Pragmatics & Cognition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pragmatics & Cognition volume 20 number 2 2012 Editor Marcelo Dascal Tel Aviv University Associate Editors Jens Allwood University of Göteborg Itiel E. Dror University College London Yaron M. Senderowicz Tel Aviv University Benny Shanon The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Stephen Stich Rutgers University Yorick Wilks University of Sheffield John Benjamins Publishing Company Amsterdam / Philadelphia UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs Board of Consulting Editors Jerome S. Bruner, (Psychology) New York Andy Clark, (Philosophy/Cognitive Sciences) University of Edinburgh Umberto Eco, (Semiotics/Cognitive Science) University of Bologna Willem F.G. Haselager, (Cognition and Technology) Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour James Higginbotham, (Philosophy/Linguistics) University of Southern California, Los Angeles Jaakko Hintikka, (Philosophy/Logic) Boston University Sachiko Ide, (English/Pragmatics) Japan Women’s University, Tokyo Willard McCarty, (Humanities Computing) King’s College London Jan Nuyts, (Pragmatics/Cognitive Science) University of Antwerp Dan Sperber, (Anthropology/Pragmatics) Institut Jean Nicod, Paris Deborah Tannen, (Pragmatics) Georgetown University, Washington D.C. Boris M. Velichkovsky, (Neuroscience/Computer Science) Dresden University of Technology Anna Wierzbicka, (Linguistics) Australian National University, Canberra Chaoqun Xie, (Pragmatics) Fujian Normal University UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs Special Commemorative Issue TWENTIETH BIRTHDAY of PRAGMATICS & COGNITION Culture – Language – Cognition Edited by Marcelo Dascal Tel Aviv University UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs Table of contents Opening remarks 231 Introduction 233 Marcelo Dascal Articles No need for instinct: Coordinated communication as an emergent self organized process 241 Raymond W. Gibbs, Jr. and Nathaniel Clark Like the breathability of air: Embodied embedded communication 263 Pim Haselager Linguistic fire and human cognitive powers 275 Stephen J. Cowley Language: Between cognition, communication and culture 295 Anne Reboul Language is an instrument for thought. Really? 317 Jan Nuyts Cognition, communication, and readiness for language 334 Jens Allwood Understanding others requires shared concepts 356 Anna Wierzbicka Replies Not quite organizational: A response to Raymond W. Gibbs and Nathaniel Clark 381 Daniel Everett UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs vi Table of contents Breathability, learnability, and the illusion of design: A response to Haselager 386 Daniel L. Everett Exocognitive Linguistics: A response to Cowley 388 Daniel L. Everett Response to Reboul: Between cognition, communication, and culture 392 Daniel L. Everett Language can help us think. Really. Reply to Jan Nuyts 408 Daniel L. Everett Linguistics, Truth, and Culture: A Response to Jens Allwood 411 Daniel L. Everett Understanding others requires adaptive thinking: Response to Wierzbicka 417 Daniel L. Everett UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs Opening remarks Most scientists would be thrilled, as I am, to have their ideas taken seriously enough to be made the focus of an entire journal issue. Before beginning, there- fore, let me offer my profound thanks to Marcelo Dascal and each of the authors of this special edition, for taking the time to shape and contribute to this vol- ume about Language: The Cultural Tool. Their cogent and incisive criticisms have helped clear my thinking on many issues. This is not to minimize disagreements between me and my commentators. There are many and some are profound, touching on foundational assumptions about linguistics, as well as the philosophy and psychology of language and the mind. Overall, however, this discussion as a whole ought to convince readers of two things. First, that many researchers agree that the idea of an innate Universal Grammar, UG, (of any variety) has passed its sell-by date. Second, that the role of culture is greater than they may have thought prior to reading this special issue of Pragmatics and Cognition. Pragmatics & Cognition 20:2 (2012), 231–231. doi 10.1075/pc.20.2.01ope UNCORRECTEDissn 0929–0907 / e-issn 1569–9943 © John Benjamins PROOFSPublishing Company © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs UNCORRECTED PROOFS © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs Introduction Marcelo Dascal Dear readers, authors, reviewers, referees, members of the Board of Consulting