the for attention. But, to repeat it, in these kinds of models, the traditional assumption of economic rationality is pre- served. The other strand of the literature consisting of a second series of theoretical developments focusing on selective attention and problem solving (see, e.g., Gabaix et al., 2003; Gabaix et al., 2006; Schwartz- stein, 2010), by contrast, is more in line with the second interpretation of bounded rationality. These contributions provide models whose theoretical predictions are corroborated by some experiments. In par- ticular, they show how selective attention may lead individuals to persistently fail to recognize important empirical regularities, make biased forecasts, and hold incorrect beliefs about the statistical rela-

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 27

tionships between variables. This literature is linked to the notions of accessibility and salience put forward by Kahneman in his dual cog- nitive system based on the distinction between intuition (system 1) and reasoning (system 2), where he defines accessibility as “the ease with which particular mental contents come to mind” (Higgins, 1996, quoted by Kahneman in his 2002 Nobel Lecture; Kahneman, 2003, 1452) as well as to heuristics used as efficient means of solving prob- lems that we can find in Gigerenzer and Todd (1999). Interesting work based on both theoretical modeling and experiments47 by Ga- baix et al. (2005, 2006) supports the theoretical benchmark of partially myopic cognition due to limited but ‘efficient’ attention (what Gabaix and Laibson, 2005 call the ‘Directed Cognition model’) and the empir- ical existence of some heuristics48. Whether this second strand of the literature can be considered as a kind of middle ground between standard and ecological rationality is a question of interpretation. But given the -off between tractabil- ity and realism involved in theoretical modeling, this literature looks however very promising and reveals a more profound rupture with the classical conception of rationality in economics. But the problem does not limit itself to the question of rationality. Another classical drawback of information economics is that it is based on the mathematical theory of information introduced by Shannon (1948). One major drawback relates to the problem of the meaning of information, which, if it is not a concern in the mathemat- ical theory of information, becomes of utmost importance when deal- ing with attention. Whether we pay attention to somebody or some- thing can reasonably be expected to depend on how the same infor- mation is interpreted or perceived by different individuals or even by the same individual depending on the context49. Arrow (1974) already stressed that the same information can have very different value for different individuals. Boulding (1955) also emphasized that

47 The experimental design derives from previous work by Camerer et al. (1993), Camerer and Johnson (2004) and Costa-Gomes (2001). It uses the “Mouselab” programming language to measure subjects’ information acquisition. Information is hidden behind boxes on a computer screen and subjects have to use the com- puter mouse to open (or close) the boxes in order to get (costly) information that helps solving a problem (of income maximization) in a given limited period of time. On the one hand, Mouselab records permit to know the order and duration of information acquisition. On the other hand, since one screen box can be open at any time, it is possible to know what information is acquired on a second-by- second basis throughout the experiment. 48 In particular, they show that subjects tend to become more and more likely to end an analysis of a problem the more boxes they open holding fixed the eco- nomic benefit of additional analysis (what they call the ‘box heuristics’). 49 See Garrouste and Langlois (1997) for an appraisal of the problem of interpre- tation of information, and therefore, of its derived economic value, that econo- mists have to take into account seriously.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 28 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

we cannot regard knowledge as simply the accumulation of information in a stockpile, even though all messages that are received by the brain may leave some sort of deposit there. Knowledge must itself be regarded as a structure, a very complex and frequently quite loose pattern...with its parts connected in various ways by ties of varying degrees of strength. Messages are continually shot into this structure; some of them pass right through its interstices...without effecting any perceptible change in it. Sometimes messages ‘stick’ to the structure and become part of it....Occasionally, however, a message which is inconsistent with the basic pattern of the mental structure, but which is of a nature that it cannot be disbelieved hits the structure, which is then forced to undergo a complete reorganization” (Boulding, 1955, 103-104). This explains the fact that some scholars, mostly belonging to the Austrian tradition, stress the idea that information and knowledge are different concepts and that their differences are not reducible to the distinction between a flow and a stock, as it is the case in infor- mation economics50. This conceptual assimilation of knowledge to information seems the reason why Hayek’s conception of attention is not developed by economics of attention. A related problem lies in the nature of information, which can be manifold in reality and there- fore, cannot be always easily reducible to bits limited by a Shannon capacity constraint. As noticed by Sims (2006, 4), information can take the form of internal human information processing, of wiring media (telephone lines, internet connection, periodical subscription etc.) but also of costly investigation through interviews, surveys etc. If the two former kinds of information can be dealt with using a unitary and plastic concept of information, it is no more the case with the last form of information which involves discontinuities.

