Lecture Notes on Nonstandard Analysis Ucla Summer School in Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lecture Notes on Nonstandard Analysis Ucla Summer School in Logic LECTURE NOTES ON NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS UCLA SUMMER SCHOOL IN LOGIC ISAAC GOLDBRING Contents 1. The hyperreals 3 1.1. Basic facts about the ordered real field 3 1.2. The nonstandard extension 4 1.3. Arithmetic in the hyperreals 5 ∗ 1.4. The structure of N 7 1.5. More practice with transfer 8 1.6. Problems 9 2. Logical formalisms for nonstandard extensions 10 2.1. Approach 1: The compactness theorem 11 2.2. Approach 2: The ultrapower construction 12 2.3. Problems 16 3. Sequences and series 17 3.1. First results about sequences 17 3.2. Cluster points 19 3.3. Series 21 3.4. Problems 22 4. Continuity 23 4.1. First results about continuity 23 4.2. Uniform continuity 25 4.3. Sequences of functions 27 4.4. Problems 30 5. Differentiation 33 5.1. The derivative 33 5.2. Continuous differentiability 35 5.3. Problems 36 6. Riemann Integration 38 6.1. Hyperfinite Riemann sums and integrability 38 6.2. The Peano Existence Theorem 41 6.3. Problems 43 7. Weekend Problem Set #1 44 8. Many-sorted and Higher-Type Structures 47 8.1. Many-sorted structures 47 Date: November 10, 2014. 1 2 ISAAC GOLDBRING 8.2. Higher-type sorts 48 8.3. Saturation 51 8.4. Useful nonstandard principles 53 8.5. Recap: the nonstandard setting 54 8.6. Problems 54 9. Metric Space Topology 55 9.1. Open and closed sets, compactness, completeness 55 9.2. More about continuity 63 9.3. Compact maps 64 9.4. Problems 65 10. Banach Spaces 67 10.1. Normed spaces 67 10.2. Bounded linear maps 68 10.3. Finite-dimensional spaces and compact linear maps 69 10.4. Problems 71 11. Hilbert Spaces 73 11.1. Inner product spaces 73 11.2. Orthonormal bases and `2 75 11.3. Orthogonal projections 79 11.4. Hyperfinite-dimensional subspaces 82 11.5. Problems 83 12. Weekend Problem Set #2 85 13. The Spectral Theorem for compact hermitian operators 88 13.1. Problems 93 14. The Bernstein-Robinson Theorem 94 15. Measure Theory 101 15.1. General measure theory 101 15.2. Loeb measure 102 15.3. Product measure 103 15.4. Integration 104 15.5. Conditional expectation 104 15.6. Problems 105 16. Szemer´ediRegularity Lemma 106 16.1. Problems 108 References 110 Nonstandard analysis was invented by Abraham Robinson in the 1960s as a way to rescue the na¨ıve use of infinitesimal and infinite elements favored by mathematicians such as Leibniz and Euler before the advent of the rigorous methods introduced by Cauchy and Weierstrauss. Indeed, Robinson realized that the compactness theorem of first-order logic could be used to provide fields that \logically behaved" like the ordered real field while containing \ideal" elements such as infinitesimal and infinite elements. LECTURE NOTES ON NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS 3 Since its origins, nonstandard analysis has become a powerful mathemat- ical tool, not only for yielding easier definitions for standard concepts and providing slick proofs of well-known mathematical theorems, but for also providing mathematicians with amazing new tools to prove theorems, e.g. hyperfinite approximation. In addition, by providing useful mathematical heuristics a precise language to be discussed, many mathematical ideas have been elucidated greatly. In these notes, we try and cover a wide spectrum of applications of non- standard methods. In the first part of these notes, we explain what a non- standard extension is and we use it to reprove some basic facts from calculus. We then broaden our nonstandard framework to handle more sophisticated mathematical situations and begin studying metric space topology. We then enter functional analysis by discussing Banach and Hilbert spaces. Here we prove our first serious theorems: the Spectral Theorem for compact hermit- ian operators and the Bernstein-Robinson Theorem on invariant subspaces; this latter theorem was the first major theorem whose first proof was non- standard. We then end by briefly discussing Loeb measure and using it to give a slick