Editors, Associate Editors and all those who have collaborated throughout the years with Pragmatics & Cognition. Welcome to this very Special Issue, which commemorates the 20th year of existence of our journal. Were it not for your interest, loyalty, enthusiasm and steady cooperation, the journal would not have achieved the aims set up at its foundation and the prestige it enjoys. To refresh our memory, here is how the Introduction to Volume I spelled out our vision: A new journal, specially an interdisciplinary one, helps to shape a new research niche, carved out by a critical mass of work already in the making, but which has not so far found an adequate vehicle of diffusion and crystallization. The niche Pragmatics & Cognition has identified, and purports to develop, lies at the inter- section of two rapidly expanding areas of research: Pragmatics and Cognition. Each of these areas is concerned with one of the two most important kinds of (human) activity — the use of symbols in the performance of mental operations. Though the interdependence between these activities has been often asserted and debated, it has not so far received the kind of systematic attention and specific re- search it well deserves. It is to the investigation of the interrelations between these two domains that Pragmatics & Cognition is primarily devoted. The Introduction goes on stressing the broad sense in which both ‘Pragmatics’ and ‘Cognition’ should be taken in our newly created journal, the variety of disciplines for which it would be relevant, and the necessary presence of discussions and criti- cal reviews as a sine qua non for the growth of understanding and knowledge, especially for shaping an interdisciplinary niche that purports to become an open space rather than a closed disciplinary sphere. The research niche P&C developed turned out to be far from static. It had to satisfy a growing interest, manifested in many submissions and in proposals of expanding its scope towards new aspects of its announced purposes. As a result, in the course of its dynamic evolution, P&C not only fulfilled its initial promises Pragmatics & Cognition 20:2 (2012), 233–240. doi 10.1075/pc.20.2.02int UNCORRECTEDissn 0929–0907 / e-issn 1569–9943 © John Benjamins PROOFSPublishing Company © JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY 1st proofs 234 Marcelo Dascal and goals. It was virtually forced to expand its original vision, slowly encompass- ing many more domains and disciplines, where the interaction between pragmat- ics and cognition is acknowledged as a fundamental ingredient and is usefully explored both in the journal’s regular and Special Issues. Part of this expansion consisted in acknowledging the relevance of recent technological developments to our concerns. Accordingly, we launched a series of Special Issues focused on ‘Cognition and Technology’. The first of these Special Issues, published in 2005 as Volume 13, Number 3, explored the Cog-Tech connection, bearing the title “Cognitive Technologies and the Pragmatics of Cognition”. The significance of the pragmatics-cognition-technology interface was soon recognized by authors and readers and was thereafter naturally embedded in the ensuing regular issues of P&C as articles, discussions and book reviews. From our modest two issues per volume the journal’s size thus jumped to three yearly issues, a total of 600 pages per volume. It is in the light of this brief historical summary that the present Special Commemorative Issue has been conceived. Its chosen theme and focal author il- lustrate the journal’s original goals, achievements, and issues debated and show why P&C is proud to have become a dynamic forum for innovative thinking and dialogue, and looks forward to continuing to pave the way for ever more to come. In Volume I, Number 1, 1993, an American linguist who graduated at the University of Campinas, Brazil, specializing in Amazonian languages, published a paper titled “Sapir, Reichenbach, and the syntax of tense in Pirahã”. Daniel L. Everett, who had been working in the Amazon forest with the Pirahã tribe for years, and became Associate Professor and chair of the Department of Linguistics at the University of Pittsburgh, argued in this paper that the adoption of a param- etrized neo- Reichenbachian model of tense syntax was able to account for tense- related facts in Pirahã, e.g., for its speakers’ lack of concern for precision in time statements. His conclusion was that this model offered new support for Sapir’s lin- guistic relativity hypothesis. He was thus suggesting a syntactical solution for what rather a context dependent, viz. pragmatic phenomenon. Everett’s hypothesis thus fit as a glove P&C’s objectives: the investigation of the interdependence between the use of language and cognition, the growing development of new trends in linguistics and in the recently born Cognitive Sciences, the acknowledgment of the necessarily interdisciplinary character of these disciplines, and the elabora-
