Formal Representations of Suspended Judgment

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Formal Representations of Suspended Judgment Formal Representation s of Suspended Judgment Doctoral thesis for obtaining the academic degree Doctor of Philosophy (Dr.phil.) submitted by Ali Zolfagharian at the Faculty of Humanities Department of Philosophy iii Konstanz, 2019 Konstanzer Online-Publikations-System (KOPS) URL: http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:352-2-gpnx2i068ae09 Introduction iv The distinction between ignorance and suspension v Formal Representations of Suspended Judgment Doctoral thesis for obtaining the academic degree Doctor of Philosophy (Dr.phil.) submitted by Ali Zolfagharian at the Faculty of Humanities Department of Philosophy Konstanz, 2019 Introduction vi Date of the oral examination: 23.04.2020 1. Reviewer: Prof. Spohn 2. Reviewer: Prof. Müller 3. Reviewer: Jun.-Prof. Dr. Carolin Antos-Kuby The distinction between ignorance and suspension vii This page intentionally left blank Introduction viii Contents 0. Introduction 1 1. Suspension of Judgment 4 1 The distinction between ignorance and suspension 6 2 The necessity of non-belief for suspension 9 3 Believing and suspending at the same time 14 3.1 Two-minded 14 3.2 Suspending while having a high degree of belief 15 4 Is suspension a negation-invariant operator? 17 5 Degrees of suspended judgment 18 6 Qualitative and Quantitative epistemic states 20 7 Doxastic attitudes: definitions and relationships 22 2. Belief Revision 24 1 Traditional Belief Revision (TBR) 27 1.1 Logical consequence operator 28 1.2 Belief set 28 1.3 Belief base 30 1.4 Update rules 30 1.4.1 Expansion 31 1.4.2 Contraction 32 1.4.3 Revision 38 1.4.4 Two general rules 40 2 The representation of doxastic attitudes in TBR. 41 2.1 Disbelief set 41 2.2 Suspension and ignorance 42 3 System of Spheres and Indeterministic Belief Revision 44 3.1 Indeterministic Belief Revision: from spheres to ellipses 47 3.1.1 relational belief revision 47 3.1.2 Epistemic Entrenchment 50 4 The representation of suspended judgment in IndBR 52 4.1 Accepted proposition 52 The distinction between ignorance and suspension ix 4.2 Basic doxastic attitudes 53 4.3 Epistemic bi-lattice 53 4.4 Some unwanted results 55 5 Qualitative acceptance Revision 56 5.1 Acceptance base 58 5.2 Inferable sets 59 5.3 Accepted in 60 5.4 Assessable proposition 60 5.5 Accepted proposition 61 5.6 Basic doxastic attitudes 61 5.7 Conditionally accepted propositions 62 5.8 Epistemic change 62 5.8.1 Expansion 63 5.8.2 Contraction 63 3. Bayesian Epistemology 69 1 Preliminary 73 1.1 Probabilism 75 1.2 regularity 75 1.3 Principle of indifference 76 1.4 Principal principle 77 1.5 Unwanted result 80 1.6 Reflection principle 81 1.7 Conditionalization 81 1.8 Crucial questions 82 2 Representing the degree of suspension and ignorance 82 3 Dutch book argument for probabilism 84 3.1 Czech book argument 86 3.1.1 Ignorance 87 3.2 Package principle and betting on our actions 88 4 Quantitative notion of belief and basic doxastic attitudes 89 5 BE cannot distinguish suspension and ignorance 90 Introduction x 4. Dempster-Shafer theory 92 1 Preliminary 93 1.1 Set of possibilities 93 1.2 Mass Function 95 1.3 Belief Function 100 1.4 Plausibility function 103 2 The degrees of suspension, disbelief, and ignorance 104 3 Qualitative doxastic attitudes 107 3.1 From belief function to the quaternary epistemic states 109 3.2 Truth table (as a four-valued logic) 116 3.3 Qualitative Ignorance and suspended judgment 119 4 Suspension/Ignorance and the rule of combination 120 4.1 The Dempster rule of combination. 121 4.2 Yager’s rule 124 4.3 Inagaki’s unified combination rule 127 4.4 Dubois and Prade’s disjunctive consensus rule 128 5 Basic doxastic attitudes in DS 129 5. Ranking theory 131 1 Classic Ranking Theory 133 1.1 Negative Ranking function 133 1.2 Positive Ranking function 134 1.3 Two-sided ranking function 135 1.4 Conditional Rank 135 1.5 Spohn Conditionalization 136 1.6 Regularity 137 1.7 Qualitative belief and degree of unopinionatedness 137 1.8 Doxastic attitudes in RT 138 1.9 What are Ranks? 140 1.9.1 The quantitative nature of ranks 141 1.9.2 The qualitative nature of ranks 146 1.10 Grading of suspension 149 1.11 Qualitative Suspension and Ignorance 151 2 General Ranking Theory 152 The distinction between ignorance and suspension xi 2.1 Basic ranking function 153 2.2 Acceptance base 153 2.3 Assessable propositions 154 2.4 Genral ranking function 156 2.5 Accepted propositions 159 2.6 Belief, disbelief, suspension, and ignorance 160 2.7 General positive and negative ranking function. 