Aspasius on Nicomachean Ethics : an Ancient Example of ‘Higher Criticism’?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aspasius on Nicomachean Ethics : an Ancient Example of ‘Higher Criticism’? Created on 19 May 2007 at 10.02 hours page 347 ASPASIUS ON NICOMACHEAN ETHICS : AN ANCIENT EXAMPLE OF ‘HIGHER CRITICISM’? CARLO NATALI 1. Received opinions NE 7. 14 Aristotle seems to identify pleasure and happiness: Presumably it is even necessary, given that there are unimpeded activities of each state, and happiness is the activity of all of them or of one of them, that this activity, provided that it is unimpeded, is most desirable; but this is pleasure. (1153B9–12) On this passage, Aspasius notes in his commentary (In NE 151. 18–27 Heylbut):1 δι µν ον το των δοκε τατν ποφανεσθαι τγαθν κα τν δονν· ο µν οτως χει, λλ πρς το#ς λ$γοντας γ$νεσιν ε%ναι & φα λας τινς τ'ν δον'ν, ο(ς2 κα δι) ατ τ µ ε%ναι ατν3 τ γαθν *πιγνεται [κα]4 *πιχειρε *νδ+ξως .ς *νν ατν τ /ριστον λ$γειν, *πε ν γε το ς Νικοµαχεοις, νθα διεληπται κα περ δον2ς 3ριστοτ$λης σαφ'ς ε4ρηκεν ατν µ τατν ε%ναι τ52 εδαιµον6α λλ παρακολουθε ν “8σπερ το ς κµαοις τν 8ραν”. σηµειωτ$ον5 δ το: µ ε%ναι το:τ) 3ριστοτ$λους λλ) Εδµου τ *ν τ<'6 λ$γειν περ δον2ς .ς οδ$πω περ ατ2ς διειλεγµ$νου· πλν ε4τε Εδµου τα:τ= *στιν ε4τε 3ριστοτ$λους, ã Carlo Natali 2007 My thanks to David Sedley and David Charles for help with the improvement of my English text. 1 References are to G. Heylbut, Aspasii in Ethica Nicomachea quae supersunt com- mentaria [Heylbut] (Berlin, 1889). 2 ο(ς Rose: >ς codd.; del. Spengel. 3 ατν Spengel: ατ codd. 4 Secl. Hayduck. 5 σηµειωτ$ον codd.: σηµε ον L. Spengel, ‘Uber• die unter den Namen des Aristoteles erhaltenen Ethischen Schriften’ [‘Ethische Schriften’], Bayer. Ak. der Wiss., Sitzung phil.-hist. Kl., 24/4 (1841), 1–115 at 85, and all subsequent editors. I maintain the text of the manuscripts, on the basis of a similar passage in Olympiodorus (In Cat. 75. 11–12 Busse). 6 MS Z (Parisinus gr. 1903) has a lacuna here, supplemented with δεκ=τ<ω by Spengel and others; see Spengel, ‘Ethische Schriften’, 86. Created on 19 May 2007 at 10.02 hours page 348 348 Carlo Natali *νδ+ξως ε4ρηται· δι το:το λ$γεται τ /ριστον δον, ?τι σ#ν τ<' ρστ<ω κα χ@ριστον ατο:.7 With these words, then, he seems to say that the good and pleasure are one and the same. But this is not the case. Rather, against those who say that pleasure is a process or that some pleasures are base, for whom it also follows, for this reason, that pleasure is not the good, he argues on the basis of reputed opinion that it is possible to call pleasure the supreme good. For at least in the Nicomachean Ethics, in the place where he does make distinctions on pleasure, he says clearly that pleasure is not the same thing as happiness, but accompanies it ‘as the bloom accompanies the cheek of youth’ [NE 1174B33]. As evidence that this is not by Aristotle but by Eudemus one should cite the fact that in <book 10> he [ =Aristotle] talks about pleasure as if he had not yet discussed it. But whether those words express Eudemus’ or Aristotle’s view, this is an argument drawn from reputed opinion; he says that pleasure is the supreme good for the following reason: it accompanies the supreme good and cannot be separated from it. The passage attracted discussion in the nineteenth century,because it seems to attribute a section of the Nicomachean Ethics (το:το, 151. 