Recommended publications
  • REVIEWS Daniel L. Everett, How Language Began
    J. Linguistics (2017), 1–5. c Cambridge University Press 2017 doi:10.1017/S0022226717000172 REVIEWS Daniel L. Everett, How language began: The story of humanity’s greatest invention. New York: W. W. Norton, 2107. Pp. xviii + 306. Reviewed by NORBERT FRANCIS, Northern Arizona University This new book by Daniel Everett stands as a significant contribution to the discussion of language evolution because it puts forward the strongest claims so far in what has been an important exchange, probably the most visible in recent years. While How Language Began (henceforth HLB) is written for a general readership, the main proposals are presented clearly, drawing the lines of the debate sharper than in previous turns. Its strong hypotheses now set the stage for better understanding the points in contention and for drawing us closer to resolving them. Crucially, the first chapters chart a space of common ground with other approaches to the study of human evolution: • the endorsement of a materialist (evidence-based) approach to the natural science of language, and the centrality of natural selection and sexual selection as mechanisms of change; • the systems that arise should not be considered to be optimal in their design, • the out-of-Africa hypothesis, and against polygenesis; • following from the above, the gradual emergence of language capabilities (as opposed to a saltationist view); • that the faculty of language(narrow) consists of more than recursive procedures; and, • most importantly, the requisite participation of cultural/conceptual knowledge and communicative function as forces that drove the emergence of language in the Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness. In other words, it is unlikely that the core of linguistic competence (the narrow subset of the language faculty), as it emerged in humans, can be restricted to recursion.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae 04/04/2021
    Curriculum Vitae 04/04/2021 PETER CARRUTHERS [email protected] http://faculty.philosophy.umd.edu/pcarruthers/ 7400 Glenside Drive Department of Philosophy Takoma Park University of Maryland MD 20912-6923 College Park, MD 20742 Tel.: 301 270 5107 Tel.: 301 405 5705 EMPLOYMENT HISTORY 2001-present UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND, COLLEGE PARK. Professor (2001–2018), Department of Philosophy; Distinguished University Professor (2018–present). Chair of Department (June 2001–December 2008). Associate Member, Neuroscience and Cognitive Science Program (NACS) (2002–present). Member, Brain and Behavior Initiative (BBI) (2016–present). 1991-2001 UNIVERSITY OF SHEFFIELD. Senior Lecturer (1991-2), Department of Philosophy; Professor (1992-2001). Head of Department (1993-8). Director, Hang Seng Centre for Cognitive Studies (1992-2000). 1985-91 UNIVERSITY OF ESSEX. Lecturer (tenured) (1985-9), Department of Philosophy; Senior Lecturer (1989-91). 1989-90 — UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN, ANN ARBOR. Visiting Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy. 1981-85 QUEEN’S UNIVERSITY OF BELFAST. Lecturer, Department of Philosophy (confirmed in post 1984). 1979-81 UNIVERSITY OF ST. ANDREWS. Temporary Lecturer, Department of Logic and Metaphysics. 1978-79 UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD, LADY MARGARET HALL. Temporary Lecturer (part-time: 6 hours tutoring per week). EDUCATION AND QUALIFICATIONS 1977-79 UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD, BALLIOL COLLEGE. D.Phil. in Philosophy (1980). Thesis: “The place of the private language argument in the philosophy of language.” (Supervisor: Michael Dummett. Examiners: Elizabeth Anscombe, Christopher Peacocke.) 1971-77 UNIVERSITY OF LEEDS. M.Phil. in Philosophy (1977). Thesis: “Blame: an analysis.” (Supervisor: Jennifer Jackson.) Papers: Wittgenstein, Philosophical Logic, Political Philosophy. B.A. (Honors) in Philosophy (1975). 1st Class. “Congratulatory 1st.” Carruthers CV 2 HONORS AND AWARDS 2020: Graduate Faculty Mentor of the Year Award (one of 10 awards made annually among faculty at the University of Maryland).