161 3 Comparison between RT and GRT 162 6. Acceptance Revision 163 1 Definitions and relationships among doxastic attitudes 164 2 TBR, IndBR, and QAR 164 3 BE and DS 166 3.1 Definition of quantitative doxastic attitudes 168 3.2 Acceptance threshold 168 3.3 Unwanted results 169 4 RT and GRT 170 5 Acceptance revision 170 5.1 Mass function 171 5.2 Acceptance base 171 5.3 Acceptance function 172 5.3.1 Unknown propositions or non-assessable propositions 173 5.3.2 Assessable propositions 173 5.4 Accepted propositions 175 5.5 Qualitative doxastic attitudes 175 5.6 Quantitative doxastic attitudes 175 6 Comparison 176 Bibliography 178 Introduction xii To Sahar The distinction between ignorance and suspension xiii Acknowledgements I would like to express my sincere gratitude to Prof. Wolfgnag Spohn, for his continuous supervision, guidance, inspirations, criticism and his invaluable support. I would also like to express my sincere appreciation to Prof. Thomas Müller for his encouragements and guidance. I’ve participated in his colloquium for six semesters, it was an enjoyable and valuable experience. I would like to extend my sincere gratitude to the committee of LGFG for the scholarship. Their trust in me was heartwarming. Introduction xiv FORMAL REPRESENTATIONS OF SUSPENDED JUDGMENT Abstract This work investigates various theories in Formal Epistemology in order to observe their capacity of distinguishing suspended judgment from ignorance. Besides, it suggests how every theory in formal epistemology could be changed and improved to represent suspended judgment properly. After an inquiry about the nature of suspended judgment and introducing its characteristics, I observe and suggest some improvement in various theories in formal epistemology namely AGM belief revision, Indeterministic belief revision, Bayesian Epistemology, Dempster Shafer theory of evidence, and Ranking Theory. The text also suggests a new theory, the Acceptance Revision, which can properly represent all doxastic attitudes namely belief, disbelief, suspended judgment and ignorance. The distinction between ignorance and suspension xv FORMALE DARSTELLUNGEN VON URTEILSENTHALTUNG Zusammenfassung Diese Arbeit untersucht verschiedene Theorien der formalen Erkenntnistheorie, um ihre Leistungsfähigkeit dahingehend zu beurteilen, ob sie die doxastische Einstellung der Urteilsenthaltung von bloßem Nichtwissen unterscheiden können. Außerdem werden in der Arbeit Vorschläge gemacht, wie jede Theorie in der formalen Erkenntnistheorie geändert und verbessert werden kann, um die Urteilsenthaltung angemessen abzubilden. Nach einer Untersuchung des Phänomens der Urteilsenthaltung und einer Einführung in ihre Charakteristika, schlage ich eine Verbesserung verschiedener Theorien in der formalen Erkenntnistheorie vor, nämlich AGM Belief Revision, Indeterministic Belief Revision, Bayesian Epistemology, Dempster Shafer Theory of Evidence und Ranking Theory. In meiner Arbeit schlage ich auch eine neue Theorie vor, die ich Acceptance Revision nenne, die alle doxastischen Einstellungen richtig darstellen kann, nämlich Glaube, Ablehnung, Urteilsenthaltung und Nichtwissen. 0 Introduction Ideas and perspectives related to the suspension of judgment are scattered like an archipelago. This text gives a detailed map and insight into the meaning of suspension of judgment and its formal representation in various prevalent theories in formal epistemology. I found that reaching a unified account of suspended judgment is not achievable (it was not acheivable regarding belief as well). During the inquiry, I tried to keep the plurality of various possible approaches, written and unwritten; to help the reader to form her ideas if she does not agree with the conclusion. In the first chapter, the nature of suspended judgment is discussed. There are five key questions which shed light on the nature of the suspension of judgment (suspension). This inquiry leads us into ten formulae which hold in the entire Introduction 2 dissertation. This chapter contains the main assumptions, the adopted philosophical approaches, and the definitions of basic and primary concepts. From the second chapter, we play the game of mathematics-meet-epistemology to find the proper formal representation of suspension. The starting point of the chapter is the preliminary report of the belief revision theory which considers the qualitative notion of belief to represent our doxastic states. The inadequacy of the belief revision in distinguishing ignorance and suspension compels us to turn to indeterministic belief revision. This version can represent formally all four possible doxastic