5. Conclusion As far as our investigation suggests, it is not easy to circumvent the economic literature dealing with attention and to encompass the vari- ous aspects of the notion of attention that may be useful for econo- mists. In view of critics addressed to the information-based “economics of attention” and insights from the authors from the past whom we have considered, some interesting lines of research to be developed are worth pointing out. First, the comparison between Hayek and Polanyi’s respective conceptions of attention suggests that the relation between attention and intentionality is all but obvious and should be taken more seri- ously by social scientists today. In addition, the fact that attention is a historical process and con- text-dependent is an invitation to think more deeply about how to

50 See Boettke (2002).

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 29

handle and regulate the scarcity of attention in our societies. Such a global research question calls for an interdisciplinary approach in- volving economists but also historians, philosophers, psychologists, sociologists, as well as management scientists. The ways to look at the economic issues raised by the scarcity of attention are manifold. One could be to revisit Foucault’s thought on political discourse and ‘gov- ernmentality’. Another one could consist in wearing the eyeglasses of Thaler and Sunstein (2008)’s approach of ‘nudging’, a recent concept in economics which is linked with the idea that it is possible to coun- tervail behavioral biases in a non-invasive way in order to enhance both individual and social welfare. We have emphasized some of the drawbacks and limits of the eco- nomic approach of attention, pointing out in particular the risk of confining the economics of attention to a mere ramification of infor- mation economics. No doubt that one of the greatest unmet scientific challenges of our societies is to provide an institutional framework that permits to sustain an appropriate balance between the interest of information providers and users. Obviously there is a lot of work to be done but some innovative research lines are currently being explored that en- hance our understanding of the role that attention plays in various contexts of economic decision-making.

References Akerlof, George and William T. Dickens. 2000. Near-rational wage and price setting and the long-run Phillips Curve, Brookings Papers on Eco- nomic Activity, 1(1): 1-60. Allport, D. Allen. 1980. Attention and performance. In Guy Claxton (ed.), Cognitive Psychology: New Directions. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Arieli, Amos, Ben-Ami, Yaniv, and Ariel Rubinstein. 2011. Tracking De- cision Makers under Uncertainty. American Economic Journal: Microe- conomics, 3(4): 68-76. Aristotle [330 B.C.] 1984. Sense and sensibilia. Translation by Jonathan I. Beare. In Jonathan I. Beare (ed.), Complete Works of Aristotle, 2 vols. Princeton, NJ: Bollingen. Arrow, Kenneth. 1974. The limits of Organization. William W. Norton & Company. Aumann, Robert J. 1976. Agreeing to disagree. The Annals of Statistics, 4(6): 1236-1239. Baccino, Thierry and Yves Manunta. 2005. Eye-fixation-related potentials: Insights into parafoveal processing. Journal of , 19(3): 204-215. Baker, Peter and Carl Hulse C. 2009. U.S. had early signals of a terror plot, Obama says. New York Times, December 30.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 30 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