proof of an important combinatorial result, the Szemer´edi Regularity Lemma. Due to time limitations, there are many beautiful subjects I had to skip. In particular, I had to omit the nonstandard hull construction (although this is briefly introduced in the second weekend problem set) as well as applica- tions of nonstandard analysis to Lie theory (e.g. Hilbert's fifth problem), geometric group theory (e.g. asymptotic cones), and commutative algebra (e.g. bounds in the theory of polynomial rings). We have borrowed much of our presentation from two main sources: Gold- blatt's fantastic book [2] and Davis' concise [1]. Occasionally, I have bor- rowed some ideas from Henson's [3]. The material on Szemer´edi'sRegularity Lemma and the Furstenberg Correspondence come from Terence Tao's blog. I would like to thank Bruno De Mendonca Braga and Jonathan Wolf for pointing out errors in an earlier version of these notes. 1. The hyperreals 1.1. Basic facts about the ordered real field. The ordered field of real numbers is the structure (R; +; ·; 0; 1; <). We recall some basic properties: >0 • (Q is dense in R) for every r 2 R and every 2 R , there is q 2 Q such that jr − qj < ; • (Triangle Inequality) for every x; y 2 R, we have jx + yj ≤ jxj + jyj; >0 • (Archimedean Property) for every x; y 2 R , there is n 2 N such that nx > y. Perhaps the most important property of the ordered real field is Definition 1.1 (Completeness Property). If A ⊆ R is nonempty and bounded above, then there is a b 2 R such that: • for all a 2 A, we have a ≤ b (b is an upper bound for A); 4 ISAAC GOLDBRING • if a ≤ c for all a 2 A, then b ≤ c (b is the least upper bound for A). Such b is easily seen to be unique and is called the least upper bound of A, or the supremum of A, and is denote sup(A). Exercise 1.2. Show that if A is nonempty and bounded below, then A has a greatest lower bound. The greatest lower bound is also called the infimum of A and is denoted inf(A). 1.2. The nonstandard extension. In order to start \doing" nonstandard analysis as quickly as possible, we will postpone a formal construction of the nonstandard universe. Instead, we will pose some postulates that a nonstan- dard universe should possess, assume the existence of such a nonstandard universe, and then begin reasoning in this nonstandard universe. Of course, after we have seen the merits of some nonstandard reasoning, we will return and give a couple of rigorous constructions of nonstandard universes. ∗ We will work in a nonstandard universe R that has the following prop- erties: ∗ (NS1) (R; +; ·; 0; 1; <) is an ordered subfield of (R ; +; ·; 0; 1; <). ∗ ∗ (NS2) R has a positive infinitesimal element, that is, there is 2 R such >0 that > 0 but < r for every r 2 R . n (NS3) For every n 2 N and every function f : R ! R, there is a \natural ∗ n ∗ extension" f :(R ) ! R . The natural extensions of the field 2 ∗ operations +; · : R ! R coincide with the field operations in R . n ∗ ∗ n Similarly, for every A ⊆ R , there is a subset A ⊆ (R ) such that ∗ n A \ R = A. ∗ (NS4) R , equipped with the above assignment of extensions of functions and subsets, \behaves logically" like R. The last item in the above list is, of course, extremely vague and imprecise. We will need to discuss some logic in order to carefully explain what we mean by this. Roughly speaking, any statement that is expressible in first-order logic and mentioning only standard numbers is true in R if and only if it ∗ is true in R . This is often referred to as the Transfer Principle, although, ∗ logically speaking, we are just requiring that R , in a suitable first-order language, be an elementary extension of R. We will explain this in more detail later in these notes. That being said, until we rigorously explain the logical formalism of non- standard analysis, we should caution the reader that typical transferrable statements involve quantifiers over numbers and not sets of numbers. For example, the completeness property for R says that \for all sets of num- bers A that are nonempty and bounded above, sup(A) exists." This is an example of a statement that is not