24) to Eudemus and not to Aristotle. Spengel maintained that As- pasius was still close enough to the rediscovery of Aristotle’s works to be able to discuss the attribution of books of the Nicomachean Ethics, and suggested that the passage presents its argument as ‘nur ein dialektischer Versuch’.8 But a bolder interpretation emerged in the twentieth century. According to Paul Moraux, Aspasius in this passage touches on a problem of interest to ‘higher criticism’, one concerned, that is, with the attribution of authorship—in this case, the question whether the so-called common books (NE 5–7 =EE 4– 6) should be attributed to the Nicomachean Ethics or the Eudemian Ethics. He maintains that the author of the passage argues on the basis of common opinions (*νδ+ξως, 21 and 26), but also cites the Nicomachean Ethics as a work di·erent from the one that contains 7 This section of Aspasius’ commentary (150. 31–151. 27) is very di¶cult and full of lacunae. It has been edited many times: by H. Hase, ‘Aspasiou scholi»on eis ta Ethica tou Aristotelous epitom»e’, Classical Journal, 28 (1823), 306–17, and 29 (1824), 104–18 at 117; Spengel, ‘Ethische Schriften’, 84–5; V. Rose, ‘Uber• die griechischen Commentare• zur Ethik des Aristoteles’, Hermes, 5 (1871), 61–113 at 107; and Heylbut. There is a modern translation only for the commentary on book 8, in D. Konstan, Commentators on Aristotle on Friendship [Commentators] (London, 2001) (Aspasius at 13–57). A complete translation of Aspasius’ commentary by Professor Konstan is in preparation. I would like to thank him very warmly for allowing me to read it in draft, and for many useful comments on a first version of the present article. 8 L. Spengel, ‘Ethische Schriften’, 84; ‘nich mehralseine Conjectur’, he adds(85). Created on 19 May 2007 at 10.02 hours page 349 Aspasius on Nicomachean Ethics 7 349 the present passage. Moraux takes lines 24–5 to mean that Aspasius is uncertain whether the common books belong to the Eudemian or Nicomachean Ethics.9 He adds that it is not certain whether Aspa- sius considered all the common books to belong to the Eudemian Ethics, or only the final chapters of book 7, 12–15. Further, Moraux quotes a comment by Aspasius on NE 8, 1155B 13–16, which states: ‘Even things di·erent in species admit of de- gree. We have discussed this matter [Aπρ ατ'ν] previously.’10 As- pasius’ comments: οικε δ εBρ2σθαι *ν το ς *κπεπτωκ+σι τ'ν Νικοµαχεων. (In NE 161. 9–10) It appears that they were discussed in the books that have fallen out of the Nicomachean Ethics. Moraux thinks that Aspasius is here referring to the lacuna that must be admitted to exist between NE 4 and 8, if the common books are attributed to the Eudemian Ethics. Moraux’s interpretation has been revived by Anthony Kenny, in an important book about the relationship between the Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics.11 Kenny claims, inter alia,that(i)the common books belong to the Eudemian Ethics, and (ii) before the second century ad,theEudemian Ethics was preferred to the Nico- machean Ethics by ancient authors. According to Kenny, the situ- 9 P. Moraux, Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen, ii. Der Aristotelismus im I. und II. Jh. n. Chr. [Aristotelismus] (Berlin and New York, 1984), 258–61. 10 Modern editions of the Nicomachean Ethics have Aπρ ατ'ν.ThisuseofAπ$ρ is quite rare in Aristotle, and for this reason Ramsauer, Grant, Stewart, Tricot, and Gauthier think that it is a spurious interpolation. But Aspasius’ text here has περ ατ'ν. Regarding the point referred to, among those scholars who accept the passage as authentic Susemihl and Dirlmeier follow Aspasius, Irwin thinks that the allusion is to Cat. 6B10–17 or to NE 2. 8, Burnet and Broadie just say that the reference is uncertain. E. Berti, ‘Amicizia e “Focal Meaning”’, in A. Alberti and R. W. Sharples (eds.), Aspasius: The Earliest Extant Commentary on Aristotle’s Ethics [Aspasius] (Berlin and New York, 1999), 176–90 at 178, thinks that the reference is to 1096B8–16. 