Bateson, Gregory. 1972. Steps to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution and Epistemology. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Birner, Jack. 1999. The surprising place of cognitive psychology in the work of F.A. Hayek. History of Economic Ideas, 7(1-2): 43-84. Boettke, Peter. 2002. Information and Knowledge. Review of Austrian Eco- nomics, 15(4): 263-274. Bonnet, Charles. 1760. Essai analytique sur les facultés de l’âme. Copenha- gen: Philibert. Boring, Edwin G. 1933. The physical dimensions of consciousness. New York, NY: The Century Co. Boulding, Kenneth E. 1955. Notes on the Information Concept. Explora- tions [Toronto], 6: 103-112. Broadbent, Donald E. 1952. Listening to one of two synchronous messag- es. Journal of , 44: 51-55. Broadbent, Donald E. 1958. Perception and Communication. London: Per- gamon Press. Butos, William N. and Roger G. Koppl. 2006. Does the sensory order have a useful economic future? In R.G. Koppl, C. Krecké and E. Krecké (eds.), Advances in Austrian Economics (vol. 9). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science. Butos, William N. and Thomas J. McQuade. 2002. Mind, market and in- stitutions: the knowledge problem in Hayek’s thought. In J. Birner, P. Garrouste and T. Aimar (eds.), F.A. Hayek as a Political Economist. Lon- don and New York: Routledge, 113-133. Caldwell, Bruce. 2004. Some reflections on F.A. Hayek’s “The Sensory Order”. Journal of Bioeconomics, 6: 239-254. Camerer, Colin F. 2003. The behavioral challenge to economics: under- standing normal people. Paper presented at Federal Bank of Boston 48th Conference on ‘How humans behave: Implications for economics and policy’, June. Camerer, Colin F., Johnson, Eric J., Rymon,Talia, and Sankar Sen. 1993. Cognition and framing in sequential bargaining for gains and losses. In K. Binmore, A. Kirman and P. Tani (eds.), Frontiers of . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 27-47. Camerer, Colin F. and Eric J. Johnson. 2004. Thinking about attention in games: Backward and forward induction. In I. Brocas and J. D. Carril- lo (eds.), The psychology of economic decisions (vol.2.): Reasons and choices. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 111-129. Carr, Thomas H. 2004. A multilevel approach to selective attention: Mon- itoring environmental space, choosing stimuli for deep processing, and retrieving information from memory. In M.I. Posner (ed.), Cogni- tive neuroscience of attention. New York, NY: Guilford Press, 56-71. Cherry, E. Colin. 1953. Some experiments on the recognition of speech; with one and with two ears, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 25: 975-979. Coase, Ronald. 1960. The problem of . Journal of Law and Eco- nomics, 11(1): 67-73.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 31

Cohen, Michael D., March, James G., and Johan P. Olsen. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational choice. Administrative Science Quarterly, 17(1): 1-25. Condillac, Etienne Bonnot. 1754. Traité des sensations (2 vol.). Paris: De Bure Aîné. Costa-Gomes, Miguel A. and Vincent P. Crawford. 2001. Cognition and behavior in normal-form games: An experimental study. Econometrica, 69(5): 1193-1235. Costa-Gomes, Miguel A. and Vincent P. Crawford. 2006. Cognition and behavior in two-person guessing games: An experimental study. American Economic Review, 96(5): 1737-1768. Cyert, Richard M. and James G. March. 1963. A Behavioral . Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. D’Amico, Daniel and Peter J. Boettke. 2010. Making sense of Hayek’s Sensory Order. In W.N. Butos (Ed.), Advances in Austrian Economics (vol. 13). Esmerald Group Publishing Limited, 357-398. Deutsch, J. Anthony and Diana Deutsch. 1963. Attention: some theoreti- cal considerations. Psychological Review, 70(1): 80-90. De Groot, Adriann D. 1966. Perception and memory versus thought: Some old ideas and recent findings. In B. Kleinmuntz (Ed.), Problem solving: Research, method, and theory. New York, NY: John Wiley, 19-50. Dixit, Avinash. K., and Joseph E. Stiglitz. 1977. and optimum product diversity. American Economic Review, 67(3): 297- 308. Donders, Franciscus Cornelis. 1864. On the anomalies of accommodation and refraction of the eye. London: New Sydenham Society. Driver, Jon. 2001. A selective review of selective attention research form the past century. British Journal of Psychology, 92(1): 53-78. Egidi, Massimo and Luigi Marengo. 2004. Near-decomposability, organi- zation and evolution: some notes on Herbert Simon’s contribution. In Mie Augier and James G. March, James G. (eds.), Models of a Man: Es- says in Memory of Herbert A. Simon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Falkinger, Joseph. 2008. Limited attention as a scarce resource in infor- mation-rich economies. The Economic Journal, 118(532): 1596-1620. Frantz, Roger. 2003. Herbert Simon. Artificial Intelligence as a framework for understanding intuition. Journal of Economic Psychology, 24(3): 265- 277. Fodor, Jerry A. 1983. The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psy- chology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gabaix, Xavier and David Laibson. 2005. Bounded rationality and di- rected cognition. Mimeo. Gabaix, Xavier, Laibson, David, Moloche, Guillermo, and Stephen Wein- berg. 2006. Costly information-acquisition: experimental analysis of a boundedly rational model. American Economic Review, 96(4): 1043- 1068. Garrouste, Pierre. 2001. What economics borrows from the statistical the- ory of information? In Pascal Petit (ed.), Economics and Information. Boston, Dordrecht and London: Kluwer Academic Press.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 32 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