transferrable; see Exercise 1.8 below. ∗ Definition 1.3. R is called the ordered field of hyperreals. n Remark. If f : A ! R is a function, where A ⊆ R , we would like to also ∗ ∗ consider its nonstandard extension f : A ! R . We will take care of this matter shortly. LECTURE NOTES ON NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS 5 1.3. Arithmetic in the hyperreals. First, let's discuss some immediate ∗ consequences of the above postulates. Since R is an ordered field, we can start performing the field operations to our positive infinitesimal . For example, has an additive inverse −, which is then a negative infinitesimal. Also, we can consider π · ; it is reasonably easy to see that π · is also a positive infinitesimal. (This will also follow from a more general principle that we will shortly see.) −1 >0 Since 6= 0, it has a multiplicative inverse . For a given r 2 R , 1 −1 since < r , we see that > r. Since r was an arbitrary positive real number, we see that −1 is a positive infinite element. And of course, −−1 is a negative infinitep element. But now we can continue playing, considering numbers like 2 · −3 and so on..
Recommended publications
  • Nonstandard Methods in Analysis an Elementary Approach to Stochastic Differential Equations
    Nonstandard Methods in Analysis An elementary approach to Stochastic Differential Equations Vieri Benci Dipartimento di Matematica Applicata June 2008 Vieri Benci (DMA-Pisa) Nonstandard Methods 03/06 1 / 42 In most applications of NSA to analysis, only elementary tools and techniques of nonstandard calculus seems to be necessary. The advantages of a theory which includes infinitasimals rely more on the possibility of making new models rather than in the dimostration techniques. These two points will be illustrated using a-theory in the study of Brownian motion. The aim of this talk is to make two points relative to NSA: Vieri Benci (DMA-Pisa) Nonstandard Methods 03/06 2 / 42 The advantages of a theory which includes infinitasimals rely more on the possibility of making new models rather than in the dimostration techniques. These two points will be illustrated using a-theory in the study of Brownian motion. The aim of this talk is to make two points relative to NSA: In most applications of NSA to analysis, only elementary tools and techniques of nonstandard calculus seems to be necessary. Vieri Benci (DMA-Pisa) Nonstandard Methods 03/06 2 / 42 These two points will be illustrated using a-theory in the study of Brownian motion. The aim of this talk is to make two points relative to NSA: In most applications of NSA to analysis, only elementary tools and techniques of nonstandard calculus seems to be necessary. The advantages of a theory which includes infinitasimals rely more on the possibility of making new models rather than in the dimostration techniques. Vieri Benci (DMA-Pisa) Nonstandard Methods 03/06 2 / 42 The aim of this talk is to make two points relative to NSA: In most applications of NSA to analysis, only elementary tools and techniques of nonstandard calculus seems to be necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis 11
    AN INTRODUCTION TO NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS ISAAC DAVIS Abstract. In this paper we give an introduction to nonstandard analysis, starting with an ultrapower construction of the hyperreals. We then demon- strate how theorems in standard analysis \transfer over" to nonstandard anal- ysis, and how theorems in standard analysis can be proven using theorems in nonstandard analysis. 