    [Show full text]
  • A Cognitive Theory of Pretense
    A revised and abbreviated version of this paper is forthcoming in Cognition. Archived at Website for the Rutgers University Research Group on Evolution and Higher Cognition. A Cognitive Theory of Pretense Shaun Nichols Department of Philosophy College of Charleston Charleston, SC 29424 [email protected] and Stephen Stich Department of Philosophy and Center for Cognitive Science Rutgers University New Brunswick, NJ 08901 [email protected] Contents 1. Introduction 2. Some Examples of Pretense 3. Some Features of Pretense 4. A Theory about the Cognitive Mechanisms Underlying Pretense 5. A Comparison with Other Theories 6. Conclusion Abstract Recent accounts of pretense have been underdescribed in a number of ways. In this paper, we present a much more explicit cognitive account of pretense. We begin by presenting a number of real examples of pretense in children and adults. These examples bring out several features of pretense that any adequate theory of pretense must accommodate, and we use these features to develop our theory of pretense. On our theory, pretense representations are contained in a separate workspace, a Possible World Box which is part of the basic architecture of the human mind. The representations in the Possible World Box can have the same content as beliefs. Indeed, we suggest that pretense representations are in the same representational "code" as beliefs and that the representations in the Possible World Box are processed by the same inference and UpDating mechanisms that operate over real beliefs. Our model also posits a Script Elaborator which is implicated in the embellishment that occurs in pretense. Finally, we claim that the behavior that is seen in pretend play is motivated not from a "pretend desire", but from a real desire to act in a way that fits the description being constructed in the Possible World Box.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastive Linguistics; Determiners Language Classification
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 430 401 FL 025 837 TITLE Notes on Linguistics, 1998. INSTITUTION Summer Inst. of Linguistics, Dallas, TX. ISSN ISSN-0736-0673 PUB DATE 1998-00-00 NOTE 242p.; For the 1997 "Notes on Linguistics," see ED 415 721. PUB TYPE Collected Works - Serials (022) JOURNAL CIT Notes on Linguistics; n80-83 1998 EDRS PRICE MF01/PC10 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Book Reviews; Computer Software; Computer Software Development; Contrastive Linguistics; Determiners (Languages); Doctoral Dissertations; English; Greek; Language Classification; Language Patterns; *Language Research; *Linguistic Theory; Research Methodology; *Semantics; Technical Writing; *Uncommonly Taught Languages; Workshops IDENTIFIERS Alamblak; Bungku Tolaki Languages; Chamicuro; Kham ABSTRACT The four issues of the journal of language research and linguistic theory include these articles: "Notes on Determiners in Chamicuro" (Steve Parker); Lingualinks Field Manual Development" (Larry Hayashi); "Comments from an International Linguistics Consultant: Thumbnail Sketch" (Austin Hale); "Carlalinks Workshop" (Andy Black); "Implications of Agreement Languages for Linguistics" (W. P. Lehmann); and "The Semantics of Reconciliation in Three Languages" (Les Bruce) . Dissertation abstracts, book reviews, and professional notes are included in each issue.(MSE) ******************************************************************************** Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best that can be made from the original document. ******************************************************************************** NOTES ON LINGUISTICS Number 80 February 1998 Number 81 May 1998 Number 82 August 1998 Number 83 November 1998 SUMMER INSTITUTE OF LINGUISTICS 7500 WEST CAMP WISDOM ROAD DALLAS, TEXAS 75236 USA U.S. DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE AND office ot Educatlonal Research and Improvement DISSEMINATE THIS MATERIAL HAS EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES INFORMATION BEEN GRANTED BY CENTER (ERIC) \This document has been reproduced as received from the person or organization originating it.