Garrouste, Pierre and Robert N. Langlois. 1997. Cognition, redundancy, and learning in organizations. Economics of Innovation and New Tech- nology, 4(4): 287-300. Gigerenzer, Gerd, Peter M. Todd and the ABD Research Group. 1999. Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gilboa, Izthak and David Schmeideler. 1995. Case Based Decision Theo- ry. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 110(3): 605-639. Goldhaber, Michael H. 1997. The Attention Economy and the Net. First Monday, 2(4), . Hatfield, Gary. [1995] 1998. Attention in early scientific psychology. IRCS Report 95-29, Institute for Research in , University of Pennsylvania. Reprinted in 1998 in Richard D. Wright (ed.), Visual At- tention. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3-25. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1937. Economics and Knowledge. Presidential ad- dress delivered before the London Economic Club, 10 November 1936. Economica (new series), 4(13): 33-54. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1942. Scientism and the Study of Society – Part I. Economica, 9(35): 267-291. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1943. Scientism and the Study of Society – Part II. Economica, 10(37): 34-63. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1944. Scientism and the Study of Society – Part III. Economica, 11(41): 27-39. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1945. The use of knowledge in society. The American Economic Review, 35(4): 519-530. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1952. The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foun- dations of Theoretical Psychology. Chicago, IL: The University of Chi- cago Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1960. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1978. The primacy of the abstract. In F.A. Hayek (ed.), New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Hayek, Friedrich A. 1994. Hayek on Hayek: an autobiographical dia- logue. In S. Kresge and L. Wenar (eds.). Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Helmholtz, Hermann von. [1910] 1924. Treatise on Physiological Optics. Translation by The Optical Society of America's Southall. Heukelom, Floris. 2007. Kahneman and Tversky and the origin of behav- ioral economics. Tinbergen Institute Discussion Paper n° 2007 003/1. Higgins, E. Torry. 1996. Knowledge activation: Accessibility, applicabil- ity, and salience. In E. Torry Higgins and Aviv Kruglanski (eds.), So- cial Psychology: Handbook of basic principles. New York, NY: Guilford Press, 133-168. Hirshleifer, David and Siew Hong Teoh. 2003. Limited attention, infor- mation disclosure, and financial reporting. Journal of Accounting and Economics, 36(1-3): 337-386.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 33

Hotelling, Harold. 1938. The general welfare in relation to problems of taxation and of railway and utility rates. Econometrica, 6(3): 242-269. James, William. 1890. The Principles of Psychology. New York, NY: H. Holt and Company. Jersild, Arthur T. 1927. Mental set and shift. Archives of Psychology, 14(89): 5-82. Johnson, William A. and Veronica J. Dark. 1986. Selective attention. An- nual Review of Psychology, 37: 43-75. Just, Marcel A. and Patricia A. Carpenter. 1980. A theory of reading: from eye fixations to comprehension. Psychological Review, 87(4): 329-354. Kahneman, Daniel. 1973. Attention and Effort. Englewoof Cliffs, NJ: Pren- tice-Hall. Kahneman, Daniel. 2003. Maps of bounded rationality: Psychology for behavioral economics. Nobel Prize Lecture, December 8, 2002. The American Economic Review, 93(5): 1449-1475. Kahneman, Daniel and Anne Treisman. 1984. Changing views of atten- tion and automaticity. In Raja Parasuraman and D.R. Davies (eds.), Varieties of attention. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Kessous, Emmanuel, Kevin Mellet and Moustafa Zouinar. 2010. L’économie de l'attention : entre protection des ressources cognitives et extraction de la valeur. Sociologie du Travail, 52(3): 359-373. Kraut, Robert E., Shyam Sunder, Rahul Telang, Darrin Filer and Matt Cronin. 2002. Markets for attention: Will postage for email help? Working paper available at http///basic.fluid.cs.cmu.edu/articles/kraut02. Kraut, Robert E., Shyam Sunder, Rahul Telang and James H. Morris. 2005. Pricing electronic mail to solve the problem of spam. Human- Computer Interaction, 20(1): 195-223. LaBerge, David. 1997. Attention, Awareness, and the Triangular Circuit. Consciousness and cognition, 6(2-3): 149-181. Lanham, Richard. 2006. The Economics of Attention: Style and Substance in the Age of Information. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. [1704-1765] 1966. Nouveaux essais sur l’entendement humain. New Edition. Paris: Garnier-Flammarion. Loder, Thede C., Marshall W Van Alstyne and Rick L. Wash. 2004. In- formation asymmetry and thwarting spam. SSRN Working Paper n° 488444. Machlup, Fritz. 1974. Friedrich von Hayek’s contribution to economics. Swedish Journal of Economics, 76(4): 498-531. MacKay, David G. 1973. Aspects of a theory of comprehension, memory, and attention. In B.J. Baars, W.P. Banks, and J.B. Newman (eds.), Es- sential sources in the scientific study of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 235-250. Madsen, Susan R., Cameron R. John and Duane Miller. 2006. Influential factors in individual readiness for change. Journal of Business and Man- agement, 12(2): 93-110.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 34 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