11 A. Kenny, The Aristotelian Ethics [Ethics] (Oxford, 1978), 29–36. Shorter or more prudent versions of the same interpretation can be found in C. Rowe, The Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics (Cambridge, 1971); R. Bodeus,• ‘Contribution a› l’histoire des ¥uvres morales d’Aristote: les testimonia’, Revue philosophique de Louvain, 71 (1973), 451–67 at 452–3; H. B. Gottschalk, ‘Aristotelian Philosophy in the Roman World from the Time of Cicero to the End of the Second Cen- tury ad’ [‘Aristotelian Philosophy’], in W. Haase and F. Temporini (eds.), Aufstieg und Niedergang der r•omischen Welt, 2.36.2 [Aufstieg] (Berlin and New York, 1987), 1079–174 at 1158; F. Becchi, ‘Aspasio commentatore di Aristotele’ [‘Aspasio’], in Haase and Temporini (eds.), Aufstieg, 5365–96 at 5368; J. Barnes, ‘An Introduction to Aspasius’, in Alberti and Sharples (eds.), Aspasius, 1–50 at 19–21. Created on 19 May 2007 at 10.02 hours page 350 350 Carlo Natali ation had radically changed by the time of Alexander of Aphro- disias, and since then the supremacy of the Nicomachean to the Eudemian Ethics has been taken for granted. In general, Kenny thinks (iii) that the Eudemian Ethics is the more important treatise, from both a philosophical and a historical point of view. In this paper I shall discuss only Kenny’s interpretation of the passage quoted above from Aspasius’ commentary. Kenny mainly follows Moraux’s interpretation, with just a few changes, and in- serts it into his reconstruction of the history of the Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics in the period between the fourth century bc and the second century ad. He writes: In Aspasius’ writing we find the situation with which we have been fa- miliar for centuries: the Nicomachean Ethics is the undoubted treatise of Aristotle, the Eudemian Ethics is the problematic treatise whose attribu- tion fluctuates, regarded now as authentic Aristotle, now as the work of his disciple Eudemus.
Recommended publications
  • The Place of Ethics in Aristotle's Philosophy
    Offprint from OXFORDSTUDIES INANCIENT PHILOSOPHY EDITOR:BRADINWOOD VOLUMEXL Essays in Memory of Michael Frede JAMESALLEN EYJÓLFURKJALAREMILSSON WOLFGANG-RAINERMANN BENJAMINMORISON 3 THEPLACEOFETHICSIN ARISTOTLE’SPHILOSOPHY GEORGEKARAMANOLIS . The issue D the wealth of studies on Aristotle’s ethics, there has been almost nothing, as far as I know, dedicated to considering the place that ethics occupies in Aristotle’s philosophy. This issue does not seem to be interesting to modern students of Aristotle. There was, however, a debate and indeed a controversy about this issue in late antiquity, as I shall show in this paper. There are two questions in- volved here, which are interrelated, and the debate was about both of them. The first concerns the order in which ethics or practical philosophy, more generally, must be studied by the student of Aris- totle’s philosophy. The second concerns the relative significance of this part of philosophy within the framework of Aristotle’s philoso- phical work. Both questions arise from remarks that Aristotle himself makes. The second in particular, some might argue, is addressed by Aris- totle in various parts of his work. In Metaphysics Ε –, for instance, he famously discusses the relative value of theoretical, practical, and productive sciences. Aristotle there argues explicitly that the the- oretical sciences are preferable (hairetōterai) to all others, practical © George Karamanolis It is a pleasure to offer this contribution in honour of Michael Frede, who taught me so much. Drafts of this paper were presented at Princeton, Oxford, and the Department of Theory and Philosophy of Science, University of Athens. I have benefited from the comments of all these audiences.