1. Introduction For many centuries, early mathematicians and physicists would solve problems by considering infinitesimally small pieces of a shape, or movement along a path by an infinitesimal amount. Archimedes derived the formula for the area of a circle by thinking of a circle as a polygon with infinitely many infinitesimal sides [1]. In particular, the construction of calculus was first motivated by this intuitive notion of infinitesimal change. G.W. Leibniz's derivation of calculus made extensive use of “infinitesimal” numbers, which were both nonzero but small enough to add to any real number without changing it noticeably. Although intuitively clear, infinitesi- mals were ultimately rejected as mathematically unsound, and were replaced with the common -δ method of computing limits and derivatives. However, in 1960 Abraham Robinson developed nonstandard analysis, in which the reals are rigor- ously extended to include infinitesimal numbers and infinite numbers; this new extended field is called the field of hyperreal numbers. The goal was to create a system of analysis that was more intuitively appealing than standard analysis but without losing any of the rigor of standard analysis. In this paper, we will explore the construction and various uses of nonstandard analysis. In section 2 we will introduce the notion of an ultrafilter, which will allow us to do a typical ultrapower construction of the hyperreal numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • 1.1 Constructing the Real Numbers
    18.095 Lecture Series in Mathematics IAP 2015 Lecture #1 01/05/2015 What is number theory? The study of numbers of course! But what is a number? • N = f0; 1; 2; 3;:::g can be defined in several ways: { Finite ordinals (0 := fg, n + 1 := n [ fng). { Finite cardinals (isomorphism classes of finite sets). { Strings over a unary alphabet (\", \1", \11", \111", . ). N is a commutative semiring: addition and multiplication satisfy the usual commu- tative/associative/distributive properties with identities 0 and 1 (and 0 annihilates). Totally ordered (as ordinals/cardinals), making it a (positive) ordered semiring. • Z = {±n : n 2 Ng.A commutative ring (commutative semiring, additive inverses). Contains Z>0 = N − f0g closed under +; × with Z = −Z>0 t f0g t Z>0. This makes Z an ordered ring (in fact, an ordered domain). • Q = fa=b : a; 2 Z; b 6= 0g= ∼, where a=b ∼ c=d if ad = bc. A field (commutative ring, multiplicative inverses, 0 6= 1) containing Z = fn=1g. Contains Q>0 = fa=b : a; b 2 Z>0g closed under +; × with Q = −Q>0 t f0g t Q>0. This makes Q an ordered field. • R is the completion of Q, making it a complete ordered field. Each of the algebraic structures N; Z; Q; R is canonical in the following sense: every non-trivial algebraic structure of the same type (ordered semiring, ordered ring, ordered field, complete ordered field) contains a copy of N; Z; Q; R inside it. 1.1 Constructing the real numbers What do we mean by the completion of Q? There are two possibilities: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • 0.999… = 1 an Infinitesimal Explanation Bryan Dawson
    0 1 2 0.9999999999999999 0.999… = 1 An Infinitesimal Explanation Bryan Dawson know the proofs, but I still don’t What exactly does that mean? Just as real num- believe it.” Those words were uttered bers have decimal expansions, with one digit for each to me by a very good undergraduate integer power of 10, so do hyperreal numbers. But the mathematics major regarding hyperreals contain “infinite integers,” so there are digits This fact is possibly the most-argued- representing not just (the 237th digit past “Iabout result of arithmetic, one that can evoke great the decimal point) and (the 12,598th digit), passion. But why? but also (the Yth digit past the decimal point), According to Robert Ely [2] (see also Tall and where is a negative infinite hyperreal integer. Vinner [4]), the answer for some students lies in their We have four 0s followed by a 1 in intuition about the infinitely small: While they may the fifth decimal place, and also where understand that the difference between and 1 is represents zeros, followed by a 1 in the Yth less than any positive real number, they still perceive a decimal place. (Since we’ll see later that not all infinite nonzero but infinitely small difference—an infinitesimal hyperreal integers are equal, a more precise, but also difference—between the two. And it’s not just uglier, notation would be students; most professional mathematicians have not or formally studied infinitesimals and their larger setting, the hyperreal numbers, and as a result sometimes Confused? Perhaps a little background information wonder .