Malebranche, Nicolas de. 1675. De la recherche de la vérité. Où l’on traite de la nature de l’esprit de l’homme et de l’usage qu’il doit en faire pour éviter l’erreur dans les sciences. Paris: A. Pralard. March, James G. and Herbert A. Simon. 1958. Organizations. New York, NY: Wiley. Knight, Robert T. 2007. Neural networks debunk phrenology. Science, 316(5831): 1578-1579. Neumann, Odmar. 1971. Aufmerksamkeit. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, new. In Joachim Ritter (ed.), Darmstadt: Wissenschaft- liche Buchgesellschaft, vol. 1, 635-645. Norman, Donald A. and Tim Shallice. 1986. Attention to action: Willed and automatic control of behavior. In R.J. Davidson, G.E. Schwartz, and D. Shapiro (eds.), Consciousnesss and self-regulation: Advances in re- search and theory. New York, NY: Plenum Press, 1-18. Ocasio, William. 1997. Towards an attention-based view of the firm. Stra- tegic Management Journal, 18(7): 187-206. Pashler, Harold E. 1998. The Psychology of Attention. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pieters, Rik, Edward Rosbergen and Michel Wedel. 1999. Visual attention to repeated print advertising: a test of scanpath theory. Journal of Mar- keting Research, 36(4): 424-438. Pieters, Rik, Michel Wedel and Jie Zhang. 2009. Sales effects of attention to feature advertisements: a Bayesian mediation analysis. Journal of Marketing Research, 46(5): 669-681. Plotkin, Henry. 1994. The Nature of Knowledge. Harmondsworth: Allen Lane. Polanyi, Michael. 1962. The Republic of Science: its political and econom- ic theory. Minerva, 1: 154-174. Polanyi, Michael. 1965. The structure of consciousness. Brain, 88: 799-810. Polanyi, Michael. 1966a. The logic of tacit inference. Philosophy, 41(155): 1- 18. Polanyi, Michael. [1966b] 2009. The Tacit Dimension. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Polanyi, Michael. 1968. The mind-body relation. In William R. Coulson and Carl R. Rogers (eds.), Man and the Sciences of Man. Columbus, OH: Charles E. Merill Publishing Company. Polanyi, Michael. 1975. Personal knowledge. In Michael Polanyi and Harry Prosch (eds.), Meaning. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 22-45. Posner, Michael I. 2004. of attention. New York, NY: Guilford Press. Posner, Michael I. and Mary K. Rothbart. 1998. Executive attention: con- flict, target selection, and cognitive control. In Raja Parasuraman (ed.), The executive brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 401-423. Posner, Michael I., Charles R. Snyder and Brian J. Davidson. 1980. Attention and the detection of signals. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 109(2): 160-174.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36 | The ‘Economics of Attention’: A HET Perspective 35