states namely; belief, disbelief, suspension, and ignorance. For a better interpretation of the indeterministic belief revision, the four-valued logic by Belnap is applied. The chapter plays an instructive role in understanding the issues related to the formal representation of suspended judgment. Chapter three addresses the quantitative notion of belief by discussing Bayesian epistemology. Bayesian probability and the development of probability theory by Kolmogorov helped epistemologists to construct a formal representation of degrees of belief. Bayesian epistemology is the received view in formal epistemology. One of its pillars is the Dutch book argument. I give some counterexample to invalidate the theory. Also, it fails to distinguish suspension and ignorance. The problem arises because of the principle of indifference. We learn about Dempster-Shafer theory of evidence as a generalization of Bayesian epistemology in chapter four. The principle of indifference would not be applied in the theory of evidence.
Recommended publications
  • Responding to Skepticism About Doxastic Agency
    Erkenn (2018) 83:627–645 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9906-2 ORIGINAL RESEARCH Responding to Skepticism About Doxastic Agency Miriam Schleifer McCormick1 Received: 16 April 2016 / Accepted: 9 May 2017 / Published online: 8 June 2017 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017 Abstract My main aim is to argue that most conceptions of doxastic agency do not respond to the skeptic’s challenge. I begin by considering some reasons for thinking that we are not doxastic agents. I then turn to a discussion of those who try to make sense of doxastic agency by appeal to belief’s reasons-responsive nature. What they end up calling agency is not robust enough to satisfy the challenge posed by the skeptics. To satisfy the skeptic, one needs to make sense of the possibility of believing for nonevidential reasons. While this has been seen as an untenable view for both skeptics and anti-skeptics, I conclude by suggesting it is a position that has been too hastily dismissed. 1 Introduction In what sense or to what extent is agency exercised in the doxastic realm? Some argue that the kind of control we have over beliefs is sufficient for doxastic agency, while others argue that the nature of beliefs precludes agency being exercised in what we believe. But getting clear on the nature of these disagreements is difficult because the disputants do not always share a common notion of what is required for agency in general, and doxastic agency in particular. A skeptic about doxastic agency may agree with everything an anti-skeptic says but insist that none of what is proposed counts as real agency.
    [Show full text]
  • A Social Solution to the Puzzle of Doxastic Responsibility: a Two-Dimensional Account of Responsibility for Belief
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Forthcoming in Synthese 1 A Social Solution to the Puzzle of Doxastic Responsibility: A Two-Dimensional Account of Responsibility for Belief Robert Carry Osborne (This is a final, pre-copyedit version of an article published in Synthese. The final authenticated version is available online at: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11229-020-02637-9) 1. Introduction There are various, well-known difficulties surrounding the notion of doxastic responsibility and the so-called ‘ethics of belief’. The “puzzle of doxastic responsibility,” as Miriam McCormick (2015) has recently called it, arises from the tension between some version of the following three claims, each intuitively plausible on its own, but together jointly inconsistent: (RESPONSIBLE) We sometimes rightly hold agents responsible for their doxastic attitudes. (CONTROL) Voluntary control over X is a prerequisite for responsibility for X. (NON-VOLUNTARY) Beliefs are not subject to the will, that is, we lack voluntary control over them.1 The puzzle, then, is why beliefs seem to be the kinds of things for which we can rightly be held responsible, and yet do not appear to be something over which we exercise direct (voluntary or intentional) control.2 A solution to the puzzle seems to require that we reject at least one of the three claims above. As a result, the puzzle has three general answers: (a) Reject (RESPONSIBLE) and thus deny that beliefs are the proper objects of normative assessment, and so deny that anyone 1 McHugh (2017) also discusses a version of the same puzzle, which he calls “the problem of epistemic responsibility,” though his version involves four claims, and depends explicitly on a comparison with the kind of control we have over our (bodily) actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Epistemology and the Project of Mapping Science