    [Show full text]
  • Be a Metric Space
    2 The University of Sydney show that Z is closed in R. The complement of Z in R is the union of all the Pure Mathematics 3901 open intervals (n, n + 1), where n runs through all of Z, and this is open since every union of open sets is open. So Z is closed. Metric Spaces 2000 Alternatively, let (an) be a Cauchy sequence in Z. Choose an integer N such that d(xn, xm) < 1 for all n ≥ N. Put x = xN . Then for all n ≥ N we have Tutorial 5 |xn − x| = d(xn, xN ) < 1. But xn, x ∈ Z, and since two distinct integers always differ by at least 1 it follows that xn = x. This holds for all n > N. 1. Let X = (X, d) be a metric space. Let (xn) and (yn) be two sequences in X So xn → x as n → ∞ (since for all ε > 0 we have 0 = d(xn, x) < ε for all such that (yn) is a Cauchy sequence and d(xn, yn) → 0 as n → ∞. Prove that n > N). (i)(xn) is a Cauchy sequence in X, and 4. (i) Show that if D is a metric on the set X and f: Y → X is an injective (ii)(xn) converges to a limit x if and only if (yn) also converges to x. function then the formula d(a, b) = D(f(a), f(b)) defines a metric d on Y , and use this to show that d(m, n) = |m−1 − n−1| defines a metric Solution.
    [Show full text]
  • Do Simple Infinitesimal Parts Solve Zeno's Paradox of Measure?
    Do Simple Infinitesimal Parts Solve Zeno's Paradox of Measure?∗ Lu Chen (Forthcoming in Synthese) Abstract In this paper, I develop an original view of the structure of space|called infinitesimal atomism|as a reply to Zeno's paradox of measure. According to this view, space is composed of ultimate parts with infinitesimal size, where infinitesimals are understood within the framework of Robinson's (1966) nonstandard analysis. Notably, this view satisfies a version of additivity: for every region that has a size, its size is the sum of the sizes of its disjoint parts. In particular, the size of a finite region is the sum of the sizes of its infinitesimal parts. Although this view is a coherent approach to Zeno's paradox and is preferable to Skyrms's (1983) infinitesimal approach, it faces both the main problem for the standard view (the problem of unmeasurable regions) and the main problem for finite atomism (Weyl's tile argument), leaving it with no clear advantage over these familiar alternatives. Keywords: continuum; Zeno's paradox of measure; infinitesimals; unmeasurable ∗Special thanks to Jeffrey Russell and Phillip Bricker for their extensive feedback on early drafts of the paper. Many thanks to the referees of Synthese for their very helpful comments. I'd also like to thank the participants of Umass dissertation seminar for their useful feedback on my first draft. 1 regions; Weyl's tile argument 1 Zeno's Paradox of Measure A continuum, such as the region of space you occupy, is commonly taken to be indefinitely divisible. But this view runs into Zeno's famous paradox of measure.
    [Show full text]
  • Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics
    Found Sci DOI 10.1007/s10699-012-9316-5 Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics Vladimir Kanovei · Mikhail G. Katz · Thomas Mormann © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in func- tional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S, all definable sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable, suggesting that Connes views a theory as being “vir- tual” if it is not definable in a suitable model of ZFC. If so, Connes’ claim that a theory of the hyperreals is “virtual” is refuted by the existence of a definable model of the hyperreal field due to Kanovei and Shelah. Free ultrafilters aren’t definable, yet Connes exploited such ultrafilters both in his own earlier work on the classification of factors in the 1970s and 80s, and in Noncommutative Geometry, raising the question whether the latter may not be vulnera- ble to Connes’ criticism of virtuality. We analyze the philosophical underpinnings of Connes’ argument based on Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, and detect an apparent circularity in Connes’ logic. We document the reliance on non-constructive foundational material, and specifically on the Dixmier trace − (featured on the front cover of Connes’ magnum opus) V.