    [Show full text]
  • Aspasian Infidelities. on Aspasius' Philosophical Background (EN I)
    apeiron 2016; 49(2): 229–259 António Pedro Mesquita* Aspasian Infidelities. On Aspasius’ Philosophical Background (EN I) DOI 10.1515/apeiron-2015-0028 Abstract: The discussion on Aspasius’ philosophical background has benefited in recent years from a wide consensus. According to this consensus, Aspasius should be regarded as a Peripatetic, or even as an “orthodox Peripatetic” (Barnes’ phrase). It is true that Aspasius’ commentary is generally in tune with Aristotle. It is true that he shows an extensive knowledge of Aristotelian research pertinent for the discussions and that he uses Aristotelian concepts, principles, and doctrines with ease as if they were his own, thus denoting an old assimila- tion of those materials and a long accommodation to them. In a word, it is true that Aspasius is an Aristotelian. He is, however, as I will try to show in this paper, an Aristotelian strongly influenced by Stoicism. I will do so by selecting those points from Aspasius’ commentary on book I of the Nicomachean Ethics where the Stoic influence is most flagrantly evident, namely in his interpretation of art (τέχνη), his conception of continence and incontinence and, especially, his interpretation of the relation between happiness, virtue, and external goods in Aristotle. Keywords: Aspasius, Aristotelianism, Stoicism, happiness, virtue, external goods The Consensus The discussion on Aspasius’ philosophical background has benefited in recent years from a wide consensus. A good example of this consensus is the position Barnes sustains on the matter in his excellent “Introduction to Aspasius”, where he states the following1: Next, Aspasius’ philosophical position. Galen calls him a Peripatetic, and it is plain that his pupil taught Galen Peripatetic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelianism in the First Century BC
    CHAPTER 5 Aristotelianism in the First Century BC Andrea Falcon 1 A New Generation of Peripatetic Philosophers The division of the Peripatetic tradition into a Hellenistic and a post- Hellenistic period is not a modern invention. It is already accepted in antiquity. Aspasius speaks of an old and a new generation of Peripatetic philosophers. Among the philosophers who belong to the new generation, he singles out Andronicus of Rhodes and Boethus of Sidon.1 Strabo adopts a similar division. He too distinguishes between the older Peripatetics, who came immediately after Theophrastus, and their successors.2 He collectively describes the latter as better able to do philosophy in the manner of Aristotle (φιλοσοφεῖν καὶ ἀριστοτελίζειν). It remains unclear what Strabo means by doing philosophy in the manner of Aristotle.3 But he certainly thinks that the philosophers who belong to the new generation, and not those who belong to the old one, deserve the title of true Aristotelians. For Strabo, the event separating the old from the new Peripatos is the rediscovery and publication of Aristotle’s writings. We may want to resist Strabo’s negative characterization of the earlier Peripatetics. For Strabo, they were not able to engage in philosophy in any seri- ous way but were content to declaim general theses.4 This may be an unfair judgment, ultimately based on the anachronistic assumption that any serious philosophy requires engagement with an authoritative text.5 Still, the empha- sis that Strabo places on the rediscovery of Aristotle’s writings suggests that the latter were at the center of the critical engagement with Aristotle in the 1 Aspasius, On Aristotle’s Ethics 44.20–45.16.