    [Show full text]
  • Newsletter Template
    Rutgers Philosophy Newsletter Spring 2009 Rutgers is once again ranked 2nd overall Philosophy Department in the US… Inside: Every two years, Blackwell Publishers releases its Philosophical The doctoral program Gourmet Report—a ranking of the fifty best Philosophy departments 4 continues to attract top in the English-speaking world, based on the reputation and graduate students. Meet the accomplishments of their faculty members. In the February 2009 current group and learn what edition, Rutgers was once again ranked 2nd overall in the United rd recent PhDs have done. States (after NYU) and 3 overall in the world (after NYU and Oxford). In the specialty rankings, Rutgers was voted the top department internationally for Philosophy of Language and The New York Times highlights Cognitive Science, and tied for #1 in Epistemology and Mind. 6 Rutgers’ undergraduate Rutgers was among the top four departments for Metaphysics. And Philosophy program. Rutgers was within the top ten for Philosophy of Science, Applied Ethics, Decision Theory and Early Modern Philosophy. The surveys reflect the outstanding strength our department has in core areas. A Letter from the Chair 8 See more of the rankings at www.philosophicalgourmet.com. Catching up with the Faculty: New Research by Rutgers Professors; Conferences, Talks and Upcoming Projects This past year has brought some selection. In April, Larry Temkin changes to the Rutgers faculty. hosted a two-day conference While Barry Loewer continued on human rights in honor of as Chair, Jeff King took over as James Griffin. On May 13th- Graduate Vice-Chair and 14thRutgers will be hosting its first Martin Lin as Undergraduate Foundations of Statistical Vice-Chair.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Philosophy Jordan Kiper, Stephen Stich, H. Clark Barrett
    Experimental Philosophy Jordan Kiper, Stephen Stich, H. Clark Barrett, & Edouard Machery Kiper, J., Stich, S., Barrett, H.C., & Machery, E. (in press). Experimental philosophy. In D. Ludwig, I. Koskinen, Z. Mncube, L. Poliseli, & L. Reyes-Garcia (Eds.), Global Epistemologies and Philosophies of Science. New York, NY: Routledge. Acknowledgments: This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation. Abstract Philosophers have argued that some philosophical concepts are universal, but it is increasingly clear that the question of philosophical universals is far from settled, and that far more cross- cultural research is necessary. In this chapter, we illustrate the relevance of investigating philosophical concepts and describe results from recent cross-cultural studies in experimental philosophy. We focus on the concept of knowledge and outline an ongoing project, the Geography of Philosophy Project, which empirically investigates the concepts of knowledge, understanding, and wisdom across cultures, languages, religions, and socioeconomic groups. We outline questions for future research on philosophical concepts across cultures, with an aim towards resolving questions about universals and variation in philosophical concepts. 1 Introduction For centuries, thinkers have urged that fundamental philosophical concepts, such as the concepts of knowledge or right and wrong, are universal or at least shared by all rational people (e.g., Plato 1892/375 BCE; Kant, 1998/1781; Foot, 2003). Yet many social scientists, in particular cultural anthropologists (e.g., Boas, 1940), but also continental philosophers such as Foucault (1969) have remained skeptical of these claims.
    [Show full text]
  • Language Myths
    Language in popular culture Language myths Language myths LING 200: Introduction to the Study of Language Hadas Kotek April 2016 Hadas Kotek Language myths Language in popular culture Language myths Outline 1 Language in popular culture The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis An example: Whorfian Economics 2 Language myths How many words do Eskimos have for snow? Color terms Recursion and the Pirahã Slides credit: Lauren Clemens, Sabine Iatridou Hadas Kotek Language myths Language in popular culture The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis Language myths An example: Whorfian Economics Language in popular culture It is not hard to find opinions and speculation on language Perhaps because the structure of language seems so readily accessible, many of us have intuitions about the way language and language acquisition works But. We saw in this class that much of language involves rules you were not explicitly aware of. We are not as well-equipped as we think to make judgements about how language works. ¾ My aim today: Show you that you need to use your LING 200 knowledge to evaluate claims about language. Hadas Kotek Language myths Language in popular culture The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis Language myths An example: Whorfian Economics Language in popular culture The question ¾ Does language shape our view of the world? Not our experience with language . bilingualism dyslexia study abroad . but actual facts about our language Many of you will say “yes” I would like to challenge you on this belief. Hadas Kotek Language myths Language in popular culture The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis Language myths An example: Whorfian Economics The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis: Language determines thought.