    [Show full text]
  • Abraham Robinson, 1918 - 1974
    BULLETIN OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 83, Number 4, July 1977 ABRAHAM ROBINSON, 1918 - 1974 BY ANGUS J. MACINTYRE 1. Abraham Robinson died in New Haven on April 11, 1974, some six months after the diagnosis of an incurable cancer of the pancreas. In the fall of 1973 he was vigorously and enthusiastically involved at Yale in joint work with Peter Roquette on a new model-theoretic approach to diophantine problems. He finished a draft of this in November, shortly before he underwent surgery. He spoke of his satisfaction in having finished this work, and he bore with unforgettable dignity the loss of his strength and the fading of his bright plans. He was supported until the end by Reneé Robinson, who had shared with him since 1944 a life given to science and art. There is common consent that Robinson was one of the greatest of mathematical logicians, and Gödel has stressed that Robinson more than any other brought logic closer to mathematics as traditionally understood. His early work on metamathematics of algebra undoubtedly guided Ax and Kochen to the solution of the Artin Conjecture. One can reasonably hope that his memory will be further honored by future applications of his penetrating ideas. Robinson was a gentleman, unfailingly courteous, with inexhaustible enthu­ siasm. He took modest pleasure in his many honors. He was much respected for his willingness to listen, and for the sincerity of his advice. As far as I know, nothing in mathematics was alien to him. Certainly his work in logic reveals an amazing store of general mathematical knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Analysis (Math 649K) Spring 2008
    Nonstandard Analysis (Math 649k) Spring 2008 David Ross, Department of Mathematics February 29, 2008 1 1 Introduction 1.1 Outline of course: 1. Introduction: motivation, history, and propoganda 2. Nonstandard models: definition, properties, some unavoidable logic 3. Very basic Calculus/Analysis 4. Applications of saturation 5. General Topology 6. Measure Theory 7. Functional Analysis 8. Probability 1.2 Some References: 1. Abraham Robinson (1966) Nonstandard Analysis North Holland, Amster- dam 2. Martin Davis and Reuben Hersh Nonstandard Analysis Scientific Ameri- can, June 1972 3. Davis, M. (1977) Applied Nonstandard Analysis Wiley, New York. 4. Sergio Albeverio, Jens Erik Fenstad, Raphael Høegh-Krohn, and Tom Lindstrøm (1986) Nonstandard Methods in Stochastic Analysis and Math- ematical Physics. Academic Press, New York. 5. Al Hurd and Peter Loeb (1985) An introduction to Nonstandard Real Anal- ysis Academic Press, New York. 6. Keith Stroyan and Wilhelminus Luxemburg (1976) Introduction to the Theory of Infinitesimals Academic Press, New York. 7. Keith Stroyan and Jose Bayod (1986) Foundations of Infinitesimal Stochas- tic Analysis North Holland, Amsterdam 8. Leif Arkeryd, Nigel Cutland, C. Ward Henson (eds) (1997) Nonstandard Analysis: Theory and Applications, Kluwer 9. Rob Goldblatt (1998) Lectures on the Hyperreals, Springer 2 1.3 Some history: • (xxxx) Archimedes • (1615) Kepler, Nova stereometria dolorium vinariorium • (1635) Cavalieri, Geometria indivisibilus • (1635) Excercitationes geometricae (”Rigor is the affair of philosophy rather
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Power Series Rings, Inverse Limits, and I-Adic Completions of Rings
    Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings Formal semigroup rings and formal power series rings We next want to explore the notion of a (formal) power series ring in finitely many variables over a ring R, and show that it is Noetherian when R is. But we begin with a definition in much greater generality. Let S be a commutative semigroup (which will have identity 1S = 1) written multi- plicatively. The semigroup ring of S with coefficients in R may be thought of as the free R-module with basis S, with multiplication defined by the rule h k X X 0 0 X X 0 ( risi)( rjsj) = ( rirj)s: i=1 j=1 s2S 0 sisj =s We next want to construct a much larger ring in which infinite sums of multiples of elements of S are allowed. In order to insure that multiplication is well-defined, from now on we assume that S has the following additional