    [Show full text]
  • Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-48147-2 — Scale, Space and Canon in Ancient Literary Culture Reviel Netz Index More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-48147-2 — Scale, Space and Canon in Ancient Literary Culture Reviel Netz Index More Information Index Aaker, Jennifer, 110, 111 competition, 173 Abdera, 242, 310, 314, 315, 317 longevity, 179 Abel, N. H., 185 Oresteia, 197, 200, 201 Academos, 189, 323, 324, 325, 337 papyri, 15 Academy, 322, 325, 326, 329, 337, 343, 385, 391, Persians, 183 399, 404, 427, 434, 448, 476, 477–8, 512 portraits, 64 Achilles Tatius, 53, 116, 137, 551 Ptolemaic era, 39 papyri, 16, 23 Aeschylus (astronomer), 249 Acta Alexandrinorum, 87, 604 Aesop, 52, 68, 100, 116, 165 adespota, 55, 79, 81–5, 86, 88, 91, 99, 125, 192, 194, in education, 42 196, 206, 411, 413, 542, 574 papyri, 16, 23 Adkin, Neil, 782 Aethiopia, 354 Adrastus, 483 Aetia, 277 Adrastus (mathematician), 249 Africa, 266 Adrianople, 798 Agatharchides, 471 Aedesius (martyr), 734, 736 Agathocles (historian), 243 Aegae, 479, 520 Agathocles (peripatetic), 483 Aegean, 338–43 Agathon, 280 Aegina, 265 Agias (historian), 373 Aelianus (Platonist), 484 agrimensores, 675 Aelius Aristides, 133, 657, 709 Ai Khanoum, 411 papyri, 16 Akhmatova, Anna, 186 Aelius Herodian (grammarian), 713 Albertus Magnus, 407 Aelius Promotus, 583 Albinus, 484 Aenesidemus, 478–9, 519, 520 Alcaeus, 49, 59, 61–2, 70, 116, 150, 162, 214, 246, Aeolia, 479 see also Aeolian Aeolian, 246 papyri, 15, 23 Aeschines, 39, 59, 60, 64, 93, 94, 123, 161, 166, 174, portraits, 65, 67 184, 211, 213, 216, 230, 232, 331 Alcidamas, 549 commentaries, 75 papyri, 16 Ctesiphon, 21 Alcinous, 484 False Legation, 22 Alcmaeon, 310
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought
    THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT by MELISSA M. SHEW A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School ofthe University ofOregon in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy September 2008 11 University of Oregon Graduate School Confirmation of Approval and Acceptance of Dissertation prepared by: Melissa Shew Title: "The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought" This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree in the Department ofPhilosophy by: Peter Warnek, Chairperson, Philosophy John Lysaker, Member, Philosophy Ted Toadvine, Member, Philosophy James Crosswhite, Outside Member, English and Richard Linton, Vice President for Research and Graduate Studies/Dean ofthe Graduate School for the University of Oregon. September 6, 2008 Original approval signatures are on file with the Graduate School and the University of Oregon Libraries. 111 An Abstract of the Dissertation of Melissa M. Shew for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy to be taken September 2008 Title: THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT Approved: Dr. Peter Warnek This dissertation engages three facets of Greek philosophy: 1) the phenomenon of tyche (chance, fortune, happening, or luck) in Aristotle's Physics, Nicomachean Ethics, and Poetics; 2) how tyche infonns Socrates' own philosophical practice in the Platonic dialogues; and 3) how engaging tyche in these Greek texts challenges established interpretations of Greek thought in contemporary scholarship and discussion. I argue that the complex status of tyche in Aristotle's texts, when combined with its appearance in the Platonic dialogues and the framework of Greek myth and poetry (poiesis), underscores the seriousness with which the Greeks consider the role of chance in human life.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Phronãªsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, And
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 2013 Aristotelian Phronêsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice Stephen Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Citation Salkever, Stephen, "Aristotelian Phronêsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice" (2013). Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship. Paper 25. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/25 This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/25 For more information, please contact [email protected]. DRAFT—NOT FOR QUOTATION OR CITATION. Aristotelian Phronêsis , the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice Stephen Salkever Bryn Mawr College August, 2013 (A version of this paper was presented at a conference on Practical Wisdom and Globalizing Practice held in November 2012 at Sun Yat-sen University, Guangzhou, China. For questions and comments I thank my fellow conferees and especially the conference organizer, Prof. Xu Changfu of the SYSU Philosophy Department.) In this paper, I will outline some fundamental differences between the evaluative and explanatory language of Aristotelian practical reason based on his empirical psychological