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2015 Social Epistemology and the Project of Mapping Science Kamili Posey Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1097 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! ! SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE PROJECT OF MAPPING SCIENCE BY KAMILI POSEY A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York. 2015 © 2015 KAMILI POSEY All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Nikolas Pappas ______________________________ ______________________________ ______________________________ Date Chair of Examining Committee Iakovos Vasiliou ______________________________ ______________________________ ______________________________ Date Executive Officer Samir Chopra ______________________________________________ Linda Alcoff ______________________________________________ Robert Sinclair ______________________________________________ Supervisory Committee THE
    [Show full text]
  • Why Suspend Judging?∗ Jane Friedman [email protected] | 06/2017
    Why Suspend Judging?∗ Jane Friedman [email protected] j 06/2017 1 Introduction Even though philosophers have been thinking about suspension of judgment for nearly as long as they’ve been thinking about anything, and contemporary discussions have it placed as traditional epistemology’s other doxastic attitude, there is only limited consensus about the nature of the state and generally very little said about its point or purpose or role in our doxastic lives (at least in com- parison to its obviously far more charming doxastic bedfellow, belief). In this paper I want to try to say a little bit on these matters by providing a framework within which we can begin to answer the titular question here. The framework will tell us more both about the nature and function of suspension of judgment as well as give us some guidance as to its “normative profile” (when we should suspend, have reason to suspend, are justified in suspending and so on). The general thought is that suspension of judgment is closely tied to inquiry. In fact I want to argue that one is inquiring into some matter if and only if one is suspended on the matter.1 Tying suspension of judgment to inquiry in this way brings us back to some of the earliest views of the state. One of the thoughts that emerges in the work of both Sextus Empiricus and Descartes is that suspension of judgment is closely connected to inquiry and perhaps even that suspending is itself a way of being in an inquiring mode or frame of mind.2 The thought that suspending might ∗Please cite final version: Friedman, J.
    [Show full text]
  • I Am Going to Deal with the Foundations of First Philosophy in Its Entirety
    FOUNDATIONALISM & THE STRUCTURE OF EPISTEMIC WARRANT I am going to deal with the foundations of First Philosophy in its entirety. —Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy The basics of foundationalism Foundationalism is the classic view regarding the nature of warranted belief acceptance, non-acceptance and the suspending of judgement. It has been advocated by such historically significant philosophers as Aristotle, Aquinas, Descartes, Locke, Hume, Reid, and Kant as well as such significant contemporaries as A.J. Ayer, C.I. Lewis and Roderick Chisholm. It has been the subject of serious philosophical attacks by such prominent philosophers as Donald Davidson, Keith Lehrer, Laurence Bonjour and Richard Rorty.1 What is foundationalism, however? Given that foundationalism is a theory about the nature of epistemic warrant, it should be clear that it is a normative theory—i.e., it tells us when we are warranted, reasonable, or permitted to assent, not assent or suspend judgment regarding a proposition. How does it differ from the internalist and externalist views of epistemic warrant we have been discussing? Most importantly, it tells us about the structure of epistemically warranted doxastic attitudes. That is, it tells us how our epistemically warranted doxastic attitudes are related to each other. Put differently, it tells us that every member of a cognitive being’s set of doxastic attitudes is organized and formally related in very important ways. What is that organization and formal relation? According to the foundationalist, genuine (propositional) knowledge and epistemically warranted belief has a two-tier structure: some instances of our knowledge and epistemically warranted belief are foundational and every other instance is non-foundational.