Rerup, Claus. 2010. Prospective attention: Synchronizing top-down and bottom-up attention to non-salient issues. Copenhagen Business School Research Seminar, 16 April 2010. Ribot, Théodule. [1889] 2007. Psychologie de l’attention. Paris: L’Harmattan. Rizzello, Salvatore. 1999. The Economics of the Mind. Aldershot: Edward Elgar. Runde, Jochen H. 1988. Subjectivism, psychology, and the modern Aus- trians: Developments, tensions, prospects. Dordrecht: Kluwer Aca- demics. Ruz, Maria. 2006. Let the brain explain the mind: The case of attention. Philosophical Psychology, 19(4): 495-505. Schneider, Walter and Richard M. Shiffrin. 1977. Controlled and auto- matic human information processing: Perceptual learning, automatic attending and a general theory. Psychological Review, 84(2): 127-190. Schwartzstein, Joshua. 2010. Selective attention and learning. Un- published manuscript, Harvard University. Shafir, Eldar, Peter Diamond and . 1997. Money illusion. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(2): 341-374. Shannon, Claude E. 1948. A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27: 379-423 and 623-656. Shiffrin, Richard M. and Walter Schneider. 1977. Controlled and auto- matic human information processing: perceptual learning, automatic attending and a general theory. Psychological Review, 84(2): 127-190. Shiller, Robert. 1997. Why do people dislike inflation? In Christina D. Romer and David H. Romer (eds.), Reducing Inflation: Motivation and Strategy. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Simon, Herbert A. 1947. Administrative Behavior: A Study of Decision- making Processes in Administrative Organizations. Chicago, IL: Macmillan. Simon, Herbert A. [1969] 1996. The Science of the Artificial (Karl Taylor Compton Lectures). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Simon, Herbert A. 1971. Designing organizations for an information-rich world. In Martin Greenberger (ed.), Computers, Communication, and the Public Interest. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins Press, 37-72. Simon, Herbert A. and . 1972. Human Problem Solving. Eng- lewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. Simon, Herbert A. 1978. Rational decision-making in business organiza- tions, Nobel Memorial Lecture. Economic Sciences, 343-371. Simon, Herbert A. 1989. The Computer as a Laboratory for Epistemology. Carnegie Mellon University, Complex Information Processing (CIP) Paper #475. Simons, Daniel J. and Christopher F. Chabris 1999. Gorilla in our midst: sustained inattentional blindness for dynamics events. Perception, 28(9): 1059-1074. Sims, Christopher A. 2003. Implications of rational inattention. Journal of , 53(8): 1761-1800.

Œconomia – History | Methodology | Philosophy, 5(1) : 3-36 36 Agnès Festré and Pierre Garrouste |

Sims, Christopher A. 2006. Rational inattention: a research agenda. Dis- cussion Paper Series 1: Economic Studies No 34/2005, Deutsche Bun- desbank. Smith, Adam. [1795] 1975. The History of Astronomy. Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence, vol. 3. Essays on Philosophical subjects. Smith, Vernon. 2002. Nobel Prize Lecture, December 8. Steele, Gerald R. 2002. Hayek’s sensory order. Theory & Psychology, 12(3): 387-409. Stinson, Catherine. 2009. Searching for the source of executive attention. Psyche, 15(1): 137-154. Stroop, John Ridley. 1935. Studies of interference in serial verbal reaction. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 18: 643-662. Telford, Charles W. 1931. Refractory phase of voluntary and associative response. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 14: 1-35. Thaler, Richard H. and Cass R. Sunstein. 2003. Libertarian Paternalism. The American Economic Review, 93(2): 175-179. Titchener, Edward B. 1908. Lectures on the elementary psychology of feeling and attention. New York, NY: Macmillan. Treisman, Anne M. 1960. Contextual cues in selective listening. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 12(4): 242-248. Treisman, Anne M. 1969. Strategies and models of selective attention. In B.J. Baars, W.P. Banks, and J.B. Newman (eds.), Essential sources in the scientific study of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press, 207- 226. Treisman, Anne M. and Garry Gelade. 1980. A feature-integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology, 12(1): 97-136. Trichet, Jean-Claude. 2010. Opening address at the ECB Central Banking Conference. Frankfurt, 18 November 2010. Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under uncertain- ty: heuristics and biases. Science, 185(4157): 1124-1131. Vanberg, Viktor. 2004. Austrian Economics, and methodological individualism: Subjectivism reconsidered. In R.G. Koppl (Ed.), Advances in Austrian Economics (vol. 7). Amsterdam: Else- vier Science. Weick, Karl E. 1979. The of Organizing (2nd Edition). New York, NY: Random House. Wickens, Christopher D. 1980. The structure of attentional resources. In R.S. Nickerson (ed.), Attention and Performance VIII. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 239-258. Wolff, Christian. 1738. Psychologia empirica. Frankfurt and Leipzig: Offici- na Libraria Rengeriana. Wundt, Wilhelm. 1893. Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie, vols 1 and 2. Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann. Zandt, Timothy Van. 2001. Information overload in a network of targeted information. CEPR Discussion Paper n° 2836, London.

Œconomia – Histoire | Épistémologie | Philosophie, 5(1) : 3-36