    [Show full text]
  • 1 INSTRUMENTS and IMPEDIMENTS Α Senecan
    vendredi 25 mars 14h-16h Comments welcome: [email protected] 1 Maison de la Recherche D116 INSTRUMENTS AND IMPEDIMENTS Α Senecan-Aristotelian debate on the activation of the virtues My starting point is a notoriously ambiguous chapter in Aristotle. It’s well known that in Nicomachean Ethics 1.10, Aristotle rejects the view that virtuous activity is sufficient all by itself for happiness. Instead he asserts that while eudaimonia does consist in a life of virtuous activity, certain external goods, things like health, wealth, and freedom from pain, are also necessary in some sense. But in what sense? The text leaves room for interpretation: whether Aristotle means that such things are components of the best human life, such that happiness is incomplete without them, or whether they are instrumentally necessary for the best life – what we need to use to perform virtuous activities in the best way; and there are further questions about each of these possibilities. In this paper I am not seeking to provide an answer to what Aristotle meant. My interest is rather in the interpretive space defined by that ambiguity, and in what happened next in ancient philosophy within that interpretive space. I explore a series of texts in which the so- called Peripatetic philosophers, responding to Aristotle, give their accounts of the relation between happiness and external goods – and the Stoics, represented by Seneca, give their version, responding to the Peripatetics. The star player is what I call the activation argument. Some Peripatetics hold, picking up on certain things in Aristotle, that virtue is not sufficient for happiness because virtue can’t be activated—can’t give rise to any virtuous activities—without having some external goods.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Synopsis of the Aristotelian Commentary Tradition (In Less Than Sixty Minutes)
    HISTORICAL SYNOPSIS OF THE ARISTOTELIAN COMMENTARY TRADITION (IN LESS THAN SIXTY MINUTES) Fred D. Miller, Jr. CHAPTER 1 PERIPATETIC SCHOLARS Aristotle of Stagira (384–322 BCE) Exoteric works: Protrepticus, On Philosophy, Eudemus, etc. Esoteric works: Categories, Physics, De Caelo, Metaphysics, De Anima, etc. The legend of Aristotle’s misappropriated works Andronicus of Rhodes: first edition of Aristotle’s works (40 BCE) Early Peripatetic commentators Boethus of Sidon (c. 75—c. 10 BCE) comm. on Categories Alexander of Aegae (1st century CE)comm. on Categories and De Caelo Adrastus of Aphrodisias (early 1st century) comm. on Categories Aspasius (c. 131) comm. on Nicomachean Ethics Emperor Marcus Aurelius establishes four chairs of philosophy in Athens: Platonic, Peripatetic, Stoic, Epicurean (c. 170) Alexander of Aphrodisias (late 2nd —early 3rd century) Extant commentaries on Prior Analytics, De Sensu, etc. Lost comm. on Physics, De Caelo, etc. Exemplar for all subsequent commentators. Comm. on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Only books 1—5 of Alexander’s comm. are genuine; books 6—14 are by ps.-Alexander . whodunit? Themistius (c. 317—c. 388) Paraphrases of Physics, De Anima, etc. Paraphrase of Metaphysics Λ (Hebrew translation) Last of the Peripatetics CHAPTER 2 NEOPLATONIC SCHOLARS Origins of Neoplatonism Ammonius Saccas (c. 175—242) forefather of Neoplatonism Plotinus (c. 205—260) the Enneads Reality explained in terms of hypostases: THE ONE—> THE INTELLECT—>WORLD SOUL—>PERCEPTIBLE WORLD Porphyry of Tyre (232–309) Life of Plotinus On the School of Plato and Aristotle Being One On the Difference Between Plato and Aristotle Isagoge (Introduction to Aristotle’s Categories) What is Neoplatonism? A broad intellectual movement based on the philosophy of Plotinus that sought to incorporate and reconcile the doctrines of Plato, Pythagoras, and Aristotle with each other and with the universal beliefs and practices of popular religion (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Challenges to Contemporary Philosophy—Nature, Knowledge, and the Good