property: (#) For all s 2 S, f(s1; s2) 2 S × S : s1s2 = sg is finite. Thus, each element of S has only finitely many factorizations as a product of two k1 kn elements. For example, we may take S to be the set of all monomials fx1 ··· xn : n (k1; : : : ; kn) 2 N g in n variables. For this chocie of S, the usual semigroup ring R[S] may be identified with the polynomial ring R[x1; : : : ; xn] in n indeterminates over R. We next construct a formal semigroup ring denoted R[[S]]: we may think of this ring formally as consisting of all functions from S to R, but we shall indicate elements of the P ring notationally as (possibly infinite) formal sums s2S rss, where the function corre- sponding to this formal sum maps s to rs for all s 2 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Absolute Convergence in Ordered Fields
    Absolute Convergence in Ordered Fields Kristine Hampton Abstract This paper reviews Absolute Convergence in Ordered Fields by Clark and Diepeveen [1]. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Definition of Terms 2 2.1 Field . 2 2.2 Ordered Field . 3 2.3 The Symbol .......................... 3 2.4 Sequential Completeness and Cauchy Sequences . 3 2.5 New Sequences . 4 3 Summary of Results 4 4 Proof of Main Theorem 5 4.1 Main Theorem . 5 4.2 Proof . 6 5 Further Applications 8 5.1 Infinite Series in Ordered Fields . 8 5.2 Implications for Convergence Tests . 9 5.3 Uniform Convergence in Ordered Fields . 9 5.4 Integral Convergence in Ordered Fields . 9 1 1 Introduction In Absolute Convergence in Ordered Fields [1], the authors attempt to dis- tinguish between convergence and absolute convergence in ordered fields. In particular, Archimedean and non-Archimedean fields (to be defined later) are examined. In each field, the possibilities for absolute convergence with and without convergence are considered. Ultimately, the paper [1] attempts to offer conditions on various fields that guarantee if a series is convergent or not in that field if it is absolutely convergent. The results end up exposing a reliance upon sequential completeness in a field for any statements on the behavior of convergence in relation to absolute convergence to be made, and vice versa. The paper makes a noted attempt to be readable for a variety of mathematic levels, explaining new topics and ideas that might be confusing along the way. To understand the paper, only a basic understanding of series and convergence in R is required, although having a basic understanding of ordered fields would be ideal.
    [Show full text]
  • Casting out Beams: Berkeley's Criticism of the Calculus
    Casting Out Beams: Berkeley's Criticism of the Calculus Eugene C. Boman Penn State - Harrisburg First cast out the beam out of thine own eye; and thou shalt see clearly to cast out the mote out of thy brother's eye. King James Bible, Matthew 7:5 Calculus burst upon the scientific community in the late 17th century with unparalleled success. Nevertheless it took another 200 years and the combined efforts of many first rate mathematicians to finally "get it right." In particular the fundamental concept of a limit did not take on its final form until the 1800's with the work of Karl Weierstrass. The Method of Fluxions as it was known in Britain, was invented by Isaac Newton in the 1660's. For reasons known only to him, he did not publish his invention until much later. In the meantime Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz published his own formulation of Calculus which he called Calculus Differentialis in 1684. Newton's approach was kinematic. Quantities were said to "flow" in time and the fluxion (derivative) of a flowing quantity was interpreted as a velocity. Leibniz's approach was based on the idea of infinitely small quantities: infinitesimals. Their public priority brawl is both legendary [11] and a stain on both of their reputations. A slightly less well known public argument, but mathematically far more important, began in 1734 when Bishop George Berkeley published a treatise entitled The Analyst. Berkeley derided the lack of rigor in the fundamentals of both renderings of the topic. To be sure, neither Newton's nor Leibniz's formulation of the Calculus would stand up to the modern standard of rigor.
    [Show full text]