    [Show full text]
  • REVIEWS Daniel L. Everett, How Language Began
    J. Linguistics (2017), 1–5. c Cambridge University Press 2017 doi:10.1017/S0022226717000172 REVIEWS Daniel L. Everett, How language began: The story of humanity’s greatest invention. New York: W. W. Norton, 2107. Pp. xviii + 306. Reviewed by NORBERT FRANCIS, Northern Arizona University This new book by Daniel Everett stands as a significant contribution to the discussion of language evolution because it puts forward the strongest claims so far in what has been an important exchange, probably the most visible in recent years. While How Language Began (henceforth HLB) is written for a general readership, the main proposals are presented clearly, drawing the lines of the debate sharper than in previous turns. Its strong hypotheses now set the stage for better understanding the points in contention and for drawing us closer to resolving them. Crucially, the first chapters chart a space of common ground with other approaches to the study of human evolution: • the endorsement of a materialist (evidence-based) approach to the natural science of language, and the centrality of natural selection and sexual selection as mechanisms of change; • the systems that arise should not be considered to be optimal in their design, • the out-of-Africa hypothesis, and against polygenesis; • following from the above, the gradual emergence of language capabilities (as opposed to a saltationist view); • that the faculty of language(narrow) consists of more than recursive procedures; and, • most importantly, the requisite participation of cultural/conceptual knowledge and communicative function as forces that drove the emergence of language in the Environment of Evolutionary Adaptedness. In other words, it is unlikely that the core of linguistic competence (the narrow subset of the language faculty), as it emerged in humans, can be restricted to recursion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Instinct
    OPINION THE BIG IDEA The social instinct The cultural foundations of human language is a story very much in the making, says Daniel Everett, because it must first challenge the claim that language is innate NOTHING sets Homo sapiens apart from other I must admit I am puzzled by the continued species more clearly than the possession of popularity of nativism. For decades, research language and culture. Using features of supported the idea that language is formed by language unique to our species we can a number of independent factors, leaving communicate almost anything that pops into little, if any, work for a “universal grammar” or our heads. This capacity enables us to learn “language instinct” to do. Some researchers go from and elaborate on the lessons of previous so far as to argue that universal grammar is generations: we use values acquired earlier, nothing more than tautology: humans have plus trial and error, to improve our lives. The language because humans have language. unbeatable combination of language and It may be that nativism persists because it culture has made us lords of the Earth. seems hard to falsify. However, according to The question for anthropologists and Philip Lieberman, a cognitive scientist at linguists, however, is not why language and Brown University, Rhode Island, it makes one culture are so great, but what makes them testable, if paradoxical, prediction. According possible in the first place. p to universal grammar, not all features of We know that these two cognitive-social language would in fact be universal. Under tools are related: the burning issue is to nativism, we would expect that some humans understand the nature of this relationship.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Reviews
    Journal of cognition and culture �4 (�0�4) �49–�55 brill.com/jocc Book Reviews Joshua Alexander Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction. Polity Press: Cambridge, MA, 2012. US$22.95 Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction is somewhat narrower in scope than Experimental Philosophy by Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols (2008, Oxford University Press, Oxford) and broader than Experiments in Ethics by Kwame Anthony Appiah (2008, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA). The brevity, concise writing style, and focus will make Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction a useful background text for undergraduate teaching and the best introduction to this exciting field for some time to come. Because the field of experimental philosophy is new, customary readers of Journal of Cognition and Culture may not be aware of the purview of such a book. First, Alexander’s book requires background knowledge in analytic phi- losophy; the audience is exclusively analytic philosophy students and profes- sionals. This allows the book its tight focus but gives the impression that, just like in mainstream analytic philosophy, philosophers are still talking amongst themselves. For example, we don’t have an account of the treatment of the cognitive psychology of reasoning and other cognate disciplines in this book. This, and larger discussion of the work of Jesse Prinz, Shaun Nichols and Shaun Gallagher would have been most welcome. Second, Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction appears to dichotomize experimental philosophy and main- stream analytic philosophy in ways that oversimplify how philosophers work. It omits any consideration of the historical tradition of experimental philoso- phy that went under the name ‘natural philosophy’. Overall Experimental Philosophy does not aim to answer fundamental ques- tions about the relationship of philosophy to empirical research, but rather aims to provide helpful, clearly structured summaries of articles, with glosses on them, that have appeared in the recent experimental philosophical litera- ture.