    Introduction: Aristotelian Challenges to Contemporary Philosophy—Nature, Knowledge, and the Good The collection of articles presented in this book explores Aristotelianism and its critics from three distinct viewpoints in three historical periods: first, from the point of view of the philosophy of science and epistemology in Antiquity, secondly, from the perspective of the notion of individual rights in medieval philosophy; and, finally, against the background of 20th-century ethical discus- sions that offer alternatives to what can be taken as standard modern ethical theories (such as those developed by Sidgwick, for example). The main moti- vation of the selection is the general observation that, with respect to these specific themes, the influence and critical impact of Aristotelianism have not yet been sufficiently studied. When it comes to assessing central questions of the philosophy of science and epistemology and their relation to Aristotelianism, we argue that there is a danger of making simplified generalisations and attacking Aristotle as a straw man representing tendencies that derive from inaccurate or modernis- ing interpretations. The contributions in Part i focus on clearing up some such modernising misunderstandings pertaining to Aristotle’s theory of science. Secondly, with respect to the history and development of modern ethics with its notion of individual rights, Part ii of the collection addresses the question whether, in the late Middle Ages, there was a radical change in the analysis of rights. The contributors offer contrasting views on this, arguing first that ancient authors lacked neither terms nor concepts for individual rights. Others oppose this suggestion by claiming that the profundity of late medi- eval conceptual change entails that any resembling notions that one might find in antiquity can only be superficially similar to the modern ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Ethical Theory & Modern Health Care
    Bull.lnd. Inst. Hist, Med. Vol. XXVI pp. 75 to 80 ARISTOTLE'S ETHICAL THEORY & MODERN HEALTH CARE SISIR K. MAJUMDAR* ABSTRACT The Greek physician of antiquity - Hippocrates (460 - 356 B.C.) is called the Father of Modern Medicine and the Hippocratic Oath to which doctors of modern medicine traditionally and formally express their allegiance. forms the basic founda- tion of medical ethics. The tradition of Western ethical philosophy began with the ancient Greeks. Form Socrates (469-399 B.C.) and his immediate successors, Plato (427-347 B.C ) and Aristotle (384-322 B.C.), there is a clear line of continuity, through Hellenistic period (from the death of Alexander the Great (323 B.C.) to the end of Ptolemic dynasty (30 B.C.) and the Roman annexation of Egypt - broadly post- Aristotelian) and medieval thought to the present day. But the society has qualita- tively and quantitatively changed since the Industrial Revolution in the late 18th and 19th centuries. Society, today, is just a collection of discrete individuals, each with his or her own purposes and interests. Hence it has become almost imperative to apply the principle of autonomy to issues in the ethics of health care. The aim of this short essay is, therefore, an attempt to explore the relevance, if any, of Aristotelian ethical theory to the modern health care. Aristotle's ethical theory, in the main, 1978). This socio-political scenario in represents the prevailing opinions of edu- Greece of the day reflects the limitations cated and experienced men of his day in of Aristotle's ethics and its relevance to Athens and other city-states of Greece.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Root of Moderation Discourse in Iran's Eleventh Presidential Election
    ISSN 2039-2117 (online) Mediterranean Journal of Vol 9 No 1 ISSN 2039-9340 (print) Social Sciences January 2018 Research Article © 2018 Jafari et.al.. This is an open access article licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Philosophical Root of Moderation Discourse in Iran’s Eleventh Presidential Election Leila Jafari PHD Student, Faculty of Administrative Sciences and Economics, Department of Political Science, University of Isfahan Ali Alihosseini Associate Professor, Faculty of Administrative Sciences and Economics, Department of Political Science, University of Isfahan Corresponding Author Seyyedjavad Emamjomehzadeh Associate Professor, Faculty of Administrative Sciences and Economics, Department of Political Science, University of Isfahan Doi: 10.2478/mjss-2018-0014 Abstract Moderation was a triumphant discourse of Iran's eleventh presidential election. It’s a new attitude in the political realm and most of the movements relate themselves to it and each one interprete their actions according to moderation. For clarifying this ambiguous trend, we should refer to its philosophical root. It seems that Aristotle is the first one who represented this theory. In fact, moderation is one of the main principles of Aristotelian ethics. Understanding this concept requires understanding the basic concepts of the intellectual and moral theory of Aristotle. Moderation is the center of his theory of virtue. According to this principle, all the moral virtues are intermediates and excess, and defects in the actions and emotions cause moral vices. This theory could be the best way to pass excess and deficiencies in Iran's political sphere. Keywords: Aristotle's ethics, moderation, virtue, excess, deficiency 1.
    [Show full text]