    [Show full text]
  • Questions for Uniqueness (3408 Words)
    1 Questions for Uniqueness (3408 words) Abstract: In this paper, I argue that the so-called Uniqueness Thesis, or Uniqueness, is untenable because we cannot conceive of epistemic rationality as free of any practical components. Uniqueness states that given the same body of evidence, there is at most one rational doxastic attitude taken towards any proposition. Some authors, on the other hand, argue that it is rationally permissible to hold differing doxastic attitudes; call that view Permissivism. First, I provide a precise formulation for Uniqueness and evaluate some of the arguments for and against it. I show that many extant arguments against Uniqueness are question-begging and why these arguments fail. Finally, I offer a better argument against Uniqueness. My argument brings out that rational belief is not determined solely by evidence but also by the questions that guide one’s inquiry. 1. Introduction Given the same body of evidence, is it rational to possess differing doxastic attitudes towards a certain proposition? Some authors argue that it is permissible; call that Permissivism. Others oppose this view and argue for the so-called Uniqueness Thesis, or Uniqueness, which states that for agents with the same body of total evidence, there is at most one rational doxastic attitude taken towards any proposition. What I argue is that Uniqueness is untenable because we cannot conceive of epistemic rationality as free of any practical components. Although arguments have been provided for and against Uniqueness based on practical grounds, these arguments treat doxastic attitudes similarly with bodily actions. The practical component that I discuss here, on the other hand, is restricted to knowledge, i.e., how one inquires.
    [Show full text]
  • Agrippan Pyrrhonism and the Challenge of Disagreement
    Journal of Philosophical Research Volume 40 2015 pp. 23–39 AGRIPPAN PYRRHONISM AND THE CHALLENGE OF DISAGREEMENT DIEGO E. MACHUCA CONICET ABSTRACT: This paper argues for the following three claims. First, the Agrippan mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment. Second, the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Five Modes of Agrippa, which nonetheless does not prevent him from non-doxastically assenting to them. And third, some recent objec- tions to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist’s ad hominem style of argumentation and the real challenge posed by the mode from disagreement. I. INTRODUCTION The subject of this essay is the set of arguments known as the Five Modes of Agrippa, which are the most powerful weapons of the Pyrrhonian argumentative arsenal found in Sextus Empiricus’s extant works. My purpose is to offer an interpretation both of certain aspects of the challenge posed by these modes and of the Pyrrhonist’s attitude towards them. More precisely, I propose to show: (i) that the mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment; (ii) that the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Agrippan modes, which nonethe- less does not prevent him from assenting to them in a weak, non-doxastic way; and (iii) that some recent objections to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist’s ad hominem style of argumentation and the real challenge posed by the mode from disagreement.
    [Show full text]
  • Disagreeing with the Pyrrhonist? 25 2
    2 Disagreeing with the Pyrrhonist? Otávio Bueno 1. INTRODUCTION For the Pyrrhonian skeptic, disagreement is an integral part of the skepti- cal way of inquiry (see Pyrrhonian Outlines I 165).1 The fact that there is undecidable disagreement about a given issue makes the Pyrrhonian skeptic unable to decide that issue, and suspension of judgment emerges. But is sus- pension of judgment the appropriate response in this case? In this paper, I address two related topics. In the bulk of the paper, I exam- ine critically Jonathan Barnes’ contention to the effect that disagreement alone is not enough to yield suspension of judgment; additional Agrippa’s modes need to be invoked as well (Barnes 1990: ch. 1). I argue that noth- ing prevents the Pyrrhonian skeptic from suspending judgment only due to disagreement. In fact, that is exactly what Sextus himself points out: “And because of the dispute [that is, the undecidable disagreement over a certain issue] we cannot choose or reject anything, and so end in suspension of judg- ment” (PH I 165; see Barnes 1990: 17). But does any form of disagreement yield suspension of judgment? To answer this question I consider recent debates about the epistemol- ogy of disagreement (see, e.g., Feldman & Warfield 2010). According to the Total Evidence View, what is reasonable for us to believe depends on the total evidence available to us.2 I argue that this view clearly provides a sufficient condition for the Pyrrhonian skeptic to suspend judgment due to disagreement alone. If the total evidence available to us—including the Pyrrhonian skeptic—does not favor any side of an issue over which there is disagreement, suspension of judgment is the natural outcome.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reliabilist Strategy for Solving the Problem of Induction by Fergus