    [Show full text]
  • Recursion and the Lexicon* Jan Koster University of Groningen
    Recursion and the Lexicon* Jan Koster University of Groningen 1. A critique of biolinguistics Current theorizing about the human language faculty, particularly about recursion, is dominated by the biolinguistics perspective. This perspective has been part of the generative enterprise since its inception and can be summarized as follows: The core of language is individual-psychological and may ultimately be explained in terms of human biology. A classical formulation of this program was Lenneberg (1967) and it was revitalized recently by Jenkins (2000) and particularly by Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch (2002) (henceforth: HCF). According to HCF, recursion (in the form of Merge) is the core of the human language faculty biologically conceived. The biological perspective is far from self-evidently correct and, in fact, goes against a long tradition that emphasized the cultural, conventional nature of language. This tradition goes back at least to Aristotle’s De Interpretatione and became the core idea about language since the late Enlightenment and Romanticism, thanks to the influence of Herder, Von Humboldt and others. Most early 20th-century views were offshoots of the great conceptions formulated around the turn of the 18th century. Thus, Ferdinand de Saussure followed German Romanticism in this respect, as did the great American structuralists Franz Boas and Edward Sapir. Saussure was also influenced by one of the founding fathers of sociology, Émile Durkheim, who argued that certain social facts could not be reduced to individual psychology or biology.1 Also philosophers like Wittgenstein and Popper followed the European tradition, the former with his emphasis on the public and language game-dependent nature of linguistic rules, the latter by stipulating that language belongs to his (pseudo-technical) conception of supra-individual human culture known as “world 3” (Popper 1972).
    [Show full text]
  • Society for Philosophy and Psychology
    PROGRAM OF THE 36th MEETING OF THE SOCIETY FOR PHILOSOPHY AND PSYCHOLOGY LEWIS AND CLARK COLLEGE, PORTLAND, OREGON JUNE 9-12, 2010 WEDNESDAY, JUNE 9 7:45-4:00 Pre-conference Workshop: Howard 102 The Psychology and Philosophy of Morality Box lunch included in the workshop registration fee Fiery Cushman, Harvard University / Brown University Julia Driver, Washington University in St. Louis Susan Dwyer, University of Maryland, Baltimore County Joshua Knobe, Yale University Debra Lieberman, University of Miami Thomas Nadelhoffer, Dickinson College / Duke University David Pizarro, Cornell University Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Duke University Jen Wright, College of Charleston Liane Young, MIT / Boston College 4:20-4:30 SPP 2010 Conference Welcome Council Chambers 4:30-5:45 Invited Speaker Council Chambers Chair: Ron Mallon, University of Utah Stephen Stich, Rutgers University, & Wesley Buckwalter, CUNY Graduate Center, Gender and Philosophical Intuitions: Why Are There So Few Women in Philosophy? 5:45-6:30 Poster Madness! Council Chambers 6:30-7:30 Poster Session 1 and Reception Howard Halls 1 THURSDAY, JUNE 10 8:00-8:30 Coffee/Light Breakfast 8:30-9:45 Invited Speaker Council Chambers Chair: Jen Cole Wright, College of Charleston Linda Skitka, University of Illinois at Chicago, The Social and Political Implications of Moral Conviction 9:45-9:55 Break 9:55-11:55 Invited Symposium: Cognizing Human Groups Council Chambers Chair: Colin Allen, Indiana University Katie Kinzler, University of Chicago, The Native Language of Social Cognition Edouard Machery, University of Pittsburg, Title TBA 11:55-1:10 Lunch Break SPP Diversity Committee Meeting Trail Room 1:10-2:10 On the Cutting Edge, Session 1 Howard 102 Chair: David Rose, Carnegie-Mellon University Jonathan Phillips, Yale University, Luke Misenheimer, University of California, Berkeley, & Joshua Knobe, Yale University, “Love and Happiness” Jennifer Zamzow, University of Arizona, Perspective Taking in Moral Judgments Steve Guglielmo, Andrew Monroe, & Kyle Dillon, Brown University, “Coming Up Short vs.
    [Show full text]