    A Reliabilist Strategy for Solving the Problem of Induction By Fergus Dale Prien ORCID: 0000-0002-0940-9676 Dissertation Submitted in Total Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Research in Philosophy In the School of Historical and Philosophical Studies At the University of Melbourne Melbourne November 2019 Student Name: Fergus Prien Student Number: 588353 Acknowledgements There are a number of people and institutions that must be thanked for having made it possible for me to undertake this research project, and now complete it. I thank the Australian Government for supporting my research training at the University of Melbourne through the Research Training Program (RTP). I also thank the University of Melbourne and the School of Historical and Philosophical Studies in general for the opportunity to study at a great institution with learned academics who care about both the intellectual formation and general wellbeing of their students. More specifically, I would like to thank my primary supervisor, Howard Sankey, for the great multitude of hours that he has put in to both reviewing the various iterations of this dissertation (many far different from this one) and patiently helping me to think and write more critically. I have certainly grown in my scholarly ability and passion for philosophy under his supervision. I want to thank Brennan McDavid for her contribution to the supervision of my dissertation during her time at the University of Melbourne, as well as Greg Restall for agreeing to be my secondary supervisor quite late in this project. I also want to thank Brian Ellis, James Franklin, Callan Ledsham, Andrew Mullins, Xavier Symons, Brother Reginald Mary Chua, Fernando Jativa, and my fellow graduate philosophy students at the University of Melbourne who attended both or either of my seminar presentations – the feedback that I received from these people at specific points in my research certainly contributed to how I have formulated the thesis that I defend in this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Rainer Hirsch-Luipold, Reinhard Feldmeier und Heinz-Günther Nesselrath unter der Mitarbeit von Natalia Pedrique und Andrea Villani Band XXV Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary and Interpretative Essays by Katja Maria Vogt, Richard Bett, Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi, Christiana M. M. Olfert, Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley, and James Warren edited by Katja Maria Vogt Mohr Siebeck SAPERE is a Project of the Göttingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony. e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156430-7 ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio nal- bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http:// dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. www.mohr.de This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This ap- plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro- cessing in electronic systems. This book was supervised by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tübin- gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times.
    [Show full text]
  • Attitudes Beyond Belief: a Theory of Non-Doxastic Attitude Formation and Evaluation
    Attitudes Beyond Belief: A Theory of Non-Doxastic Attitude Formation and Evaluation by Daniel Drucker A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2017 Doctoral Committee: Associate Professor Eric Swanson, Chair Associate Professor Ezra Russell Keshet Associate Professor Sarah Swanson Moss Professor Brian James Weatherson Daniel Drucker [email protected] ORCID iD 0000-0001-6075-1170 ©Daniel Drucker 2017 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I’ll be brief; there’s no way to fully express my gratitude here. So, thank you to Eric Swanson for being the best possible committee chair, conscientious, empathetic, and wise; to Sarah Moss, for the intense and challenging conversations that always left me wanting to be and do better; to Brian Weatherson, for showing the importance of a view of the whole of philosophy; and to Ezra Keshet, for his generosity and example(s). Thanks to Michigan’s (sometimes honorary) philosophers, who’ve been my friends and family for six years, including: Chloe, Sara, Boris, Dave, Gordon, Kevin, Mara, Paul, Bryan, Francesca, Sarah B., Victor, Lingxi, Mercy, Guus, Alex, Matt, Josh, Sydney, Zoe,¨ Jim, Maria, Ishani, Eduardo, Neil, Filipa, Adam, Cat, Alvaro, Chip, Steve, Umer, Patrick, Nils, Rohan, Jamie, Rich, Damian, Nina, and Elise. It’s incredible that this kind of community exists; I’m unspeakably lucky to have been a part of it. The proof of this is how impossible it feels to leave it. Thanks to Plato and Agnes Callard, who shaped my worldview in ways I still don’t fully understand. Thanks to Hakeem Jerome Jefferson, one of the only non-philosophers on the list, for teaching me as much as any philosopher could.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Cicero's Eclectic Probabilism
    Revista Archai ISSN: 1984-249X Universidade de Brasília Skvirsky, Alexandre Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Revista Archai, no. 27, e02705, 2019 Universidade de Brasília DOI: https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=586161659005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Alexandre Skvirsky i https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9508-1023 [email protected] i Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro – Rio de Janeiro – RJ – Brasil SKVIRSKY, A. (2019). Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica. Archai 27, e02705. Abstract: The objective is to show the peculiar way in which Cicero’s philosophical thinking is original and distances itself from the main representatives of the New Academy: the Roman thinker does not practice epoche, nor does he assign any special role to it in his thought. Instead, Cicero introduces the concept of doubt to characterize his own way of thinking. Keywords: Cicero, epoche, doubt, skepticism, probabilism. https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 [1] 2 Rev. Archai, n. 27, Brasília, 2019, e02705. Cicero’s philosophical contributions have often been downplayed, even by himself. His importance as a translator and divulger of philosophy among the Romans frequently overshadows his originality as a philosopher.
    [Show full text]